Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


The 'Two Truths' doctrine (Satyadvaya) and the nature of Upaya in Nagarjuna

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search


Dilip Loundo

Ph.D. in Indian Philosophy from the University of Mumbai (India). Coordinator, Centre for the Study of Indian Religions and Philosophies, Post-Graduate Programme of Religious Studies, Universidade Federal de Juiz de Fora (UFJF).


ABSTRACT

The objective of this article is to contribute to the understanding of Nāgārjuna's 'two truths' doctrine (satyadvaya) as presented in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā ("The Fundamental Verses of the Middle Path") (XXIV.8-10). For that purpose, we argue that 'two truths' doctrine the basic structural framework for the operational functionality of upāya of upāya (lit., 'skilful means'), perhaps the most important epistemological/pedagogical notion of Mahāyāna Buddhism.

Keywords Nāgārjuna; Mahāyāna Buddhism; upāya; satyadvaya


RESUMO

O objetivo deste artigo é contribuir para a compreensão da doutrina das "duas verdades" (satyadvaya), tal como presente no Mūlamadhyamakakārikā ("Os versos fundamentais do caminho do meio") (XXIV.8-10) de Nāgārjuna. Argumentamos, para tanto, que a doutrina das "duas verdades" constitui o fundamento estrutural básico para a funcionalidade operacional do upāya (lit., "meios hábeis"), que é, talvez, a noção epistemológico-pedagógica mais importante do budismo Mahāyāna.

Palavras-chave Nāgārjuna; Budismo Mahāyāna; upāya; satyadvaya


I Introduction

The objective of this article is to contribute to the understanding of Nāgārjuna's 'two truths' doctrine (satyadvaya) as presented in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā3 ("The Fundamental Verses of the Middle Path") (XXIV.8-10, pp. 331-3) by arguing that it constitutes the basic structural framework for the operational functionality of an upāya (lit., 'skilful means'), perhaps the most important epistemological/pedagogical notion of Mahāyāna Buddhism.


My interpretation of the relevant passages of the MMK takes the support of canonic sūtras - both the pāli as well as the Mahāyāna sūtras - and post-Nāgārjunian commentarial tradition with emphasis on Candrakīrti and Tsongkhapa. As a methodological principle, I'll adopt an insider's perspective, more apologetic rather than juridical, trying to reconstruct Nāgārjuna's internal logic as a meaningful and coherent articulation between the 'two-truths' doctrine (satyadvaya) and his overall philosophy of emptiness (sūnyatā).


II The critical context


As Walser has convincingly shown (2008, pp. 224-63), Nāgārjuna's contextual intervention is directly related to the major developments that followed the Buddha's death (mahāparanirvāna) and the major split that took place within the saṅgha between the Mahāsāṃgika school and the Sthaviravāda school.


Though the primary divergences seems to be related to matters of vinaya - i.e., the rules of monastic discipline -, subsequent developments show the proliferation of various subschools upholding specific hermeneutical readings of the Buddha's words (sūtras or buddhavacana) and consigning them into specific abhidharmas - the in-depth and systematic reflections on the sūtras. One of those hermeneutical developments, closely associated with the Mahāsāṃgika school, is the Prajñāptivāda subschool who seems to have been one the first systematisers of the two-truths doctrine within the Buddhist tradition, being a sort of embryonic cell of what was latter called Mahāyāna and the proper partisan context of influence inherited by Nāgārjuna (Walser, 2008, p. 234).


The Prajñāptivāda subschool sustained that all composite phenomena as well as all elementary dharmas - i.e., the elementary conceptual constituents of experience systematized by the ābhidharmika tradition in the line of the Buddha's teachings on aggregates (skandhas), links (nidānas), etc. - were mere conceptual constructions (prajñāpti) having no substantiality on their own (Ramanan, 1998, pp. 62-3).


The world as one's mundane experiences meant to satisfy egocentric designs and anchored on seemingly independent subjects and objects, is said to constitute saṃvṛti-sat(ya) or prajñāpti-sat(ya), i.e., conventional truth; whereas the (meta-linguistic) realization of their fundamental interdependent nature as (mere) conceptual and conventional constructions, otherwise known as nirvāṇa, would constitute paramārtha-sat(ya) or dravya-sat(ya), i.e., the ultimate truth.


The oppositional context of Nāgārjuna's intervention, on the other hand, is represented by the Sarvāstivāda subschool, an offshoot and dissidence of the Sthaviravāda school (pāli, Theravāda) (Baruah, 2000, p. 44).

Building on the alleged transforming capabilities of analytical procedures that allegedly established the elementary dharmas as ultimate non-analysable factors of experience, the Sarvāstivāda school goes on to entrust these latter with an unexpected ontological dimension. In sharp contrast with the lower level of reality represented by one's phenomenal world of physical and mental composite constructs, these pre-empirical elementary conceptual dharmas are declared to pertain to the highest level of ontological existence as substantive, real and permanent entities, endowed with intrinsic nature (svabhāva).


From here emerged the Sarvāstivāda's revised version of the two-truths doctrine: the elementary dharmas are declared to constitute paramārtha-sat and one's phenomenal experiences are declared to constitute prajñāpti-sat. In other words, paramārtha-sat or dravya-sat was to be understood as a discursive positive postulation of ever-lasting conceptual realities having intrinsic nature (svabhāva), i.e, existing in all three times and, as such, immune to any sort of determination by extrinsic factors and causes (apratyayahetu) (Walser, 2008, pp. 208-12).


It's interesting to note that the Sarvāstivāda position seems to be an extreme development within a framework of possibilities open up to the ābhidharmica traditions. In fact, the highly sophisticated systematization of instrumental concepts - the elementary dharmas (skandhas, nidānas, āyatanas, etc.), originally aiming at deconstructing the composite and interdependent nature of all phenomena - posed an eminent risk of having them (i.e., the instrumental concepts) either being mistaken for or actually understood as ontological conceptual reifications.


In fact, though for the majority of the ābhidarmika traditions, most of the dharmas have a momentary and conditional character (saṁskṛta dharmas), being therefore (mutually) dependent on causes and conditions (pratyayahetu), some of them - an unfoldment of the basic notion of nirvāṇa - were classified as being 'unconditional' (asaṁskṛta dharmas).

An 'unconditional dharma', even if conceived to accommodate the unique state of nirvāṇa and understood as a matter of realisation rather than conceptualization - as it was the case among the Mahāsāṃgikas (and, therefore, among the Prajñāptivāda school) (Walser, 2008, pp. 214-8) - may easily be suggestive of a transcendent and eternal realm, i.e, an eternal dharma beyond pratītyasamutpāda.

Sarvāstivāda's intervention seems, therefore, to constitute a radical exploration into the eternality of a saṁskṛta dharmas, by positing that the constitutive and recurrent character of the elementary dharmas in general - both saṁskṛta and asaṁskṛta - would justify their being invested with an ontological dimension. In short, if the idea of eternal unconditional dharmas is in itself quite problematic, the idea of eternal conditioned dharmas seems to border contradiction. Accordingly, the Sarvāstivāda school strives hard to reconcile the idea of momentary appearance (kṣanikatā) of saṁskṛta dharmas with the idea of their eternal existence (svabhāva) (King, 1995, p. 100).


Not surprisingly, the Sarvāstivāda school drew considerable opposition among Buddhist circles, being accused of being directly influenced by Vedic realist schools of Sāṃkhya and Vaiśeṣika and, as a consequence, they were expelled from the Buddhist community (King 1995, p. 91).

The Sarvāstivāda school's support of ultimate substantial realities - the elementary dharmas - as ontological constituents of an otherwise interdependent world marked by dependent co-origination (pratītiyasamuptpāda) seem to constitute a clear violation of the Buddha's words in three basic senses: (i) it brought the idea of an ultimate truth under the preview of propositional sentences, something proscribed the Buddha, notably in the pāli Kaccānagottasutta (Sansk., Kātyāyanagotrasūtra) where he sentenced: "Kaccāna, one extreme is: 'Everything exist'.


Another extreme is: 'Nothing exists'. While avoiding both the extremes, the Tathāgata (i.e., the Buddha) teaches that the dharma is the middle way."4; (ii) it suggested that a certain level of objective reality was, so to say, immune to pratītyasamutpāda and to the principle of impermanence (anitya); (iii) and, finally, while severing one's reality between conventional and non-conventional levels, the teleology of nirvāṇa as a means to overcome suffering would end up in a sort of meditative state focused on the latter - i.e., the non-conventional primary elements (dharmas) -, i.e., a transcendent state beyond pratītyasamutpāda and one's phenomenic experiences.


To Nāgārjuna, the Sarvāstivāda's stand represented an extreme development of an otherwise problematic ābhidharmika tradition which brought together two incompatible ideas: on the one side, the idea of asaṁskṛta and its Sarvāstivāda's corollary as nityasaṁskṛta (eternally conditioned) and, on the other, the idea of dharma (Sharma, 1996, p. 66 & King, 1995, p. 113)

Those tendencies would amount to an actual dualism, i.e., to an ontological rupture between saṁsāra and nirvāṇa and, as a consequence, to a rejection of the Buddha's Middle Way (madhyamāpratipada), its epistemological dimension - i.e., the need to refrain from metaphysical declarations ('is' and 'is not') - as well as its praxiological dimension - i.e., the need to neither be egoistically in the world nor abandon it. Finally, they circumvented the fundamental idea of the whole pervasiveness of pratītyasamutpāda as the Buddha's essential teaching.

In Mahāhatthipadopamasutta (Sanskrit, Mahāhastīpadopamāsūtra; or The Great Sermon on the Simile of the Elephant's Footprint), the Buddha says: "Whoever sees paṭiccasamuppāda (sanskrit, pratītyasamutapāda) sees the dhamma (sânscrit, dharma), whoever sees the dhamma sees paṭiccasamuppāda."5 In other words, nirvana is the realization of pratītyasamutpāda rather its evasion.


Nāgārjuna's critical intervention presents a higher degree of radicality. Aiming at purging the ābhidharmika tradition from the dangers of reifying the Buddha's analytical discourse by claiming ontological substantiality and permanence to elementary soteriological concepts, Nāgārjuna brings into the picture the fundamental idea of 'emptiness' (śūnyatā) as a means to clarify what pratītyasamutpāda ultimately stands for. It's a fact that the idea of emptiness never reaches a technical sense in the pāli canon and in the ābhidharmika tradition - being therefore intimately associated with what we call Mahāyāna.


Still the spirit of the adjectival sense of the word śūnya and its derivative śunyatā as the 'condition of being void of essence' (nairātmya) is presented in many of the pāli discourses, as it's the outstanding case of the Suññalokasutta (sanskrit, Śūnyalokasūtra or The Sermon on the Empty Universe) where the Buddha proclaims: "Ānanda, empty (suñña) is the world. It is empty because it is empty of essence and of everything that belongs to it".6


Therefore, the contextual emergence of śūnyatā in the Buddhist tradition and the paramount role of Nāgārjuna's MMK target a very specific goal. The main objective is to hold śūnyatā as a razor sword meant to eliminate any attempt of Sarvāstivāda type to entrust any kind of substantiality to the major ābhidharmika elementary concepts (dharmas) - even if they are assumed as mere analytical concepts of a pre-empirical/experiential nature. One by one, in a sharp and systematic way, Nāgārjuna unveils the interdependent nature of each and every Sarvāstivāda's elementary dharma.

He shows that, inasmuch as any other empirical phenomena, the elementary concepts are equally amenable to further analysis and dependent on further causes and conditions (hetupratyaya). For example, in MMK IV, titled "Skandhaparīkṣā" ("Examinaton of Aggregates"), Nāgārjuna analyses, systematically, the interdependent nature of the five basic dharmas or aggregates (skandha).

The constitutive or construed character of all concepts as 'concepts of reciprocity' (anyonyaprajñāpti)7 imply an ultimate dialectical interdependence between every subject and object, agent and patient, preventing the possibility of any substantialized entity (svabhāva).


Nāgārjuna's radical support to the interdependent and conventional nature of all phenomena and all ābhidharmika dharmas constitutes a reinstatement of the eminent character of reality as prajñāpti-sat and the consequent rejection of Sarvāstivāda's dravya-sat. This opens the way for the consolidation and further clarification of the actual content of Mahāsāṃgika's (and Prajñāptivāda's) original two-truths doctrine as the epistemological counterpart of the newly explicative term of 'emptiness' (śūnyatā) as a pedagogical and prophylactic concept.

Rather than a dichotomy of reality - impermanent/permanent - the pair saṃvṛti-sat(ya)/ paramārtha-sat(ya) acquires, in Nāgārjuna's critical context, the character of a dichotomy of meaning that co-exists in the same phenomenal reality. In his Mūlamadhyamakāvatarbhāṣya, Candrakīrti is unequivocal: "It has been shown that each phenomenon (bhāva) has its own two natures (rūpa): a conventional (saṃvṛti) and an ultimate nature (paramārtha)". (cited in Tsongkhapa 2006, p. 483)8 Saṃvṛti-sat(ya) points to the level of meaning that hides - or at least does not reveal - the empty nature of reality, i.e., their interdependent originated character.

It is marked by a subjective disposition to attribute the status of ultimate reality to (mere) conventionality or, in other words, to perpetrate 'metaphysical phantasies', i.e., to erroneously project substantiality into insubstantiality, essentiality into non-essentiality (or conventionality), and permanence into non-permanence. It has practical efficiency as it enables the realization of egocentric designs but, in the long term, on account of its being grounded on ignorance, it is the cause of endless suffering.

Paramārtha-sat(ya), on the other hand, points to the level of meaning that realizes (mere) conventionality as such - i.e., the all-pervasive character of pratītyasamutpāda or emptiness of all phenomena - being, therefore, of the nature of a metalinguistic realization. Accordingly, Candrakīrti concludes: "Whatever is ultimate (paramārtha) for ordinary beings is merely conventional (saṃvṛti) for the āryas who are engaged with appearances. The essence of conventional phenomena, which is emptiness (śūnyatā), is the ultimate for them" (cited in Tsongkhapa, 2006, p. 484).


The Mahāyāna's renewed understanding of the 'two truths' doctrine in accordance with their cluster of specific sūtras and the words of Nāgārjuna brings the fundamental teleology of nirvāṇa under specific jurisdiction of bodhi, i.e., the 'realization' of the profound implications of ordinary reality rather than an experience of any extraordinary reality. In other words, if saṃvṛti-satya is to be understood as the level of meaning that hides conventionality as such, paramārtha-satya or bodhi is the level of meaning that reveals it. "Paramārtha-satya says Dan Lusthaus, is the clear seeing of the actuality of saṃvṛti, i.e., saṃvṛti made transparent" (Lusthaus, 2002, p. 231).

Accordingly, "this means that there are not actually two truths but merely a single truth in its presentation" (Matsunaga, 1974, p. 61), this being perhaps the precise meaning of the expression satyadvaya (lit., "two levels of truth"), widely used by Candrakīrti in his commentary on the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā titled Prasannapadā, understood as the ultimate explanation of Nāgārjuna's "dve satye" (lit., "two truths").9 As a metalinguistic dimension underscoring every propositional and conceptual expression, paramārtha-satya is the silence behind each and every word.


Therefore, the postulation of emptiness (śūnyatā) as a soteriological clarifying technique makes only sense because there a recurrent existential error which tends to superimpose (samāropa) the substantial (ātman/svabhāva) onto the insubstantial (śūnya), this (i.e., the superimposition) being the proper meaning of samvrtti.


Therefore, in Nāgārjuna's understanding, the Buddha's words do not contemplate any instance of denial of the world. As Dungen puts it, echoing the teachings of Tsongkhapa, "the object of negation (Buddha's teachings) is not the world of conventionality as such, but the erroneous substantialization of the phenomena or, what is the same, the lack of (realization of the) interdependent origination of (all) phenomena and the belief in their independent and autonomous existence, endowed with self-nature (svabhāva)" (2012).


Accordingly, the Buddha's teachings are meant to prompt one to sublate one's samvṛti perspectives (prapañcopaśamam) (MMK I, p. 101) - both the mundane 'metaphysics' that shapes one's routine attachment to the objects of the world and also the sophisticated metaphysics of doctrinal philosophers - because there lies the ultimate root-cause of suffering (duḥkha).


III The two truths doctrine and the Buddha's teachings


Though Nāgārjuna's general contextual intervention in the MMK could be described as an attempt to rehabilitate a rather epistemological perspective to the two-truths doctrine, the specific sub-context in which the explicit mention to it occurs, suggests an important additional element that may, perhaps, have been decisive for the consolidation of what came to be known as the Mahāyāna or Śūnyavāda current of Buddhism. In fact, Nāgārjuna's appeal to the two-truths doctrine appears in a dramatic moment of the MMK.


After having forcefully sustained the emptiness of all phenomena and more specifically of all elementary dharmas, Nāgārjuna is asked by the opponent, late in the Chapter XXIV (out of 27) titled "Āryasatyaparikṣā" ("Examination of the [Four] Noble Truths), if the all-pervasiness of emptiness (śūnyatā) as a descriptive understanding of dependent co-origination (pratītyasamutpāda) would not completely obliterate the Buddha's teachings and, more specifically, the (Four) Noble Truths (āryasatya), for the simple fact of their being made of words and concepts, i.e., of 'mere' conventionalities. In other words, the Buddha's dharma, the truth of truths would itself risk belonging to samrvtti-sat instead of paramārtha-sat. In that case, how could there be any possibility at all of nirvāṇa/bodhi?


Nāgārjuna's answer touches the core of what emptiness (śūnyatā) and the Mahāyāna actually mean. He accuses the opponent of not understanding the intended meaning of śūnyatā. In fact, says Nāgārjuna, the opponent understands śūnyatā in the same spirit of any other propositional statement taking it as declaration of non-existence. Glossing Nāgārjuna, Candrakīrti states: "Thus, emptiness destroys the one who takes it to mean the non-existence of things (abhāva)... Your allegation derives from wrongly foisting the meaning of non-existence (abhāva) onto the idea of the absence of being (śūnya).


But we do not declare the meaning of non-existence (abhāva) and of absence of being (śūnya) to be the same; rather absence of being (śūnya) has the same meaning as dependent arising (pratītyasamutpāda)".10 In other words, the opponent thinks that, different from his own postulation of permanent elementary dharmas that would ensure the relative reality of composite phenomena, Nāgārjuna's postulation of the non-substantiality of all dharmas and phenomena would imply that phenomenal reality was just an illusionary world, of which the Buddha's teachings were also irremediably a part.


To refute those allegations, Nāgārjuna is forced to be more precise about the actual status of the Buddha's teachings. First, he reminds the opponent that, throughout the dialogue, he sustained that reality and its recurrent processes of appearance and disappearance of phenomena could only be admissible if things were devoid of self-nature (svabhāva). In other words, emptiness was a pre-requisite for the reality of the world and not otherwise. The opponent's postulation of self-existing entities, instead, would obstruct the possibility of a world-given experience.


Second, and that's the core of his rebuttal, Nāgārjuna states that having declared the emptiness of all dharmas, there is no possibility of understanding emptiness - and consequently all the Buddha's teachings - as ultimate ontological doctrines about reality. This amounts to the emptying of emptiness by which Nāgārjuna seeks to free its conceptual dimensions from any ontological claim.

In other words, Nāgārjuna's position is clear: śūnyatā, as much as the Buddha's fundamental teachings, such as the pratītyasamutpāda, are not ontological statements about reality, they are not (ontological) doctrines (dṛṣṭis). Instead, they function as a major instrument to eliminate all the dṛṣṭis (sarvadṛṣṭiprahāṇa). In three major passages of the MMK, Nāgārjuna shows an uncompromising posture on that:




    The Victorious Ones have announced that emptiness is the relinquishing of all views (sarvadṛṣṭiprahāṇa). Those who are possessed of the view of emptiness are said to be incorrigible.11

    'Empty', 'non-empty', 'both', or 'neither' - these should not be declared. It is expressed only for the purpose of communication (or teaching) (prajñāpty arthaṃ).12

    We affirm that the interdependent origination (pratītyasamutpādaḥ) is (what we call) emptiness. Now this (viz., Emptiness) is (also) dependent on convention (prajñāptir upādāya). This is the Middle Way (madhyamā).13


We have now reached a climax in Nāgārjuna's argumentation. How to classify the extraordinary character of the Buddha's words and teachings which are not a dṛṣṭi (ontological doctrine), and how do they actually operate so effectively to lead men to nirvāṇa/bodhi?


The answer to first part of the question is the word upāya, usually translated as "skilful means", or "skilful strategy/pedagogy", as a timely and appropriate form of teaching suiting the specificities of each one's suffering and ignorance. In this case, however, the Buddha's proficiency in skilful or pedagogical means (upāya kauśalya) is not to be understood as an introductory discourse for the sake of later definitive one.

There is no definite discourse about reality. Therefore all the Buddha's teachings, may be simpler or indirect (neyārtha) or more sophisticated and direct (nītārtha), are to be considered upāyas. In other words, notwithstanding the dissimilarity with regard to the ultimate nature of reality, upāyas are unavoidable tools to realize it.

In the Pāli canon, as Richard Gombrich rightly points out, "The exercise of skill to which it (the word upāya) refers, the ability to adapt one's message to the audience, is of enormous importance" (2006, p. 17). Accordingly, the expression upāya kauśalya appears already in some the Pāli sūtras with the peculiar sense of a pedagogical proficiency. For example, in the Kimbilattheragāthā14 and in the Dhamma (nāvā) Sutta15 the expressions upāyakusalena and upāyaññū kusalo are used, respectively, to describe the Buddha's attribute of skilfulness in means.


But it's only in the Mahāyāna sūtras, mainly in the Saddharmapuṇḍarīka-Sūtra, the Vimalakīrtinirdeśa Sūtra, the Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra and, above all, in the various Prajñapāramitā Sūtras - among which the Upāyakauśalya Sūtra stands high - that the expression upāya kauśalya emerges as a technical term to designate a pāramitā, i.e., a perfection or virtue of a bodhisattva, particularly associated with the bodhisattva Avalokiteśvara.16 As regards Nāgārjuna, the exercise of skilful means is extensively seen throughout his works,17 though the word upāya, in a technical sense, is not explicitly mentioned in the MMK.

In other works, we can find explicit explanations of its meaning and implications, and a close association with the notion of yukti - an argumentative device - whereby upāya assumes the unequivocal sense of a rational means. In Bodhisambhāra(ka) Śāstra (The Treatise on the Provisions Essential to Enlightenment), Nāgārjuna echoes the growing importance, in Mahāyāna tradition, of upāya kauśalya as a major pāramitā of a bodhisattva. He eloquently states:


    Prajñāpāramitā is the mother of Bodhisattvas, skill in means (upāya) is their father, and compassion (karuṇā) is their daughter... Attracting with gifts, teaching the Dharma, listening to the teaching of the Dharma, and also practicing acts of benefit to others - these are skillful means (upāya) for attracting [others]. (Nāgārjuna, 2015, Verses 6 & 17)

The answer to the second part of the question above - the structure and operationality of an upāya - bring us back to the MMK. It's my contention that in Chapter XXIV, from verses 8 to 10, Nāgārjuna describes precisely the operationality of an upāya by resorting to the two-truths doctrine. Let us start with verse 8 that reads as follows:

    The teachings of the dharma by the Buddha are based upon two truths: the conventional truth (loka-saṃvṛtisatya) and the truth based on the ultimate reality (or, 'the ultimate truth') (satyam ca paramārthataḥ).18

If we recollect the exact context of the statement above - viz., a reaction of Nāgārjuna to the opponent's perplexity over what he considers to be a contradiction between śūnyatā and the Four Noble Truths (āryasatyāni catvāri) - we are bound to agree that Nāgārjuna's motivation is basically to explain the nature, the status and the operationality of the Buddha's words.

If he is not able to do so, all his highly sophisticated rhetoric will fall apart. In other words, the contextual goal of MMK XXIV.8 is not to present the two-truths doctrine as such but, instead, to make the case for a soteriological efficacy of the Buddha's pedagogical discourse by resorting to the two truths doctrine. Let us consider this closely.


Nāgārjuna's critical reinterpretation of the two truths doctrine, in line with the Prajñāptivāda School, is implicitly presented throughout the text of the MMK, right from the beginning till the very end. It constitutes, in fact, a major leitmotiv of the whole exercise of systematically rejecting the Sarvāstivāda's postulation of the elementary dharmas as constitutive of paramārtha-satya.


Besides, we should also note that the two-truths doctrine is not an invention of the Buddha, the Abhidharma tradition - be it the Mahāsāṃgika or the Sarvāstivāda schools19 - or the Mahāyāna tradition. It constitutes, instead, a pan-Indian doctrine that points to a plurality of ontological/epistemological levels wherein the conventional truth (saṃvṛti-satya) is useful for one to achieve temporary worldly goals but, in the long run, an obstacle for one to realize the ultimate truth (paramārtha-satya) which frees one, in a definitive way, from all suffering. One could perhaps trace it back to the Upaniṣads and more specifically to the oldest of them such as the Bṛhadāraṇyaka, the Chāndogya, the Kaṭha and the Muṇḍaka Upaniṣads that either precede or are contemporary to the Buddha.

In general terms, they reflect the soteriological developments that expanded, in great depth, the ancient Vedic formulation of the soul's two possible paths after dead depending upon one's more or less good behaviour in this world: the path of the gods (devayāna) and the path of the manes (pitṛyāna), respectively. (Ṛg Veda, 2015, X.xviii.1 & X.ii.7)


This expansion entrusted the two paths with an unequivocal epistemological and teleological sense: (i) the path of rituals (yajña/iṣṭāpūrta), marked by partial knowledge or relative ignorance, is constitutive of an initial stage of self-transformation that projects existential change as a better rebirth; (ii) and the path of knowledge (jnãna/satya/tapas), marked by the complete elimination of ignorance and the full knowledge of the Non-Dual Reality (brahman), is constitutive of the ultimate stage of self-transformation leading to one's definitive overcoming of suffering, here and now, in this very world.


These two existential paths or levels of Reality are variously named in the Upaniṣads: pitṛloka (the world of the manes) and brahmaloka/devaloka (the world of Brahman) in the Bṛhadāraṇyaka Upaniṣad (1983, VI.ii.15-16, pp. 776, 780-1); pitṛloka (the world of the manes) and brahman/devayāna (the world of Brahman) in the Chāndogya Upaniṣad (1983, V.x.1&4, pp. 293 & 298); preyas (the path of one's desires) and śreyas (the path of one's betterment) and the Kaṭha Upaniṣad (1983, II.1, p. 152); and finally - perhaps the most accomplished epistemological sense - aparā-vidyā (lower knowledge/truth) and parā-vidyā (supreme knowledge/truth) in the Muṇḍaka Upaniṣad (1983, II.1.4, p. 320).


Therefore, what's at stake in MMK XXIV.8 is not a discussion on the constitutive elements of the 'two-truths' doctrine per se, but the way in which Nāgārjuna's reinterpretation of it, in line with Prajñāptivāda school, and, above all, by resorting to the concept of śūnyatā, impacts on one's understanding of the operational functionality and soteriological efficacy of the Buddha's discourse.

It constitutes a decisive moment in Indian Buddhism leading to a revision of the specific relation that articulates the nature of the Buddha's teachings, on the one hand, and the 'two-truths' doctrine, on the other.


It's common to find in some hermeneutical currents of the ābhidharmika tradition the expressions saṃvṛti-sat (Pāli, sammuti-sacca) and paramārtha-sat (Pāli, paramattha-sacca) being used as designative of two levels of the Buddha's teachings (deśanā; Pāli, desanā): an introductory or lower level, otherwise known as neyārtha (Pāli, neyyattha), mostly conveyed by concepts such as 'I' and 'mine'; and a profound and superior level, otherwise known as nītārtha (Pāli, nītattha), mostly conveyed by the Four Noble Truths and deconstructive concepts such as the elementary dharmas (skandhas, nidānas, āyatanas).20 In this case, both the levels and, therefore, the meaning of the word sat ('truth') itself have a clear pedagogical sense.

However, the Sarvāstivāda's intervention claiming to the 'the ultimate teaching' (nītārtha) - the elementary dharmas - the status of an 'ultimate (discursive) truth' (paramārtha-sat) prompts, in other circles, a counter reaction. That's precisely the case of the Mahāsāṃgika - and some of its subschools, such as the Prajñāptivāda - who declared, as discussed above, the conventional nature (saṃvṛti-sat) of all discursive reality - including the Buddha's teaching - and paramārtha-sat as a metalinguistic dimension.



Taking the Prajñāptivāda's critique to the ultimate consequences, Nāgārjuna's task in MMK XXIV.8 is to explain the renewed understanding of the correlation between the pair saṃvṛti-sat/paramārtha-sat and the Buddha's teachings.


His fiercely attack, throughout the MMK, on the Sarvāstivāda's elementary dharmas brings language, and more specifically the Buddha's soteriological discourse in both its dimensions (neyārtha and nītārtha), into the inescapable realm of samvṛtisat.

In other words, departing from the ābhidharmika tendency "to consider such words as 'I' and 'mine' as sammutisacca and the Noble Truth, the Eightfold Path, etc., as paramattha-sacca, Nāgārjuna includes ordinary discourse, as well as the Buddha Dharma in samvṛtisatya" (McCagney, 1997p. 86). In MMK XXIV.8, Nāgārjuna is unequivocal about that point: "You can't teach paramārtha-satya without resorting to saṃvṛti-satya".21 As a consequence, saṃvṛti-sat(ya) and neyārtha, on the one side, and paramārtha-sat(ya) and nītārtha, on the other, cease to be synonymous.

And the whole idea of inferior and superior levels of teaching begs itself for a redefinition within a pedagogical/epistemological context that necessarily involves samvṛtisat. It, finally, proscribes a possible translation or explanation of MMK XXIV.8's samvṛti-satya as 'lower teaching' and paramārtha-satya as a 'higher teaching'.


IV The Buddha's teachings as Upāya


Given the above considerations, the opponent's objections in MMK XXIV.8 to Nāgārjuna's resorting to śūnyatā as a critical instrument to denounce the impropriety of the Sarvāstivāda's elementary dharmas, not only seems to challenge the essential teachings of the Buddha - the Four Noble Truths and the Eightfold Path - but also the possibility of any Buddhist teaching at all.

Therefore, if in a first moment, Nāgārjuna denounces the opponent's misunderstanding of śūnyatā as an ontological doctrine - or, as state above, the opponent's misunderstanding of 'absence of substantiality' (śūnya) as 'non-existence' (abhāva) -, in a second moment, he is compelled to explain in detail how a discourse that keeps no representational relation to Reality can be conducive to the latter's complete realization.

In other words, how can a samvṛti-satya-based discourse lead to paramārtha-satya, if the latter is the spontaneous residue that follows the elimination of the errors of the former?


Nāgārjuna's answer to this fundamental query constitutes the core purpose of MMK XXIV.8 and following verses.

Combining the words of verses 8 and 10, it's clear that Nāgārjuna purports the following resolution: the Buddha's teachings are, everywhere, a peculiar combination of samvṛti-satya and paramārtha-satya, the first reflecting the unavoidable dimension of language and the second, the unavoidable stand from where any act perpetrated by a man like the Buddha - one who has attained nirvana/Bodhi - is originated.

This combination is precisely what defines the nature of an upāya, the fundamental feature of the Buddha's words. In verse 8, the word samupāśritya could be invoked as a philological corroboration. In fact, its primary sense of 'based on' - more commonly denoted by the cognate upāśritya - when prefix by sam could suggest the idea of an 'act of concertation', 'an act of combination', or 'an act of gathering' of constitutive factors. In that case, the translation would run as follows:


    The teachings of the Buddhas on the dharma are based on (a joint concertation of) two truths: the conventional truth (samvṛti-satya) and the truth (satya-paramārtha) based on the ultimate Reality (or the ultimate Truth). (MMK XXIV.8, p. 331)22

And, in verse 10, Nāgārjuna's stand is the more unequivocal in favouring this interpretation. He states:

    You can't teach the ultimate truth (paramārtha) without resorting to conventional truth (saṃvṛti). And without the realization of ultimate truth (paramārtha), realization (nirvāṇa) is not achieved.23


To admit the soteriological efficacy of the Buddha's discourse within Nāgārjuna's revised version of the two-truth doctrine, understood as a peculiar combination of saṃvṛtisatya and paramārthasatya, implies a significant re-evaluation of the saṃvṛti realm. Candrakīrti's gloss of the relevant passage of MMK XXIV.8-10 sets the explanatory tone for that re-evaluation.


In addition to the meaning as 'concealment' or 'being covered by ignorance' which reflects the mundane attitude of projecting substantiality or intrinsic nature (svabhāva) on that which is eminently unsubstantial or śūnya,24 Candrakīrti mentions a second meaning which points to a soteriological and ultimate function that brings forth the fundamental process of "mutual dependence" (anyonasaṃāśraya) or "dependent co-origination" (parasparasaṃbhava).25 We could, therefore, state that saṃvṛti is, simultaneously, "a closure and a powerful openness to the Other, an openness transversed by language and communication" (Lusthaus, 2002, p. 231)

In other words, saṃvṛti comprehends a twofold possibility in regard to its relation to paramārtha: (i) one which lacks the guidance and inspiration of paramārtha, i.e., which ignores the conventional nature of Reality; (ii) and another guided and inspired by paramārtha that realises conventionality - i.e., dependent co-origination (pratītyasamutpāda) or emptiness (śūnyatā) of svabhāva - as such.

It's precisely this latter meaning that peculiarly identifies the Buddha's teachings. It constitutes, in Candrakīrti's words, the unavoidable "means (upāya) to attain nirvāṇa", just like a "container for someone who wants water".26 The definitive clarification of this unique combination of the two truths in defining the nature of the Buddha's words and teachings is, finally, present in Candrakīrti's Madhyamakavatāra: "The conventional truth (saṃvṛtisatya) is the means (upāya-bhūta), the ultimate truth (paramārthasatya) is the goal (upeya-bhūta)".27



We are now in a better position to appreciate Nāgārjuna's reply to the opponent. He states that there is, in fact, a way of speaking the unspeakable and that the words of the Buddha have precisely that character. They don't speak directly, through propositional cognitive ways, but indirectly by systematically resorting to language that targets the elimination of one's errors about reality.


In other words, the Buddha's teaching are a language of the 'unsaying'28 (of errors), otherwise called '(eliminative) superimposition' (samāropa).29 That's precisely what Candrakīrti means when he states:


How can there be teaching (śruti) and instruction (deśana) of the dharma that is (by nature) inexpressible (anakṣara)? It is through (eliminative) superimposition of ideas (samāropa) that the inexpressible (anakṣara) can be taught and instructed.30


In short, the structure of the Buddha's teachings is invariably a combination of linguistic conventions and an inspiration derived from his having realized the ultimate truth. In other words, as a liberated being, the Buddha's actions can only be sourced in the ultimate truth (paramārtha) whereas, while resorting to teaching, he has necessarily to take support of conventional language (saṃvṛti).

As an extraordinary articulation between saṃvṛti-satya (conventional truth) e paramārtha-satya (supreme truth), the Buddha's teachings involves a re-orientation, a re-signification, a 'subversion', an expansion of the original meaning of saṃvṛti-satya, meant to suit the requirements of the meta-conceptual level of paramārtha-satya.


And, finally, this extraordinary re-orientation is operationally manifest as a pure eliminative procedure, a pedagogy of (eliminative) superimpositions (samāropa) (Tsondru, 2011, pp. 577-8). This eventful character of error elimination constitutes the inner most meaning of śūnyatā as a soteriological concept: instead of any substantive 'emptiness', it points to the radical procedure of 'emptying' illicit forms of superimposition (i.e., the superimposition of substantiality (svabhāva) onto the world).

Accordingly, Nāgārjuna states: "The Victorious Ones (Buddhas) have declared that emptiness (śūnyatā) is the process of relinquishing of all views (dṛṣṭi). Those who are possessed with the view of emptiness are said to be incorrigible."31


This extraordinary concertation between paramārtha-satya and saṃvṛti-satya is marked by a double fold dynamics: (i) it's a concertation aptly manipulated by a being in the plenitude of self-realization (Buddha/bodhisattva); and (ii) it's a concertation that adjusts itself to the specific requirements of the aspirants to nirvāṇa.


It's precisely this purportful combination of the two-truths doctrine in the context of a soteriological pedagogy, founded in the Buddha's teachings, that constitutes properly the nature of upāya. Upāya (s) are, therefore, sets of systematic argumentative teachings in which conventional language is entrusted with a unique eliminative capability.

They involve a rigorous and, at the same time, subversive use (i.e., systematically eliminative) of the main logical and epistemological instruments, especially the main (empirical) means of knowledge (pramāṇas), viz., pratyakṣa (perception) and anumāna.


Instead of substantive reifications, they are forced to expose and unveil the absence (anupalabdhi) of substantiality (svabhāva), the interdependent and empty nature of all one's objects of attachment - i.e., the objects of one's 'metaphysical inventions' on which both absolute existence or eternalism (śāśvatavāda) and absolute non-existence or nihilism (ucchedavāda) are erroneously superimposed.32

The principles behind this subversive task of turning upside down the traditional instrumentality of (empirical) pramāṇas and make them subservient to the main goal of deconstructing one's metaphysical inventions, are superbly discussed in Kamalaśila's Mūlamadhyamāka-āloka (The Illumination of the Middle Way) (2004).


The systematic elimination (upaśama) of one's obsessions (prapañca) (MMK Dedicatory Verse) or 'metaphysical inventions' - viz., the erroneous attribution of svabhāva to empty (śūnya) entities -, as Nāgārjuna puts it, constitutes, therefore, a rational procedure of apophatic character in strict compliance with the rules of logic and that has two key features.

First, it has existential efficacy since it does not pierce mere 'theoretical' constructs, but conceptual constructs that are constitutive of one's being in the world. In other words, the Buddha's eliminative deconstruction targets one's errors about reality that are constitutive of one's attachments. In fact, the ideas of attachment (kleśa), on the one hand, and of permanence (nitya) or substantiality (svabhāva), on the other, are to be understood in a co-extensive way.

Even when one 'theoretically' acknowledges the impermanent character of mundane objects, the joy and suffering that underscore our attachment for them are indicative of the subliminal presence of the wrong idea of permanence. Second, the modus operandi (of the systematic elimination) may involve positive or negative propositional judgments.

In fact, in mundane usage, both positive and negative propositions are 'positive cognitions' while their extraordinary upāyaka usage should necessarily involve the elimination of a previous cognition and this can be done with either of the two formal dimension of language. In other words, instead of a propositional judgment, the eliminative deconstruction of errors represents an instrumentalization of language as existential resolution, as existential decision.


The pedagogic alternation, in Mahāyāna Buddhism, between śūnyata (formally a propositional negation) and tathāgatagarbha or tathātā (formally as propositional affirmation), as distinct and equally effective moments of elimination of one's constitutive errors, is an excellence example of how saṃvṛti concepts (prajñāpti) are used for the sake of paramārtha.

This sequence of eliminative superimpositions - at time formally positive, at times formally negative - or, in other terms, this balance between positive and negative eliminative propositions preventing any form of discursive reification, has its programmatic principles well defined in the Prajñā Paramita Hṛdaya Sūtra's famous aphorism "Form (rūpa) is nothing but emptiness (śūnytā) and emptiness is nothing but form".33


The Lankāvatāra Sūtra, on the other hand, presents magnificent descriptions of that systematic procedure. The deconstruction of possible reifications of the seemingly 'negative' concept of śūnyata appears, for example, in the following passage:



    This [teaching of] emptiness, no-birth, non-duality, and no-self-nature is found in all the sutras of all the Buddhas, and this doctrine is recognized in every one of them. However. Mahāmati, the sutras are the teaching in conformity with the dispositions of all beings and deviate from the [real] sense, and not the truth-preserving statement.34

Conversely, the deconstruction of possible reifications of the seemingly 'positive' concept of tathāgatagarbha appears, for example, in the following passage:

    And the "No, Mahāmati, my Tathāgatagarbha is not the same as the ego taught by the philosophers; Thus, Mahāmati, the doctrine of the Tathāgatagarbha is disclosed in order to awaken the philosophers from their clinging to the idea of the ego."

An exemplary corollary of this fundamental pedagogical posture, that brings definitive centrality of the concept of upāya, is the Buddha's judicious usage of the words ātman (self) and anātman (non-self). In each and every concrete situation, neither ātman nor anātman are the object of any ontological declaration. Instead, they are resorted to as instruments of elimination of one's ontological phantasies towards one or another.

In ultimate analysis, one should avoid both the reifications, which are deemed to be the root-cause of one's suffering: the attachment for 'positive metaphysics' or eternalism (śāśvatavāda) as well as the attachment for 'negative metaphysics' or nihilism (ucchedavāda), respectively.

When a final truth is sought within the propositional discourse itself, the Buddha's answer is the silence. That's the magnificent lesson he delivered to Vaccagotta in the well-known Atthattasutta: "'Now then, Venerable Gotama, is there an ātman (Pāli, atta)?' When this was said, the Blessed One was silent. 'Then is there non-ātman (Pāli, anatta)?' A second time, the Blessed One was silent."35


V Conclusion


In synthesis, instead of ontological doctrines, the Buddha's words, as a peculiar combination of saṃvṛti-sat and paramartha-sat, are a continuous and systematic process of unsaying, of emptying one's erroneous conceptual attachments. The plurality of linguistic events that constitute a soteriological dialogue between masters and disciples do not have validity per se, having the status of instrumental concepts to be ultimately discarded.


Their final purportfulness is nirvāṇa/bodhi, i.e., the realization of the empty nature of all phenomena, the realization of conventionality as such. In other words, the final conclusion (pratijñā) of the argument does not occur in form of propositional language, but of a transformed being. Different from the causal and productive character of (empirical) means of knowledge (pramāṇas), the Buddha's teachings, as an upāya, are deemed to possess the character of a pramāṇa on account of their extraordinary results.

Candrakīrti states: "The wise men state that the words of the Buddha and of all those enlightened ones, are, in their entirety, a means of knowledge (pramāṇa)."36 The same idea is pregnant in Buddhist logicians such as Dignāga and Dharmakīrti.

The first designates the Buddha's words as pramāṇabhūta - i.e., "words that (have the power to) become a pramāṇa' - and the second designates them as being endowed pramaṇatā37 - i.e., 'intrinsic authority' (Ruegg, 1994, pp. 305-6) In short, the unique peculiarity of the Buddha's words lies in their being entirely committed to truthfulness on account of soteriological efficacy, which is nothing else but the removal of the existential blocks that prevent Reality to shine as it 'really is' (tathāgata). That's the gist of Nāgārjuna's insightful gloss of the Prajñā Paramita Hrdaya Sūtra recorded in the MMK:


There is no difference whatsoever between (the state of) realisation (nirvāṇa) and the mundane world (saṃsāra). There is no difference whatsoever between the mundane world (saṃsāra) and (the state of) realisation (nirvāṇa).38


The Buddha never talks about the un-describable Truth or Being, to use a term from Western metaphysics. But contrary to Wittgenstein's recommendation in his Tratactus Logico-Philosophicus (2015) - viz., "Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent" -, he does see this as reason to be silent. Much to the contrary.

The Buddha shows us that there is cognitive and, above all, soteriological functionality of language much beyond the suspension of its propositional functionality, i.e., much beyond the phenomenological 'suspension of judgement' (epoché).39 To go beyond it, means that 'suspension of judgement' has to necessarily be followed or has to necessarily involve - if understood as a process, rather than an event - by a systematic and logical deconstruction of subjectivity, the ultimate false ground of all ontological judgements.40


Congruent with the Buddha´s teachings, Nāgārjuna unleashes a rigorous logic that seeks to reverse the constitutive path of one's erroneous cognitions, the primary cause of one's attachments and suffering. This prophylactic intervention of reason, exclusively committed to error elimination, is all that needs to be done for the realization of nirvāṇa, the ever present paramārthika dimension of Reality.


This unique deconstructive role of language - or perhaps better, of conversational or dialogical language - as upāya is certainly something difficult to digest for a western modern tradition that has, by and large, crystalized reason as propositional analytical judgments. But there are exceptions and counter-current philosophical episodes. One of those is German philosopher Hans-George Gadamer who, in his commentary on Paul Celon's poetry titled "Who Am I and Who Are You?", gives the closest description in western modern philosophy of what an upāya stands for. He says:


The language of philosophy is a language that sublates itself, saying nothing and turning towards the whole at one and the same time. (Gadamer, 1997, p. 42)

2The present article is based on two homonymous conferences delivered at Oxford Centre of Hindu Studies, University of Oxford, in February, 2015, and at the Faculty of Divinity, University of Cambridge, in March, 2015. They were part of my activities as Visiting Scholar (Shivdasani Fellow) at the Oxford Centre of Hindu Studies, University of Oxford.


3From now on, to be referred to by the abbreviation MMK. I'll basically refer to the Sanskrit text included in David Kalupahana's Mūlamadhyamaka-kārikā. (1991) and, complementarily, to Raghunath Pandey´s edition "The Madhyamakaśāstram of Nāgārjuna" (1988-9).

4"Sabbamatthīti kho kaccāna, ayameko anto. Sabbaṃ natthīti ayaṃ dutiyo anto. Ete te kaccāna ubho ante anupagamma majjhena tathāgato dhammaṃ deseti" (Kaccānagottasutta, 2015, Saṃyutta Nikāya 12.15). In the MMK, Nāgārjuna makes an explicit reference to this sutra: "While admonishing Kātyāyana (pāli, Kaccāyana), the Buddha rejected both the theses, viz., 'everything exists' (astitva) and 'nothing exists' (nāstitva) ['Kātyāyanāvavāde cātīti nāstīti cobhayaṃ / pratiṣiddhaṃ bhagavatā bhāvābhāvavibhāvinā']" (MMK XV.7, p. 232).


5"'yo paṭiccasamuppādaṃ passati. So dhammaṃ passati. Yo dhammaṃ passati. So paṭiccasamuppādaṃ passatī'ti" (Mahāhatthipadopamasutta, 2015, Majjhima Nikāya 28).

6"Yasmā ca kho ānanda, suññaṃ attena vā attaniyena vā, tasmā suñño lokoti vuccati" (Suññalokasutta, 2015, Saṃyutta Nikāya 35.85).


7The notion of anyonyaprajñāpti was originally formulated by the Prajñāptivāda school and corresponds to the Nagarjuna's expression prajñāptir upādāya (vide MMK XXIV.18, p. 339) (Walser, 2008, p. 260).


8This and other quotations from Candrakīrti's Mūlamadhyamakāvatarbhāṣya are taken from Tsongkhapa's Tibetan commentary on Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā titled rTsa she ṭik chen rigs pa'i rgya mtsho /Tsashay tikchen rikpeh gyatso (Ocean of Reasoning: A Great Commentary on Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā). In the sequence, Tsongkhapa adds: "Each of the internal and external phenomena has two natures: an ultimate and a conventional nature" (2006, p. 483).


Tsongkhapa's modern commentator Dungen further explains: "(in Tsongkhapa), the basis of the division is not two levels of reality, but two objects of knowledge defined as the two epistemic isolates (or 'natures') of a single given phenomenon. Ultimate reality is not "higher" than conventional reality, but merely a property of every possible phenomenon" (2012).


9A suitable translation in terms of western philosophy would be Heidegger's distinction between 'Being' (das Sein) and 'beings' (das Seiende). He says: "Being is essentially different from a being, from be-ings... We call it the ontological difference - the differentiation between being and beings" (Heidegger, 1982, p. 17). The forgetfulness of this distinction (between 'Being' and 'beings') - otherwise called "the 'forgetfulness of Being' that... occurs in the course of Western philosophy" (Korab-Karpowicz, 2007, p. 301) - is perhaps responsible for the contemporary western divorce between philosophy and soteriology.

10"evaṃ tāvadabhāvena gṛhyamāṇā śūnytā grahītāraṃ vināśayati... abhāvārthaṃ hi śūnyatārthamadhyāropya prasaṅga udbhāvito bhavatā | na ca vayamabhāvārthaṃ śūnyatārthaṃ vyācakṣmahe, kiṃ tarhi pratītyasamutpādārtham | ityato na yuktametat śūnyatādarśanadūṣṇam" (Candrakīrti, 2015, XXIV.13).


11"śūnyatā sarvadṛṣṭīnāṃ proktā niḥsaraṇaṃ jinaiḥ / yeṣāṃ tu śūnytā-dṛṣṭis tān asādhyān babhāṣire" (MMK XIII.8, p. 223).

12"śūnyam iti na vaktavyam aśūnyam iti vā bhavet / ubhayaṃ nobhayaṃ ceti prajñāpty arthaṃ tu kathyate" (MMK XXII.11, p. 307).

13"yaḥ pratītyasamutpādaḥ śūnyatāṃ tāṃ pracakṣāmahe / sā prajñāptir upādāya pratipat madhyamā" (MMK XXIV.18, p. 339).

14"upāyakusalenāhaṃ buddhenādiccabandhunā / yoniso paṭipajjitvā bhave cittaṃ udabbahinti."["But with the help of the Buddha, the Kinsman of the Sun, so skilled in means, I practiced wisely, and extracted any attachment to being reborn from my mind."] (Kimbilattheragāthā, 2015, Theragātā 158, Kuddaka Nikāya).

15"piyena'rittena samaṅgibhūto / so tāraye tattha bahūpi aññe / tatrūpāyaññū kusalo mutīmā." ["As one who, having boarded a boat firmly equipped with oars and a rudder, and knowing the method, is skilful and wise, by means of it he causes many others to cross over."] (Dhamma [nāvā] Sutta, 2015, Suttanipāta 323, Kuddaka Nikāya).


16For the notion of upāya in the Mahāyāna sūtras see Michael Pye's "Skilful Means: A Concept in Mahayana Buddhism" (2003).

17See John Schroeder's "Nāgārjuna and the Doctrine of 'Skilful Means'" (2000).

18"dve satye samupāśritya buddhānāṃ dharma deśanā / loka-saṃvṛti-satyaṃ ca satyaṃ ca paramārthataḥ" (MMK XXIV.8, p. 331).

19Besides these schools, early Theravāda commentaries on the Kathāvatthu (viz., the Kathāvatthuppakaraṇaṭṭhakathā) and Aṅguttara Nikāya (viz., Manorathapūraṇī) make explicit references to the two truths doctrine. The former goes as follows: "The Awakened One, the best of teachers, spoke of two truths, conventional and higher; no third is ascertained" (cited in McCagney, 1997, p. 84).

20See, especially, the commentaries on the Kathāvatthu and Aṅguttara Nikāya (McCagney, 1997, pp. 82-6).

21"vyavahāramanāśritya paramārtho na deśyate" (MMK XXIV.8, p. 331).

22See note N. 16 above.

23"vyavāharamanāśritya paramārtho na deśyate / paramārthamanāgamya nirvāṇam nādhigamyate" (MMK XXIV.10, p. 333).

24He says: "'The mundane' (saṃvṛti) means being utterly obscured. Again, ignorance arising from the utter obscuring of the true nature of things is called 'the mundane'". ["samantādvaraṇaṃ saṃvṛtiḥ / ajñānaṃ hi samantātsarvapadārthatattvāvacchādanātsaṃvṛtirityucyate"] (Candrakīrti, 2015, XXIV.8).

25He says: "Again, to be reciprocally dependent in existence, that is, for things to be based on each other in utter reciprocity, is to be ' mundane' (saṃvṛti)" ["parasparasaṃbhavanaṃ vā saṃvṛtiranyonyasamāśrayeṇetyarthaḥ"] (Candrakīrti, 2015, XXIV.8).

26"This is why the mundane world (samvrti), as we have defined it, because it is the means to the attainment of nirvāṇa, must, at the outset, necessarily be accepted. It is like a container for someone who wants water". ["tasmānnirvāṇādhigamopāyatvādavaśyameva yathāvasthitā saṃvṛtirādāvevābhyupeyā bhājanamiva salilārthineti"] (Candrakīrti, 2015, XXIV.10).


27"upāyabhūtaṃ vyavahārasatyam / upeyabhūtaṃ paramārthasatyam" (Candrakīrti, 2014, 6.80, p. 14).

28I lent this term from Michael A. Sells' (1994).


29Samāropa represents, here, the extraordinary pedagogical meaning of saṃvṛti above discussed. It should be distinguished from the mundane sense of the word that points to an illicit superimposition of attributes - the superimposition of svabhāva - constitutive of the mundane dimension of saṃvṛti. In this case, however, as the Buddha's word, superimposition means, exclusively, an event of error elimination. We should also note that the word samāropa is also usually construed in combination with the word apavāda, meaning ´removal'. In this sense, the pair samāropa-apavāda - superimposition-removal - points to a formally positive attribution followed by a formally negative attribution where both are endowed with an eliminative character.


30"anakṣarasya dharmasya śrutiḥ kā deśanā ca kā | śrūyate deśyate cāpi samāropādanakṣaraḥ" (Candrakīrti, 2015, XV.2).

31"śūnytā sarva dṛṣṭīnāṃ proktā niḥsaraṇaṃ jinaisḥ / yeṣāṃ tu śūnyatādṛṣṭis tān asādhyān babhāṣire" (MMK XIII.8, p. 223).


32"'Exists' implies grasping after eternalism. 'Does not exist' implies the philosophy of annihilation. Therefore, a discerning person should not rely upon existence or non-existence." ["astīti śāśvatagrāho nāstīty ucchedadarśanaṃ / tasmāt astitvanāstitve nāśrīyeta vicakṣaṇaḥ"] (MMK XV.10).


33"rūpaṃ śūnyatā śūnyatā rūpaṃ" (Prajñā Paramita Hṛdaya Sūtra, 2015, p. 2).

34atha khalu bhagavān punarapi mahāmatiṃ bodhisattvaṃ mahāsattvametadavocat-etaddhi mahāmate śūnyatānutpādādvayaniḥsvabhāvalakṣaṇaṃ sarvabuddhānāṃ sarvasūtrāntagatam | yatra kvacitsūtrānte'yamevārtho vibhāvayitavyaḥ | eṣa hi mahāmate sūtrāntaḥ sarvasattvāśayadeśanārthavyabhicāraṇī, na sā tattvapratyavasthānakathā II.137.

35"kinnu kho bho gotama, atthattāti. Evaṃ vutte bhagavā tuṇhi ahosi. Kiṃ pana bho gotama, natthattāti. Dutiyampi kho bhagavā tuṇhi ahosi" (Atthattasutta, 2015, Saṃyutta Nikāya IV).


36"Ata eva buddhānāmeva bhagavatāṃ vacanaṃ pramāṇamityupavarṇayanti vicakṣanāḥ" (Candrakīrti, 2015, XV.6).

37"tavat pramānaṃ bhagavān abhūtavinivṛttaye / bhūtoktiḥ sādhanāpekṣā tato yuktā pramāṇatā" (Dharmakīrti, 1964, p. 134).

38"na saṃsārasya nirvāṇātkiṃcidasti viśeṣanam / na nirvāṇasya saṃsārāt-kiṃcidasti viśeṣanam" (MMK XXV.19).

39Understood as a mere event of self-decision, 'suspension of judgement' risks to promote the reification of transcendental subjectivity as it appear to the case of Edmund Husserl (1964, pp. 32-3).


40The ancient Pyrrhonist scepticism as reported by Sextus Empiricus (2015) and also Diogenes Laercius (2015) seems to subscribe to this ultimate procedure as part of its radical inquire (skeptomai) into the so-called 'ten modes' or 'tropes' (rpoiroi), among which the notions of 'relationness', 'circularity', 'mutual implication' and 'convergence of opposites' come remarkably close to the Mahāyāna's concepts of pratītyasamutpāda and śūnyatā.


References

(i) Ancient and Classical Literature

ATTHATTASUTTA. (Pāli original). In: Sutta Piṭaka. [Online] Available at: http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sltp/SN_IV_utf8.html#pts.400. (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

BṚHADĀRAṆYAKA UPANIṢAD. Madras (Chennai): Samata Books, 1983. [ Links ]

CANDRAKĪRTI. "Prasannapadā: Lucid Exposition of the Middle Way". (English translation by Mervyn Sprung). Boulder (US): Prajna Press, 1979. [ Links ]

CANDRAKĪRTI. "Madhyamakāvatāra & Madhyamakavatarabhāṣya: Introduction to the Middle Way". (English translation by Padmakara Translation Group). Boston: Shambala, 2002. [ Links ]

CANDRAKĪRTI. "Madhyamakāvatāra-kārikā-Chapter 6". (Sanskrit original edited by Li Xuezhu). Journal of Indian Philosophy, online publication (DOI 10.1007/s10781-014-9227-6), Accessed 22 May 2014. [ Links ]

CANDRAKĪRTI. "Prasannapadā". (Sanskrit original). [Online] Available at: gretil.sub.uni-goettingen.de/gretil/1_sanskr/6_sastra/3_phil/buddh/canprasu.htm (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

CHĀNDOGYA UPANIṢAD. (Sanskrit original). Madras (Chennai): Samata Books, 1983. [ Links ]

DHAMMA [NĀVĀ] SUTTA. (Pāli original). In: Sutta Piṭaka. Available at: http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sltp/Sn_utf8.html#v.316 (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

DHARMAKĪRTI. "Pramāṇavārttika". (Sanskrit original and English translation by Satkari Mookerjee). Patna: Nava Nalanda Mahavihara, 1964. [ Links ]

KACCĀNAGOTTASUTTA. (Pāli original). In: Sutta Piṭaka. Available at: http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sltp/SN_II_utf8.html#pts.016 (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

KAMALAŚĪLA. "Mūlamadhyamakāloka". (English translation of Sanskrit original by Ryusei Keira). In: R. Keira. Madhyamika and Epistemology A Study of Kamasila's Mehtod for Proving the Voideness of All Dharmas. Wien: Universitat Wien, 2004. [ Links ]

KAṬHA UPANIṢAD. (Sanskrit original). Madras (Chennai): Samata Books, 1983. [ Links ]

KIMBILATTHERAGĀTHĀ. (Pāli original). In: Sutta Piṭaka. Available at: http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sltp/Th_utf8.html#v.121 (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

LAERCIUS, D. "The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers. Life of Pyrrho". (English translation by C.D. Yonge). Available at: http://classicpersuasion.org/pw/diogenes/dlpyrrho.htm (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

LANKĀVATARA SŪTRA. (Sanskrit original). Available at: http://www.dsbcproject.org/node/4102 (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

MAHĀHATTHIPADOPAMASUTTA. (Pāli original). In: Sutta Piṭaka. Available at: http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sltp/MN_I_utf8.html#pts.184 (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

MAITREYA, A. "Ratnagotravibhāga". (English translation from the Sanskrit original by Jikido Takasaki). In: J. Takasaki. A Study on the Ratnagotravibhāga (Uttaratantra) Being a Treatise on the Tathāgatagarbha Theory of Mahāyāna Buddhism. Roma: Instituto Italiano Per il Medio ed Estremo Oriente, 1964. [ Links ]

MUṆḌAKA UPANIṢAD. (Sanskrit original). Madras (Chennai): Samata Books, 1983. [ Links ]

NĀGĀRJUNA. "The Madhyamakaśāstram of Nāgārjuna". Ed. by Raghunath Pandey). Vol. I & II. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1988-9. [ Links ]

NĀGĀRJUNA. "Mūlamadhyamaka-Kārikā. The Philosophy of the Middle Way". (Sanskrit original and English translation by David Kalupahana). New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1991. [ Links ]

NĀGĀRJUNA. "Bodhisambhāraka: The Treatise on the Provisions Essential to Enlightenment". (English translation by Christian Lindtner). Available at: http://www.bodhicitta.net/Bodhisambhara.htm (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

PRAJÑĀ PARAMITA HṚDAYA SŪTRA. (Sanskrit original). Available at: www.aci-la.org/ALLAUDIO/Sanskrit/DM_Sanskrit4/Sanskrit04-HeartSutra-deva-trans.pdf (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

ṚG VEDA. (Sanskrit original). Available at: http://www.sacred-texts.com/hin/rvsan/rvi10.htm (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

SUÑÑALOKASUTTA. (Pāli original). In: Sutta Piṭaka. Available at: http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sltp/SN_IV_utf8.html#pts.054 (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]


TSONGKHAPA. "Ocean of Reasoning: A Great Commentary on Nāgārjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika". (English translation from the Tibetan original by Jan Garfield & Geshe Ngawang Samten). New York: Oxford University Press, 2006. [ Links ]

UPĀYAKAUŚALYA SŪTRA: THE SKILL IN MEANS. (English translation by Mark Tatz). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1994. [ Links ]

(ii) Contemporary Literature

BARUAH, B. "Buddhist sects and sectarianism". New Delhi: Sarup & Sons, 2000. [ Links ]

DUNGEN, W. "Studies in Buddhadharma. On the Two Truths". 2012. Available at: www.sofiatopia.org/bodhi/two_truths.htm (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

GOMBRICH, R. "How Buddhism Began". London: Routledge, 2006. [ Links ]

HEIDEGGER, M. "The Basic Problems of Phenomenology". Bloomington (US): Indiana University Press, 1982. [ Links ]

HERZBERGER, R., HERZBERGER, H. "Two Truths, or One?". In: P. Bilimoria, J. N. Mohanty (ed.). Relativism, Suffering and Beyond: Essays in Memory of Bimal K. Matilal. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2003. pp. 278-300. [ Links ]

GADAMER, H.-G. "Gadamer on Celan: 'Who am I and Who Are You' and Other Essays". State University of New York Press. New York, 1997. [ Links ]

GARFIELD, J. L. "Taking Conventional Truth Seriously: Authority Regarding Deceptive Reality". Philosophy East and West, Vol. 60, Nr. 3, pp. 341-354, July 2010. [ Links ]

HUSSERL, E. "The Paris Lectures". The Hague: Spinger Science; Business Media, 1964. [ Links ]

KING, R. "Early Advaita Vedānta and Buddhism". Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995. [ Links ]

KORAB-KARPOWICZ, W. J. "Heidegger's Hidden Path: From Philosophy to Politics". The Review of Metaphysics, Nr. 61, pp. 295-315, December 2007. [ Links ]

LUSTHAUS, D. "Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Chʼeng Wei-shih Lun". London: Routledge, 2002. [ Links ]

MATSUNAGA, D., MATSUNAGA, A. "The Concept of Upāya in Mahāyāna Buddhist Philosophy". Japanese Journal of Religious Studies, 1/1, pp. 51-72, March 1974. [ Links ]

MCCAGNEY, N. "Nāgārjuna and the Philosophy of Openness". Maryland (US): Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 1997. [ Links ]

NAGAO, G. "Wisdom, Compassion and the Search for Understanding". Michigan: Institute for the Study of Buddhist Tradition, 2000. [ Links ]

PYE, M. "Skilful Means: A Concept in Mahayana Buddhism". London: Routledge, 2003. [ Links ]

RAMANAN, K. "Nagarjuna's Philosophy: As Presented in the Maha-Prajnaparamita-Sastra". Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1998. [ Links ]

RUEGG, D. S. "Pramanabuta, Pramana(bhuta)-Purusa, Pratyaksdharman and Saksatkrtadharman as Epithets of the Rsi, Acarya and Tathagata in Grammatical, Epistemological and Madhyamaka Texts". Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, Vol. 57, Issue 02, pp. 303-320, 1994. [ Links ]

SCHROEDER, J. "Nāgārjuna and the Doctrine of 'Skilful Means'". Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, Nr. 4, pp. 559-583, October 2000. [ Links ]

SELLS, Michael. "Mystical Languages of Unsaying". Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1994. [ Links ]

SHARMA, C. "The Advaita Tradition in Indian Philosophy: A Study of Advaita in Buddhism, Vedanta and Kashmira Shaivism". Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1996. [ Links ]

SHENGAI LI. "Candrakīrti's Āgama: A Study of the Concept and Uses of Scripture in Classical Indian Buddhism", 2012. Available at: depot.library.wisc.edu/repository/fedora/1711.dl:QNU5OBB2ULHON85/datastreams/REF/content (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

TATZ, M. "Introduction". In: Upāyakauśalya Sūtra: The Skill in Means. (English translation by Mark Tatz). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1994. [ Links ]

THAKCHOE, S. "The Two Truths Debate: Tsongkhapa and Gorampa on the Middle Way". Sommerville: Wisdom Publications, 2007. [ Links ]

TSONDRU, M. J. "Ornament of Reason: The Great Commentary to Nāgārjuna's Root of the Middle Way". (English translation from the Tibetan original by Dharmachacra Translation Committee). Ithaca: Snow Lion Publications, 2011. [ Links ]

WALSER, J. "Nāgārjuna in Context: Mahayana Buddhism and Early Indian Culture". New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 2008. [ Links ]

WESTERHOFF, J. "Nāgārjuna's Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction". New York: Oxford University Press, 2009. [ Links ]

WITTGENSTEIN, L. "Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus". (English translation by C.K. Ogden). Available at: http://www.kfs.org/jonathan/witt/t7en.html (Accessed 10 January 2015). [ Links ]

Received: February 15, 2015; Accepted: April 15, 2015

Source