Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Indian Philosophy .

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search




1 The Paper This paper deals with the thought of major writers in the classical Indian theory. Most lived in the period 100 A.D. to 1600 A.D. In recent years, philosophers have begun to reassess the sophistication and richness of the philosophical literature of ancient and classical India. The analytical techniques of modern philosophy are being used to interpret the texts in fresh and original ways. This paper explains the key methods, concepts and devices

of Indian philosophical theory, situating them in a proper historical context. It will not be a mere survey of thinkers and doctrines, but will seek new interpretations designed to bring out the richness and contemporary interest of the Indian theory. We will ask: what is the nature of their philosophical

project? what are the methods of philosophical inquiry used in pursuit of those goals? We shall concentrate on those philosophers who worked within and explored the parameters of a specific philosophical method, the so-called pramåna method, a way of analysing the basis and grounds of rational belief. We will study the work of the philosophers belonging to the traditional schools of Nyåya, Vaiße∑ika, Buddhism and Jainism, who used this method in their

philosophical theory. And we will look at several independent sceptical philosophers who were highly critical of the conception of rational inquiry this method sustains. Knowledge of Sanskrit is not a requirement for this paper since all the texts we discuss are available in translation. Most of the

secondary literature is available in the University and College libraries. SOAS library has all the books that are needed for this paper and students who are not at SOAS are allowed access to books and journals there.


2 General Reading There are a number of excellent introductions to Indian philosophical theory. For more advanced treatment of the theory, the work of Bimal Matilal is highly recommended.

[[Bimal Krishna [Matilal]], Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis

(Oxford, 2005) A recently re-printed classic. Jonardon Ganeri, P hi l os ophy i n C l a s s i c a l I ndi a : T he P r ope r W o r k of R e a s on (Routledge, 2001). A study of rationality and analysis in Indian philosophical theory. J. N. Mohanty, C l a s s i c a l I ndi a n P hi l os ophy (Rowman and Littlefield, 2002). A short but wide-ranging and engaging book.

The volumes of Karl Potter’s E nc y c l opa e di a of I n di a n P hi l os opi e r s contain useful introductions and surveys of the primary literature. This is an ongoing project with different volumes being devoted to different philosophical schools. So far eight volumes have been published. Volume 1 is a comprehensive bibliography (it is available online at http://faculty.washington.edu/kpotter/).

Others. Bimal Krishna Matilal, P e r c e pt i on. The best single volume in Indian epistemology, scholarly and reliable. Bimal Krishna Matilal, C ol l e c t e d E s s a ys (Oxford, 2002). Volume 1: M i nd, L a ngua ge a nd W or l d . Volume 2: E t hi c s a nd E pi c s . A collection of fine essays on a great variety of philosophical and methodological topics. Bimal Krishna Matilal, L ogi c , L a ngua g e a nd R e a l i t y (Motilal Banarsidass, 1985) .

Difficult but definitive treatment of many important issues. J.N. Mohanty, R e a s on a n d T r a di t i on i n I ndi a n T ho ught (Oxford, 1998) . Challenging interpretations of many key doctrines. Stephen Phillips, C l a s s i c a l I ndi a n M e t a phys i c s (Open Court, 1995) . Modern and engagingly written. S.N. Dasgupta, A H i s t or y of I ndi a n P hi l os ophy (Cambridge, 1922-55) . An old and monumental classic, quite dated but still useful.


a. Nyåya i. Early Nyåya The principal interests of the philosophers of the Nyåya school are epistemology and philosophical method. These are the philosophers who most forcefully advocate the so-called pramåˆa method as a method for rational inquiry. The main philosophers and texts in early Nyåya are – Gautama Ak∑apåda c. AD 150. NyåyasËtra Våtsyåyana c. AD 450. Nyåyabhå∑ya – commentary on NyåyasËtra Uddyotakara c. AD 600. Nyåyavårttika – commentary on Nyåyabhå∑ya Jayanta c. AD 875. Nyåyamañjar¥ – an independent work on Nyåya Våcaspati c. AD 960. Nyåyavårttikatåtparya†¥kå – commentary on Nyåyavårttika Udayana AD. 975–1050. Ótmatattvaviveka, Lak∑aˆåval¥, Nyåyakusumåñjali, and other treatises.

NyåyasËtra, by Gautama Ak∑apåda; [Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyaya]], Gautama’s NyåyasËtra with Våtsyåyana’s Commentary, with an introduction by Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya (Calcutta: Indian Studies Past and Present, 1982). Nyåyavårttika by Uddyotakara; Ganganatha Jha, The NyåyasËtras of Gautama with the Bhå∑ya of Våtsyåyana and the Vårttika of Uddyotakara (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1984), vols. 1–4. Nyåyamañjar¥ by Jayanta.; J. V. Bhattacharyya, Nyåyamañjar¥: The Compendium of Indian Speculative Logic (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1978). Ótmatattvaviveka, by Udayana; Kisor Kumar Chakrabarti, Classical Indian Philosophy of Mind: The Nyåya Dualist Tradition (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999), pp.219–276. ––, N. S. Dravid, Ótmatattvaviveka of Udayanåcårya (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Study, 1995). Lak∑aˆåval¥, by Udayana; Musashi Tachikawa, The Structure of the World in Udayana’s Realism: A Study of the Lak∑aˆåval¥ and the Kiraˆåval¥ (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1981). Nyåyakusumåñjali, by Udayana; N. S. Dravid, Nyåyakusumåñjali of Udayanåcårya (Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1996).

ii. Navya-Nyåya Navya-Nyåya, the ‘new’ Nyåya is a philosophical system invented by Ga∫geßa Upådhyåya c. AD 1325. It tries to find solutions to many of the criticisms that the early Nyåya conception of rational inquiry were confronted with by the sceptics. Raghunåtha Íiromaˆi c. AD 1500 revolutionised the teachings and methods of the school. Both he and his great follower, Gadådhara Bha††åcårya c. AD 1650, wrote short independent tracts on particular philosophical problems and concepts.

Tattvacintåmaˆi, by Ga∫geßa; Chapter I (epistemology) – Stephen Phillips and N. S. R. Tatacharya, Ga∫geßa’s ‘Jewel of Reflection on the Truth (about Epistemology),’ the Perception Chapter (Columbia University Press, 2005). Chapter II (logic) – Cornelius Goekoop, The Logic of Invariable Concomitance in the Tattvacintåmaˆi (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Co., 1967), pp. 55–154. Daniel H. H. Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyåya Logic (Harvard:

Harvard University Press, 1951). B. K. Matilal, The Navya-Nyåya Doctrine of Negation (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1968). There is a very thorough précis of the whole book in Karl Potter and Sibajiban Bhattacharyya eds. Indian Philosophical Analysis – Nyåya-Vaiße∑ika from Ga∫geßa to Raghunåtha Íiromaˆi Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, vol. 6 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1993), pp. 85–311.


PadårthatattvanirËpaˆa, by Raghunåtha; Karl H. Potter, The PadårthatattvanirËpaˆam of Raghunåtha Íiromaˆi (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, Harvard Yenching Institute Studies, vol. 17, 1957). Vi∑ayatåvåda, by Gadådhara; Sibajiban Bhattacharyya, Gadådhara’s Theory of Objectivity (Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990), vol. 2.

b. Vaiße∑ika Vaiße∑ika is an ancient school of metaphysics, known especially for its theory of categories and attempts to offer philosophical explanations for a variety of natural phenomena. Its generally naturalistic outlook complemented the heuristic methods of the Nyåya school, and with Udayana the two schools virtually merged into one. Important philosophers and texts in Vaiße∑ika include – Kaˆåda c. AD 100. Vaiße∑ikasËtra. Praßastapåda c. 575. Padårthadarmasaµgraha. Ír¥dhara c. 990. Nyåyakandal¥. Ía∫kara Mißra c. 1425. Upaskåra.

Vaiße∑ikasËtra, by Kaˆåda; Nandalal Sinha, The Vaiße∑ikasËtras of Kaˆåda, with the Upaskåra commentary of Ía∫kara Mißra (Allahabad: The Panini Office, Bhuvaneswari Asrama, 1911). Padårthadarmasaµgraha, by Praßastapåda; Ganganatha Jha, Padårthadharmasaµgraha with Ír¥dhara’s Nyåyakandal¥, The Pandit, n.s. vols. 25–37 (1903–15). Reprinted as a single volume.

c. The Buddhists i. Någårjuna and the Madhyamaka School Någårjuna’s c. AD 150 interpretation of the teachings of the Buddha was called the Doctrine of the Middle Way. He argues that all philosophical and scientific theories are empty of content. He is a severe critic of the pramåˆa method for conducting rational inquiry, and he claims instead that the only way to reason is by exposing incoherences within the fabric of one’s conceptions. Candrak¥rti c. AD 600 is an influential exponent and interpreter of Någårjuna.

MËlamadhyamakakårikå (The Middle Stanzas), by Någårjuna; Jay L. Garfield, The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995). ––, David Kalupahana, Någårjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle Way (Albany: SUNY Press 1986). ––, Kenneth Inada, Någårjuna: A Translation of his MËlamadhyamakakårikå (Tokyo: Hokuseido Press, 1970). ––, Frederick Streng, Emptiness: A Study in Religious Meaning (Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1967), pp. 183– 220. Vigrahavyåvartan¥ (Reply to Critics), by Någårjuna; K. Bhattacharya, E. H. Johnston and A. Kunst in The Dialectical Method of Någårjuna: Vigrahavyåvartan¥ (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1986). Prasannapadå, by Candrak¥rti; Mervyn Sprung, Lucid Exposition of the Middle Way: The Essential Chapters from the Prasannapadå of Candrak¥rti (Boulder, Colorado: Prajña Press, 1979).

ii. Di∫någa and Yogåcåra Buddhism Di∫någa c. AD 500 and his great follower Dharmak¥rti c. AD 625 interpreted the teachings of the Buddha in a very different direction, as a kind of idealism. The members of this school were brilliant logicians and made many important advances in philosophical theory. Although they are idealists, they are also advocates of the pramåˆa method as the correct way of investigating and resolving philosophical problems. They disagree with the Nyåya about almost every matter of philosophical substance, but because they share a common approach


to the rational resolution of philosophical dilemmas, the encounter between the two schools is fascinating and is an important axis in the evolution of Indian philosophical thought.

Pramåˆasamuccaya (Collection on Knowing), by Di∫någa; Chapter I (perception). Masaaki Hattori, Dignåga, On Perception, being the Pratyak∑apariccheda of Dignåga’s Pramåˆasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan versions (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968), pp. 21–70. Chapter II, V (logic, language). Richard P. Hayes, Dignåga on the Interpretation of Signs (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1988), pp. 231–248, 252–299.

Ólambanapar¥k∑å (Examination of Supports), by Di∫någa; Fernando Tola And Carmen Dragonetti, “Dignåga’s Ólambanapar¥k∑åv®tti,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 10 (1982), pp. 105–134. –, N. Aiyaswami Shastri, Ólambanapar¥k∑å and v®tti by Di∫någa with the Commentary of Dharmapåla, restored into Sanskrit from the Tibetan and Chinese Versions and Edited with an English Translation and Notes (Madras: The Adyar Library, 1942). Hetucakra∂amaru (Chart of Reasons), by

Di∫någa; Durgacharan Chatterji, “Hetucakranirˆaya - A Translation”, Indian Historical Quarterly 9 (1933), pp. 266– 272, 511–514. ––, Richard S. Y. Chi, Buddhist Formal Logic: A Study of Dignåga’s Hetucakra and K’uei-chi’s Great Commentary on the Nyåyapraveßa (London: Royal Asiatic Society, 1969). Pramåˆavårttika (Commentary on Knowing), by Dharmak¥rti; Chapter I (‘inference for oneself’). [v. 1–10] Richard P. Hayes and Brendan S. Gillon, “Introduction to Dharmak¥rti’s Theory of Inference as Presented in Pramåˆavårttika Svopajñav®tti 1– 10,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 19 (1991), pp. 1–74.

Chapter II ( ‘establishment of knowing’). [verses 1–6] Shoryu Katsura, “Dharmak¥rti’s Theory of Truth,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 12 (1984), pp. 215–235. [34–72] Eli Franco, Dharmak¥rti on Compassion and Rebirth (Vienna: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien Universität Wien, 1997). Chapter III (‘perception’). [1–51] Satkari Mookerjee and Hojun Nagasaki, The Pramåˆavårttika of Dharmak¥rti – An English Translation of the First Chapter

with the Autocommentary (Nalanda: Nava-Nalanda Mahavira Research Publication, 1964). Chapter IV (‘inference for others’). [1–148] Tom J. F. Tillemans, Dharmak¥rtis Pramåˆavårttika – An Annotated Translation of the Fourth Chapter (parårthånumåna) Vol. 1 (Vienna: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 2000). Nyåyabindu, by Dharmak¥rti; Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyaya, Vin¥tadeva’s Nyåyabindu†¥kå (Calcutta: Indian Studies Past & Present, 1971). ––, Theodore Stcherbatsky, “A Short Treatise of Logic by Dharmak¥rti with its Commentary by Dharmottara,” in his Buddhist Logic, vol. 2 (New York: Dover Publications, 1962), pp. 1–253. ––, G. C. Pande, Nyåyabindu (Sarnath, 1996). Vådanyåya, by Dharmak¥rti; Pradeep P. Gokhale, Vådanyåya of Dharmak¥rti: The Logic of Debate (Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications, 1993).

d. Others i. The Jainas Important Jaina philosophers include Siddhasena Divåkara c. AD 700, Haribhadra SËri c. AD 750, Hemacandra c. AD 1150 and Malli∑ena c. AD 1290. Their belief in the principles of tolerance, harmony and rapprochement lead them to a philosophy of pluralism in metaphysics and ethics and to perspectivalism in epistemology and semantics.

Nyåyåvatåra, by Siddhasena Divåkara; Piotr Balcerowicz, Jaina Epistemology in Historical and Comparative Perspective (Franz Steiner Verlag, 2000). –, Satis Chandra Vidyabhusana, Nyåyåvatåra: The Earliest Jaina Work on Pure Logic (Arrah: Central Jain Publishing House, 1915); reprinted in A. N. Upadhye ed., Siddhasena’s Nyåyåvatåra and Other Works (Bombay: Jain Sahitya Vikasa Mandala, 1971). ––,


Satkari Mookerjee, “A Critical and Comparative Study of Jaina Logic and Epistemology on the Basis of the Nyåyåvatåra of Siddhasena Divåkara”, Vaishali Institute Research Bulletin 1 (1971), pp. 1–144. Pramåˆam¥måµså, by Hemacandra; Satkari Mookerjee and N. Tatia, Hemacandra’s Pramåˆam¥måµså, Text and Translation with Critical Notes (Varanasi: Tara Publications, 1970). Syådvådamañjar¥, by Malli∑eˆa; partial translation by S. K. Saksena and C. A. Moore, in S. Radhakrishnan and C. A. Moore eds. A Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957), pp. 260–268.

ii. The Sceptics Two important sceptical thinkers are Jayaråßi c. AD 750, and Ír¥har∑a c. AD 1150. They are critics of the epistemological and metaphysical theories of the Nyåya, Vaiße∑ika, Buddhist and Jaina philosophers, and their criticisms were often the spur for philosophical progress in those systems.

Tattvopaplasiµha, by Jayaråßi; Chapter 1 (Perception). Eli Franco, Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayaråßi's Scepticism (2nd Edition, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1994). Chapter 2 (Inference). S.N. Shastri and S. N. Saksena, in Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan and Charles Moore eds, A Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957), pp. 236–246. Khaˆ∂anakhaˆ∂akhådya, by Ír¥har∑a; Ganganath Jha, The Khaˆ∂anakhaˆ∂akhådya of Ír¥ Har∑a (Delhi: Sri Satguru, 1986), 2 vols. ––, (Book I, Introduction). Phyllis Granoff, Philosophy and Argument in Late Vedånta: Ír¥har∑a’s Khaˆ∂anakhaˆ∂akhådya (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1978), pp. 71–208. ––, (Book I, Inference). Gangopadhyay, Mrinalkanti, Indian Logic In Its Sources (Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1984), pp. 67–118.


a. Early Nyåya — Methods of Rationality Inquiry (the pramåˆa method)

i. Rationality and philosophical method in India Wilhelm Halbfass, “Darßana, Ónv¥k∑ik¥, Philosophy,” in his India and Europe: an Essay in Understanding (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988), pp. 263–286. Bimal Krishna Matilal, “On The Concept of Philosophy in India,” in Philosophy, Culture and Religion: Collected Essays (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001). Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), chapter 3.

ii. The senses, the mind and the soul. Kishor Chakrabarti, Indian Philosophy of Mind: The Nyåya Dualist Tradition (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999). Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1986), chapters 6, 8. Bimal Krishna Matilal, “A Realist View Of Perception,” in P. K. Sen and R. R. Verma eds., The Philosophy of P.F. Strawson (New Delhi: Indian Council Of Philosophical Research, 1995), pp. 305–326; reprinted in his Philosophy, Religion, Culture: Collected Essays (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001). Arindam Chakrabarti, “I Touch What I Saw,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992), pp. 103–117.


Jonardon Ganeri, “Cross-modality and the self,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (2001).

iii. Extrapolation, informal logic, theory of debate Bimal Krishna Matilal, The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998). Esther Solomon, Indian Dialectics (Ahmedabad: B. J. Institute of Learning and Research, 1976), 2 volumes. Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyay, Indian Logic In Its Sources (Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1984). Claus Oetke, “Ancient Indian Logic as a Theory of Non-Monotonic Reasoning,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 24 (1996), pp. 447–539. John Taber, “Is Indian Logic Non-Monotonic?,” Philosophy East and West 54 (2004), pp. 143-170. Jonardon Ganeri ed., Indian Logic: A Reader (London: Cuzon, 2001). Jonardon Ganeri, Survey chapter on Indian Logic in Handbook of the History of Logic, Volume 1: Greek, Indian and Arabic Logic, edited by D.M. Gabbay and J. Woods, 2004, pp. 255–332. Pradeep Gokhale, Inference and Fallacies Discussed in Ancient Indian Logic (Delhi: Sri Satguru, 1992).

iv. Testimony and tradition. Bimal Krishna Matilal and Arindam Chakrabarti eds., Knowing from Words (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994). J. N. Mohanty, Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), chapters 8, 9. Jonardon Ganeri, “Testimony,” in Semantic Powers: Meaning and the Means of Knowing in Classical Indian Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999), pp. 72–81.


b. Madhyamaka Buddhism — Emptiness, Scepticism and Objectivity

i. Emptiness David Seyfort Ruegg, The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India (Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, 1981). C. W. Huntington, The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction to Early Indian Madhyamaka (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1989). David Burton, Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Någårjuna’s Philosophy (London: Curzon Press, 1999).

ii. The four options, Någårjuna’s dialectical method. Robinson, Richard H., “Some Logical Aspects of Någårjuna’s System”, Philosophy East and West 6 (1957), pp. 291–308. David Seyfort Ruegg, “The Uses of The Four Positions of The Catu∑ko†i and The Problem of The Description of Reality in Mahåyåna Buddhism,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 5 (1977), pp. 1–71. Brian Galloway, “Some Logical Issues in Madhyamaka Thought”, Journal of Indian Philosophy 17 (1989), pp. 1–35. Frank Hoffman, “Rationality in Early Buddhist Four-Fold Logic,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 10 (1982), pp. 309–337. Vijay Bharadwaja, “Rationality, Argumentation and Philosophical Embarrassment: A Study of Four Logical Alternatives (catu∑ko†i) in Buddhist Logic,” Philosophy East & West


34 (1984), pp. 303–319; reprinted in his Form and Validity in Indian Logic (Shimla: Indian Institute for Advanced Study, 1990), chapter 4.

iii. Paradoxes of causation, proof and motion Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), chapter 2. Mark Siderits, “Någårjuna as Anti-Realist,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 16 (1988), pp. 311–325. Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, “Någårjuna’s Arguments against Motion: Their Grammatical Basis,” in G. Bhattacharya et al. eds., A Corpus of Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Professor Gaurinath Sastri (Calcutta: Sanskrit Pustak Bhandar, 1980), pp. 85–95. Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, “The Grammatical Basis of Någårjuna’s Arguments: Some Further Considerations,” Indologica Taurinensia, 8–9 (1980–1), pp. 35–43. George Cardona, “A Path Still Taken: Some Early Indian Arguments Concerning Time,” Journal of the American Oriental Society 111.3 (1991), pp. 445–464.


iv. The threat of self-refutation Richard Robinson, “Did Någårjuna Really Refute All Philosophical Views?”, Philosophy East and West 22 (1972), pp. 325–331. David Seyfort Ruegg, “Does the Mådhyamika have a Thesis and Philosophical Position,” in B. K. Matilal and R. D. G. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in The Buddhist Analysis of Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp. 229–238. Paul Sagal, “Någårjuna’s Paradox,” American Philosophical Quarterly 29.1 (1992), pp. 79– 85.

v. The theory of no-self Jonardon Ganeri, “An irrealist theory of self,” The Harvard Review of Philosophy XII (Spring 2004), pp. 61–80. Mark Siderits, Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy (Ashgate, 2004). Roy Perrett, “Personal Identity, Minimalism and Madhyamaka,” Philosophy East and West 52 (2002), pp. 373-385. Matthew Kapstein, Reason’s Traces (Wisdom Books, 2001).


c. Vaiße∑ika Metaphysics – Order in Nature

i. The categories Wilhelm Halbfass, On Being and What There Is: Classical Vaiße∑ika and the History of Indian Ontology (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), chapters 1–5. Karl Potter ed., Indian Metaphysics and Epistemology – The Tradition of Nyåya-Vaiße∑ika up to Ga∫geßa, the Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, vol. 2 (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), introduction. S. Bhaduri, Studies in Nyåya-Vaiße∑ika Metaphysics (Poona: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, 1947).

ii. Universals, cross-cutting systems of natural kinds. Bimal Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), chapters 11, 12. Kishor Chakrabarti, “The Nyåya-Vaiße∑ika Theory of Universals”, Journal of Indian Philosophy 3 (1975), pp. 363–382. Wilhelm Halbfass, On Being and What There Is: Classical Vaiße∑ika and the History of Indian Ontology (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), chapters 6, 7. Sibajiban Bhattacharyya, “The Navya-Nyåya Theory of Universals,” in his Gadådhara’s Theory of Objectivity, Part 1: General Introduction to Navya-Nyåya Concepts (New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1990), chapter 3.


iii. Absence as a type of entity. Daniel Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyåya Logic (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951), pp. 54–62, 69–72. Bimal Matilal, The Navya-Nyåya Doctrine of Negation (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1968). Bimal Matilal, “Double Negation in Navya-Nyåya”, in M. Nagatomi et al. eds., Sanskrit and Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1980), pp. 1–10; reprinted in Logic, Language and Reality (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1985), pp. 145–154. Prabal Kumar Sen, “The Nyåya-Vaiße∑ika Theory of Variegated Colour (citrarËpa): Some Vexed Problems, Epistemology, Logic And Ontology After Matilal (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Studies), Studies in Humanities and Social Sciences 3.2 (1996), pp. 151–172.

iv. Number Jonardon Ganeri, “Objectivity and Proof in the Indian Theory of Number,” Synthese 129.3 (2001), pp. 413–437. Jonardon Ganeri, “Numbers as Properties of Objects: Frege and the Nyåya”, Epistemology, Logic And Ontology After Matilal (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Studies), Studies In Humanities And Social Sciences 3.2 (1996), pp. 111–121. Roy W. Perrett, “A Note on the Navya-Nyåya Account of Number,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (1985), pp. 227–234. B. K. Matilal, “On the theory of number and paryåpti in Navya-Nyåya,” in his Mind, Language and World (Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 133-140.

d. Yogåcåra Buddhism – Reduction and Rational Reconstruction

i. Metaphysics and epistemology in Di∫någa and Dharmak¥rti Masaaki Hattori, Dignåga, On Perception, being the Pratyak∑apariccheda of Dignåga’s Pramåˆasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan versions (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968). Richard Hayes, Dignåga on the Interpretation of Signs (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1988). B. K. Matilal & J. G. D. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982). Bimal Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), chapters 7, 10. George Dreyfuss, Recognizing Reality (Albany: SUNY, 1997). John Dunne, Foundations of Dharmak¥rti’s Philosophy (Wisdom Books, 2004).

ii. Language, meaning, exclusion Katsura Shoryu, “Dignåga and Dharmak¥rti on apoha,” in E. Steinkellner ed., Studies in the Buddhist Epistemological Tradition (Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1991), pp. 129–146. Hattori Masaaki, “The Sautråntika Background of the apoha Theory,” in Leslie S. Kawamura & Keith Scott eds., Buddhist Thought and Civilization: Essays in Honour of Herbert V. Guenther on his Sixtieth Birthday (Emeryville: Dharma Press, 1977), pp. 47–58. Hattori Masaaki, “Apoha and Pratibhå,” in M. Nagatomi et al. eds. Sanskrit and Indian Studies: Essays in Honour of Daniel H. H. Ingalls (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1980), pp. 61–74. Bimal Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), chapter 12. Jonardon Ganeri, “Dharmak¥rti’s Semantics for the Particle eva (only)” in Shoryu Katsura ed., Dharmak¥rti’s Thought and Its Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy (Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie Der Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 101–116..


iii. Extrapolation, the triple condition theory of reason Katsura Shoryu, “Dignåga on trairËpya,” Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies 32 (1983), pp. 15–21. Bimal Matilal, “Buddhist Logic and Epistemology,” in B. K. Matilal and R. D. Evans eds., Buddhist Logic and Epistemology: Studies in the Buddhist Analysis of Inference and Language (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1982), pp. 1–30; reprinted in his The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998), chapter 4. Tom F. Tillemans, “On sapak∑a,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 18 (1990), pp. 53–80. Claus Oetke, Studies on the Doctrine of trairËpya (Wien: Wiener Studien fur Tibetologie und Buddhismuskunde, 1993). Jonardon Ganeri, “Dharmak¥rti’s semantics for the quantifier only”, in Shoryu Katsura ed., Dharmak¥rti’s Thought and Its Impact on Indian and Tibetan Philosophy (Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie Der Wissenschaften, 1999), pp. 101–116. Richard Hayes, “On the Reinterpretation of Dharmak¥rti’s svabhåvahetu,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 15 (1987), pp. 319–332.


e. Jaina Philosophy – Rationality, Harmony and Perspective

i. Manysidedness Sukhlalji Sanghvi, “Anekåntavåda: The Principal Jaina Contribution to Logic,” in his Advanced Studies in Indian Logic & Metaphysics (Calcutta: Indian Studies Past & Present, 1961), pp. 15–28. Y. J. Padmarajiah, Jaina Theories of Reality and Knowledge (Bombay: Jain Sahitya Vikas Mandal, 1963). Jayandra Soni, “Dravya, Guˆa and Paryåya in Jaina Thought,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 19.1 (1991), pp. 75–88. Frank Van Den Bossche, “Jain Relativism: An Attempt at Understanding,” in R. Smet and K. Watanabe eds. Jain Studies in Honour of Jozef Deleu (Tokyo: Hon-No-Tomosha, 1993), pp. 457–474. Frank Van Den Bossche, “Existence and Non-Existence in Haribhadra SËri’s Anekåntajayapatåkå,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 23 (1995), pp. 429–468.

ii. Standpoints, logic of assertion Jonardon Ganeri, “Jaina logic and the philosophical basis of pluralism”, History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (2002), pp. 267–281. Jonardon Ganeri, Philosophy in Classical India, chapter 5. Pradeep Gokhale, “The Logical Structure of Syådvåda”, Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research 8 (1991), pp. 73–81. R. A. Kumar, T. M. Dak and A. D. Mishra eds., Anekåntavåda and Syådvåda (Landun: Jain Visva Bharati, 1996). B. K. Matilal, “Anekånta: both yes and no?”, Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research 8 (1991), pp. 1–12; reprinted as “The Jaina Contribution to Logic,” in The Character of Logic in India (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998), pp. 127–139. Piotr Balcerowicz, “The logical structure of the naya method of the Jainas,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 31 (2003).

iii. Jaina logical theory Sukhlalji Sanghvi, “On Problems of Inference,” in his Advanced Studies in Indian Logic & Metaphysics (Calcutta: Indian Studies Past & Present, 1961), pp. 77–110. Piotr Balcerowicz, “Is inexplicability otherwise (anyathånupapatti) otherwise explicable?,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 31 (2003), pp. 343-380.


e. Navya-Nyåya – Reason in Equilibrium

i. Reasoning from hypotheses Sitansusekhar Bagchi, Inductive Reasoning: A Study of Tarka and its Role in Indian Logic (Calcutta: Munishchandra Sinha, 1953). Vijay Bharadwaja, Form and Validity in Indian Logic (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Study, 1990), chapter 5. Esther Solomon, Indian Dialectics (Ahmedabad: B. J. Institute of Learning and Research, 1976) , chapter 12 (vol. 1), chapter 13 (vol. 2).


ii. Scepticism, doxastic ascent – Jayaråßi and Ír¥har∑a Phyllis Granoff, Philosophy and Argument in Late Vedånta: Ír¥har∑a’s Khaˆ∂anakhaˆ∂akhådya (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1978). Stephen Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics (La Salle: Open Court, 1995), chapter 3. Bimal Matilal, Logical and Ethical Issues in Religious Belief (Calcutta: University of Calcutta Press, 1982), chapter 4. Bimal Matilal, The Logical Illumination of Indian Mysticism, inaugural lecture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977). C. Ram–Prasad, “Immediacy and the Direct Theory of Perception: Problems from Ír¥har∑a,” Studies In Humanities And Social Sciences 3.2 (1996) – Epistemology, Logic And Ontology After Matilal (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Studies), pp. 33–56. Eli Franco, Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayaråßi’s Scepticism, 2nd edition (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1994).


iii. Epistemic equilibrium, the new epistemology Stephen Phillips, Classical Indian Metaphysics (La Salle: Open Court, 1995), chapter 4. Mrinalkanti Gangopadhyay, “Ga∫geßa on vyåptigraha:The Means for the Ascertainment of Invariable Concomitance,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 3 (1975), pp. 167–208. Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), chapters 4, 5.


iv. Navya-Nyåya logic Daniel Ingalls, Materials for the Study of Navya-Nyåya Logic (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951). Bimal Krishna Matilal, The Navya-Nyåya Doctrine of Negation (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1968). J. N. Mohanty, Ga∫geßa’s Theory of Truth (Santiniketan, 1966). Cornelius Goekoop, The Logic of Invariable Concomitance in the Tattvacintåmaˆi (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Co., 1967). Toshihiro Wada, Invariable Concomitance in Navya-Nyåya (Delhi: Sri Satguru, 1990).




Source