Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Thinking in Buddhism: Nagarjuna's Middle Way - Conclusion by Jonah Winters"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " As with any subject, much more could be said about Madhyamika, and often has been. Candrakirti's commentary, for example, runs to many hundreds of pages. This thesis, too,...")
 
m (Text replacement - "one thing " to "one thing ")
 
(8 intermediate revisions by 4 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
[[File:Black-3d40.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 +
As with any [[subject]], much more could be said about [[Madhyamika]], and often has been. [[Candrakirti's]] commentary, for example, runs to many hundreds of pages. This {{Wiki|thesis}}, too, far exceeds the normal length of bachelor's theses. In [[light]] of [[Nagarjuna's]] [[teaching]] that excessive theorizing is one of the main [[causes]] of [[suffering]] and bondage, it may seem that lengthy commentary is [[self]]- negating. This objection would be quite valid, were the intent of these research projects to express [[truth]] and the [[nature]] of [[reality]]. However, as exemplified in the Introduction, were that the intent of these works, they likely would have said no more than "this flax weighs three pounds."
 +
(SHOWING THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTS)
 +
The {{Wiki|purpose}} of the [[philosophy]] of [[Madhyamika]], with its [[stress]] on [[emptiness]], is not to discard all theorizing. Rather, the point is to demonstrate that theories are not ultimately valid. Ascribing excessive validity to the products of [[thought]] will [[cause]] one to [[grasp]] onto them and lose [[sight]] of the [[true nature]] of things, which is [[empty]]. The truest {{Wiki|conceptual}} expression of [[reality]] will always be a [[paradox]]. "A [[saint]] ([[bodhisattva]]) is a [[saint]] because there is no [[saint]]," says the [[Perfection]] of [[Wisdom]] school, "and that is why there is a [[saint]]!"
 
   
 
   
  As with any subject, much more could be said about Madhyamika, and often has been. Candrakirti's commentary, for example, runs to many hundreds of pages. This thesis, too, far exceeds the normal length of bachelor's theses. In light of Nagarjuna's teaching that excessive theorizing is one of the main causes of suffering and bondage, it may seem that lengthy commentary is self- negating. This objection would be quite valid, were the intent of these research projects to express truth and the nature of reality. However, as exemplified in the Introduction, were that the intent of these works, they likely would have said no more than "this flax weighs three pounds."
+
Note: quoted in [[Nagao]] 1989, vii
(SHOWING THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTS)
+
 
The purpose of the philosophy of Madhyamika, with its stress on emptiness, is not to discard all theorizing. Rather, the point is to demonstrate that theories are not ultimately valid. Ascribing excessive validity to the products of thought will cause one to grasp onto them and lose sight of the true nature of things, which is empty. The truest conceptual expression of reality will always be a paradox. "A saint (bodhisattva) is a saint because there is no saint," says the Perfection of Wisdom school, "and that is why there is a saint!"
+
Concepts are applicable in the [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] [[sphere]] only. This is the place of commentary and research: such projects can clarify the [[nature]] of the [[phenomenal]] [[world]] and discuss the [[relative]] validity of various theories within that plane. Neither the [[Buddha]] nor [[Nagarjuna]] would have said that the [[rational]] {{Wiki|faculty}} has no [[function]], for, though no {{Wiki|theory}} is absolutely true, some theories are certainly better than others.
        Note: quoted in Nagao 1989, vii
+
 
    Concepts are applicable in the conventional sphere only. This is the place of commentary and research: such projects can clarify the nature of the phenomenal world and discuss the relative validity of various theories within that plane. Neither the Buddha nor Nagarjuna would have said that the rational faculty has no function, for, though no theory is absolutely true, some theories are certainly better than others.
+
When one wishes to speak of the [[ultimate]] [[sphere]], [[thoughts]] can point the way towards a proper [[understanding]] of it and teach one how to achieve the Perfect [[Wisdom]] which can {{Wiki|perceive}} it, but theories themselves cannot express its [[nature]].
    When one wishes to speak of the ultimate sphere, thoughts can point the way towards a proper understanding of it and teach one how to achieve the Perfect Wisdom which can perceive it, but theories themselves cannot express its nature.
 
 
(A CONCEPT / A DUALITY / A SKILFUL MEAN)
 
(A CONCEPT / A DUALITY / A SKILFUL MEAN)
As a conventional truth, the Madhyamika philosophy propounds a system of ordering one's thought, and then it shows where such thought must end. This system includes
+
As a [[conventional truth]], the [[Madhyamika]] [[philosophy]] propounds a system of ordering one's [[thought]], and then it shows where such [[thought]] must end. This system includes
        the theory of dependent arising,
+
:        the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[dependent arising]],
        the four Noble Truths,
+
:        the four [[Noble]] [[Truths]],
        the constitution of the psychophysical personality,
+
:        the constitution of the {{Wiki|psychophysical]] [[personality]],
        and the Noble Eightfold Path;
+
:        and the [[Noble Eightfold Path]];
        the theory of emptiness points out the limit of the mental faculty.
+
:        the theory of [[emptiness]] points out the limit of the [[mental]] faculty.
    Nagarjuna demonstrates that all of his ideas are pragmatic only in one of the most famous verses of his treatise:  
+
 
        "We state that whatever is dependent arising, that is emptiness.
+
[[Nagarjuna]] demonstrates that all of his ideas are pragmatic only in one of the most famous verses of his treatise:  
        That is dependent upon convention.
+
:        "We state that whatever is [[dependent arising]], that is [[emptiness]].
        That itself is the middle path."
+
:        That is dependent upon convention.
            Note: karika XXIV.18  
+
:        That itself is the [[middle path]]."
    This verse succinctly ties together his entire philosophy, shows where it comes to an end, and defines the point of it all.  
+
::            Note: karika XXIV.18  
    Nagarjuna's thought can be summed up in the first two terms of the verse: dependent arising and emptiness.
+
[[File:Bu a.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
    From these all other elements of his philosophy are derived.
+
This verse succinctly ties together his entire [[philosophy]], shows where it comes to an end, and defines the point of it all.  
        Dependent arising explains all aspects of the relative world, for it details the process of causation and, hence, the ontology of the world.
+
[[Nagarjuna's]] [[thought]] can be summed up in the first two terms of the verse: [[dependent arising]] and [[emptiness]].
        Emptiness is the only possible description of ultimate truth, for it demonstrates relativity and provides a sort of anti-theory on which the rational faculty can focus.
+
From these all other [[elements]] of his [[philosophy]] are derived.
        Neither of these, though, should be relied on as valid in themselves, for they are both "dependent upon convention."
+
[[Dependent arising]] explains all aspects of the [[relative]] [[world]], for it details the process of [[causation]] and, hence, the {{Wiki|ontology}} of the [[world]].
            Note: The original of this latter phrase, sa prajnaptir upadaya, is a famously difficult one to translate. For example, Nagao renders it "a designation based upon (some material)," Ramana as "derived name," and Sprung as "a guiding, not a cognitive, notion, presupposing the everyday." Kalupahana's translation was used here because, while not necessarily more accurate than any others, it is clearer and more succinct.
+
[[Emptiness]] is the only possible description of [[ultimate truth]], for it demonstrates [[relativity]] and provides a sort of anti-theory on which the [[rational]] {{Wiki|faculty}} can focus.
        Any theory, even one as all-encompassing as emptiness, is still a theory based on convention.
+
 
        Were there no dependently arisen things, there would be no theory of dependent arising.
+
Neither of these, though, should be relied on as valid in themselves, for they are both "[[dependent upon]] convention."
        Further, even though these things are empty, they are at least phenomenally real; if they were not, there would be no theory of emptiness, for there would be nothing on which to base it.
+
 
    Heinrich Zimmer. Philosophies of India. New York: Meridian Books, 1957
+
Note: The original of this [[latter]] [[phrase]], sa [[prajnaptir upadaya]], is a famously difficult one to translate. For example, [[Nagao]] renders it "a designation based upon (some material)," [[Ramana]] as "derived [[name]]," and Sprung as "a guiding, not a [[cognitive]], notion, presupposing the everyday." [[Kalupahana's]] translation was used here because, while not necessarily more accurate than any others, it is clearer and more succinct.
        Dependent arising and emptiness are relative to each other, and both are relative to the perceived world. They thus constitute a middle path.
+
:        Any {{Wiki|theory}}, even one as all-encompassing as [[emptiness]], is still a {{Wiki|theory}} based on convention.
        One must remember that dependent arising would be no more proper a description of ultimate truth than emptiness, and vice-versa, else either materialism or nihilism would result.
+
:        Were there no [[dependently arisen]] things, there would be no {{Wiki|theory}} of [[dependent arising]].
        Likewise, one must find a middle ground between theorizing and refraining from doing so.
+
:        Further, even though these things are [[empty]], they are at least phenomenally real; if they were not, there would be no {{Wiki|theory}} of [[emptiness]], for there would be [[nothing]] on which to base it.
        The philosophy of Madhyamika is of vital importance, for it explains reality and points the way to an escape from it. Were one to accept no philosophy, the mental faculties would be ungrounded and directionless. On the other hand, one must remember the proper place of philosophies as based on convention only; they have no final validity. This, Nagarjuna says, is the middle path of the Buddha.
+
 
 +
Heinrich Zimmer. [[Philosophies]] of [[India]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Meridian [[Books]], 1957
 +
:        [[Dependent arising]] and [[emptiness]] are [[relative]] to each other, and both are [[relative]] to the [[perceived]] [[world]]. They thus constitute a [[middle path]].
 +
:        One must remember that [[dependent arising]] would be no more proper a description of [[ultimate truth]] than [[emptiness]], and vice-versa, else either {{Wiki|materialism}} or [[nihilism]] would result.
 +
:        Likewise, one must find a middle ground between theorizing and refraining from doing so.
 +
 
 +
The [[philosophy]] of [[Madhyamika]] is of [[vital]] importance, for it explains [[reality]] and points the way to an escape from it. Were one to accept no [[philosophy]], the [[mental faculties]] would be ungrounded and directionless. On the other hand, one must remember the proper place of [[philosophies]] as based on convention only; they have no final validity. This, [[Nagarjuna]] says, is the [[middle path]] of the [[Buddha]].
 
(INDESCRIPTIBLE)
 
(INDESCRIPTIBLE)
Perhaps the most important thing demonstrated by the equation Nagarjuna presents in the above verse is that the Madhyamika philosophy is, in its essence, very simple. "Independently realized, peaceful, unobsessed by obsessions, without discriminations and a variety of meaning: such is the characteristic of truth," he says. [Note: karika XVIII.9 ] The one clear perception underlying Madhyamika is the interconnectedness and complete dependence of all things. Becoming and being, past and future, reality and emptiness, subject and object, arising and ceasing are all real things, but only in relation to each other. None exist absolutely. Unfortunately, this insight, while utterly simple and clear, is not so easily explained. The function of language and concepts is to make distinctions and impose artificial boundaries. The very word "define" has in its roots the connotation of creating boundaries (de + finis). The Buddha and Nagarjuna had no choice but to explain their insight into the nature of reality in philosophical terms, formulas, and theories. Nagarjuna's brilliance lay in his ability to explain it so clearly, and then to build such effective safeguards against excessive philosophizing into his system.
+
Perhaps the most important thing demonstrated by the equation [[Nagarjuna]] presents in the above verse is that the [[Madhyamika]] [[philosophy]] is, in its [[essence]], very simple. "Independently [[realized]], [[peaceful]], unobsessed by [[obsessions]], without discriminations and a variety of meaning: such is the [[characteristic]] of [[truth]]," he says. [Note: [[karika]] XVIII.9 ] The one clear [[perception]] underlying [[Madhyamika]] is the interconnectedness and complete [[dependence]] of all things. Becoming and [[being]], {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}}, [[reality]] and [[emptiness]], [[subject]] and [[object]], [[arising]] and ceasing are all real things, but only in [[relation]] to each other. None [[exist]] absolutely. Unfortunately, this [[insight]], while utterly simple and clear, is not so easily explained. The [[function]] of [[language]] and [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] is to make {{Wiki|distinctions}} and impose artificial [[boundaries]]. The very [[word]] "define" has in its [[roots]] the connotation of creating [[boundaries]] (de + finis). The [[Buddha]] and [[Nagarjuna]] had no choice but to explain their [[insight]] into the [[nature]] of [[reality]] in [[philosophical]] terms, [[formulas]], and theories. [[Nagarjuna's]] [[brilliance]] lay in his ability to explain it so clearly, and then [[to build]] such effective safeguards against excessive philosophizing into his system.
Ultimately, the one thing that is of importance is the Buddha's three-faceted teaching of transitoriness, soullessness, and suffering, the goal of which teaching being freedom. Only in light of this can Buddhism and Nagarjuna's enterprise be understood correctly. Rejecting all conceptual extremes and advocating a middle path is not an exercise in philosophy, but an aid to help people escape suffering and become free. The Visuddhimagga expresses poetically but succinctly the reality that remains when the Buddha's teachings are truly understood:
+
Ultimately, the one thing that is of importance is the [[Buddha's]] three-faceted [[teaching]] of transitoriness, soullessness, and [[suffering]], the goal of which [[teaching]] [[being]] freedom. Only in [[light]] of this can [[Buddhism]] and [[Nagarjuna's]] enterprise be understood correctly. Rejecting all {{Wiki|conceptual}} [[extremes]] and advocating a [[middle path]] is not an exercise in [[philosophy]], but an aid to help [[people]] escape [[suffering]] and become free. The [[Visuddhimagga]] expresses poetically but succinctly the [[reality]] that remains when the [[Buddha's]] teachings are truly understood:
    "Misery only doth exist, none miserable,
+
:    "[[Misery]] only doth [[exist]], none [[miserable]],
    No doer is there; naught save the deed is found.
+
:    No doer is there; naught save the [[deed]] is found.
    Nirvana is, but not the man who seeks it.
+
:    [[Nirvana]] is, but not the man who seeks it.
    The Path exists, but not the traveler on it."
+
:    The [[Path]] [[exists]], but not the traveler on it."
        Note: Visuddhimagga, quoted in Warren, 146
+
::        Note: [[Visuddhimagga]], quoted in Warren, 146
 +
[[File:C.jpga6e7114e.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 +
 
 
Epilogue
 
Epilogue
This research project was not merely an academic exercise. I would like to address briefly what I consider to be the importance of Madhyamika to our modern world, Occidental or otherwise. To my knowledge, there has never been in recorded history a philosophical system so exhaustively apophatic as Nagarjuna's that was not also a nihilism. Even Zen, the champion of paradox, is not really either apophatic or a system. I have defended the value of Madhyamika within the Buddhist tradition as being a defense of and an explanation of the twin doctrines of soullessness and transitoriness, the purpose of which being an aid to escape suffering. Outside the Buddhist tradition the importance of Madhyamika is slightly different, for it is not likely that the Western undercurrents of essentialism could easily be unseated — -nor would I want to.
+
 
    One value of this philosophy for the West lies in its potential to undercut the habits of "I-making" and grasping, both grasping onto the things of the world and grasping onto the products of rationality.
+
This research project was not merely an {{Wiki|academic}} exercise. I would like to address briefly what I consider to be the importance of [[Madhyamika]] to our {{Wiki|modern}} [[world]], {{Wiki|Occidental}} or otherwise. To my [[knowledge]], there has never been in recorded history a [[philosophical]] system so exhaustively {{Wiki|apophatic}} as [[Nagarjuna's]] that was not also a [[nihilism]]. Even [[Zen]], the champion of [[paradox]], is not really either {{Wiki|apophatic}} or a system. I have defended the value of [[Madhyamika]] within the [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]] as [[being]] a defense of and an explanation of the twin [[doctrines]] of soullessness and transitoriness, the {{Wiki|purpose}} of which [[being]] an aid to escape [[suffering]]. Outside the [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]] the importance of [[Madhyamika]] is slightly different, for it is not likely that the {{Wiki|Western}} undercurrents of [[essentialism]] could easily be unseated — -nor would I want to.
    Another value is the contribution Madhyamika could make to Western philosophy and theology.
+
 
Many of the structures of the modern world are based, in some way or other, on distrust of individual authority. For example, that which has become American democracy is rooted in a party system. The hope is that, if two or more parties compete for election and for legislation, then compromises will emerge in the long run, and no individual will have too much power. The method on which science is based is founded on a similar safeguard. One can never prove, but only disprove. Third, the quest for objectivity underlying all academia certainly betrays this distrust. There is a strong emphasis on removing all personal reference from research and attempting to make it uninfluenced by any personal emotions or prejudices. These safeguards are necessary components of the structures we have. However, it is not certain that these structures are the only option.
+
One value of this [[philosophy]] for the [[West]] lies in its potential to undercut the [[habits]] of "I-making" and [[grasping]], both [[grasping]] onto the things of the [[world]] and [[grasping]] onto the products of {{Wiki|rationality}}.
The Buddha's teachings demonstrate that, in a way, emphasis on the self is the root of all evil. It is an excessive "self-ishness" that causes one to desire passionately, to assert forcefully one's opinions and thoughts, to want to be right, to desire to possess. "Self-ishness" is that which, in whatever situation, causes one to seek one's own well-being and ignore the thoughts and needs of others. The Buddha's path, especially as enunciated so radically by Nagarjuna, subverts this "I-making." I do not know what the result would be if the doctrine of soullessness were introduced into our systems of politics, science, and academia, but my suspicion is that the results would be beneficial.
+
 
The other importance of Nagarjuna's agenda for me is the impact it could have on our rational structures of philosophy and theology. There are many discerning thinkers in these fields whose philosophies are in no way simplistic, but there are far too few. A study of Madhyamika philosophy has not forced me to abandon my belief in concepts like God, the soul, and the afterlife. What it has done is shown me, if I am to retain those beliefs, of what they may and may not consist. Nagarjuna's teaching of emptiness can vastly deepen and enrich one's religious and philosophical notions. Further, his teachings can demonstrate to what extent those notions are self-created and, thus, which notions may be true, which false, and which merely helpful guides that must ultimately be abandoned.
+
Another value is the contribution [[Madhyamika]] could make to {{Wiki|Western philosophy}} and {{Wiki|theology}}.
The philosophies of the Buddha and Nagarjuna offer trenchant explanations of the constitution of reality, the function of the human mind, and the purpose to which an individual's life and, in some cases, academic career should be devoted. A study of Madhyamika, if approached with a receptive attitude, will complement any philosophy, no matter how antithetical.
+
 
 +
Many of the structures of the {{Wiki|modern}} [[world]] are based, in some way or other, on [[distrust]] of {{Wiki|individual}} authority. For example, that which has become [[American]] {{Wiki|democracy}} is [[rooted]] in a party system. The {{Wiki|hope}} is that, if two or more parties compete for election and for legislation, then compromises will emerge in the long run, and no {{Wiki|individual}} will have too much [[power]]. The method on which [[science]] is based is founded on a similar safeguard. One can never prove, but only disprove. Third, the quest for objectivity underlying all {{Wiki|academia}} certainly betrays this [[distrust]]. There is a strong {{Wiki|emphasis}} on removing all personal reference from research and attempting to make it uninfluenced by any personal [[emotions]] or prejudices. These safeguards are necessary components of the structures we have. However, it is not certain that these structures are the only option.
 +
The [[Buddha's]] teachings demonstrate that, in a way, {{Wiki|emphasis}} on the [[self]] is the [[root]] of all [[evil]]. It is an excessive "self-ishness" that [[causes]] one to [[desire]] passionately, to assert forcefully one's opinions and [[thoughts]], to want to be right, to [[desire]] to possess. "Self-ishness" is that which, in whatever situation, [[causes]] one to seek one's [[own]] well-being and ignore the [[thoughts]] and needs of others. The [[Buddha's]] [[path]], especially as enunciated so radically by [[Nagarjuna]], subverts this "I-making." I do not know what the result would be if the [[doctrine]] of soullessness were introduced into our systems of {{Wiki|politics}}, [[science]], and {{Wiki|academia}}, but my [[suspicion]] is that the results would be beneficial.
 +
The other importance of [[Nagarjuna's]] agenda for me is the impact it could have on our [[rational]] structures of [[philosophy]] and {{Wiki|theology}}. There are many discerning thinkers in these fields whose [[philosophies]] are in no way simplistic, but there are far too few. A study of [[Madhyamika]] [[philosophy]] has not forced me to abandon my [[belief]] in [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] like [[God]], the [[soul]], and the [[afterlife]]. What it has done is shown me, if I am to retain those [[beliefs]], of what they may and may not consist. [[Nagarjuna's]] [[teaching]] of [[emptiness]] can vastly deepen and enrich one's [[religious]] and [[philosophical]] notions. Further, his teachings can demonstrate to what extent those notions are self-created and, thus, which notions may be true, which false, and which merely helpful guides that must ultimately be abandoned.
 +
The [[philosophies]] of the [[Buddha]] and [[Nagarjuna]] offer trenchant explanations of the constitution of [[reality]], the [[function]] of the [[human]] [[mind]], and the {{Wiki|purpose}} to which an individual's [[life]] and, in some cases, {{Wiki|academic}} career should be devoted. A study of [[Madhyamika]], if approached with a receptive [[attitude]], will complement any [[philosophy]], no {{Wiki|matter}} how [[Wikipedia:Anti-life|antithetical]].
 +
[[File:BuddhaToBe.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
Bibliography
 
Bibliography
    Satischandra Chatterjee and Dhirendramohan Datta. An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Calcutta: University of Calcutta, 1960.
+
*    Satischandra [[Chatterjee]] and Dhirendramohan [[Datta]]. An Introduction to [[Indian Philosophy]]. [[Calcutta]]: [[University of Calcutta]], 1960.
    Edward Conze. Buddhism: Its Essence and Development. New York: Harper and Row, 1975.
+
*    [[Edward Conze]]. [[Buddhism]]: Its [[Essence]] and [[Development]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Harper and Row, 1975.
    Edward Conze, ed. and trans. Buddhist Scriptures. London: Penguin Books, 1959.
+
*    [[Edward Conze]], ed. and trans. [[Buddhist Scriptures]]. {{Wiki|London}}: Penguin [[Books]], 1959.
    Edward Conze, ed. and trans. The Large Sutra on Perfect Wisdom. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1975.
+
*    [[Edward Conze]], ed. and trans. The Large [[Sutra]] on Perfect [[Wisdom]]. {{Wiki|Berkeley}}: {{Wiki|University of California Press}}, 1975.
    Michael Coulson. Sanskrit. Chicago: NTC Publishing Group, 1992.
+
*    Michael Coulson. [[Sanskrit]]. {{Wiki|Chicago}}: NTC Publishing Group, 1992.
    Ainslee~T. Embree, ed. Sources of Indian Tradition, volume one. New York: Columbia University Press, 1988.
+
*    Ainslee~T. Embree, ed. Sources of [[Indian]] [[Tradition]], volume one. {{Wiki|New York}}: {{Wiki|Columbia University Press}}, 1988.
    Etienne Lamotte, trans. Sara Webb-Boin. History of Indian Buddhism. Louvain-La-Neuve: Institut Orientaliste, 1988.
+
*    {{Wiki|Etienne Lamotte}}, trans. Sara Webb-Boin. History of [[Indian Buddhism]]. Louvain-La-Neuve: Institut Orientaliste, 1988.
    Ramendranath Ghose. The Dialectics of Nagarjuna. Allahabad, India: Vohra Publishers and Distributors, 1987.
+
*    Ramendranath Ghose. The [[Dialectics]] of [[Nagarjuna]]. [[Allahabad]], [[India]]: Vohra Publishers and Distributors, 1987.
    John Grimes, ed. A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy. Madras: University of Madras, 1988.
+
*    John Grimes, ed. A Concise {{Wiki|Dictionary}} of [[Indian Philosophy]]. [[Madras]]: {{Wiki|University}} of [[Madras]], 1988.
    Herbert Guenther. Buddhism: Tibetan schools. Encyclopedia of Religion, 1987.
+
*    {{Wiki|Herbert Guenther}}. [[Buddhism]]: [[Tibetan]] schools. {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Religion]], 1987.
    Edith Hamilton. Mythology. New York: The New American Library, 1942.
+
*    Edith Hamilton. [[Mythology]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: The New [[American]] Library, 1942.
    Peter Harvey. An Introduction to Buddhism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
+
*    [[Peter Harvey]]. An Introduction to [[Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|Cambridge}}: {{Wiki|Cambridge}} {{Wiki|University}} Press, 1990.
    Maria~Ruth Hibbets. An Investigation into the Negative Dialectics of Nagarjuna and Candrakirti. Bachelor's Thesis, Reed College, 1991.
+
*    Maria~Ruth Hibbets. An [[Investigation]] into the Negative [[Dialectics]] of [[Nagarjuna]] and [[Candrakirti]]. Bachelor's {{Wiki|Thesis}}, Reed {{Wiki|College}}, 1991.
    M.~Hiriyanna. Outlines of Indian Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1967.
+
*    M.~Hiriyanna. Outlines of [[Indian Philosophy]]. {{Wiki|London}}: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1967.
    Nolan~Pliny Jacobsen. Understanding Buddhism. Carbondale, Illinois: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986.
+
*    Nolan~Pliny Jacobsen. [[Understanding]] [[Buddhism]]. Carbondale, Illinois: Southern Illinois {{Wiki|University}} Press, 1986.
    William James. The Varieties of Religious Experience. New York: The Modern Library, 1929.
+
*    {{Wiki|William James}}. The Varieties of [[Religious]] [[Experience]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: The {{Wiki|Modern}} Library, 1929.
    David~J. Kalupahana. Causality: The Central Philosophy of Buddhism. Honolulu: The University of Hawaii Press, 1975.
+
*    David~J. [[Kalupahana]]. [[Causality]]: The Central [[Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]]. Honolulu: The {{Wiki|University of Hawaii Press}}, 1975.
    David~J. Kalupahana. Buddhist Philosophy: A Historical Analysis. Honolulu: The University of Hawaii Press, 1976.
+
*    David~J. [[Kalupahana]]. [[Buddhist Philosophy]]: A Historical Analysis. Honolulu: The {{Wiki|University of Hawaii Press}}, 1976.
    David~J. Kalupahana. Nagarjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle Way: the Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna. New York: State University of New York Press, 1986.
+
*    David~J. [[Kalupahana]]. [[Nagarjuna]]: The [[Philosophy]] of the [[Middle Way]]: the [[Mulamadhyamakakarika]] of [[Nagarjuna]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: [[State]] {{Wiki|University}} of {{Wiki|New York}} Press, 1986.
    David~J. Kalupahana. A History of Buddhist Philosophy. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1992.
+
*    David~J. [[Kalupahana]]. A History of [[Buddhist Philosophy]]. Honolulu: {{Wiki|University of Hawaii Press}}, 1992.
    Michael~H. Kohn, trans. The Shambhala Dictionary of Buddhism and Zen. Boston: Shambhala, 1991.
+
*    Michael~H. Kohn, trans. The [[Shambhala]] {{Wiki|Dictionary}} of [[Buddhism]] and [[Zen]]. Boston: [[Shambhala]], 1991.
    Hermann Kulke and Deitmar Rothermund. A History of India. London: Routledge, 1990.
+
*    Hermann Kulke and Deitmar Rothermund. A History of [[India]]. {{Wiki|London}}: Routledge, 1990.
    Karen Lang, trans. aryadeva's Catuhsataka. Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag, 1986.
+
*    Karen Lang, trans. [[aryadeva's]] [[Catuhsataka]]. Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag, 1986.
    Chr. Lindtner. Nagarjuniana: Studies in the Writings and Philosophy of Nagarjuna. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987.
+
*    Chr. [[Lindtner]]. [[Nagarjuniana]]: Studies in the Writings and [[Philosophy]] of [[Nagarjuna]]. {{Wiki|Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1987.
    Donald~S. Lopez. A Study of Svatantrika. Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion Publications, 1987.
+
*    Donald~S. Lopez. A Study of [[Svatantrika]]. Ithaca, NY: Snow [[Lion]] Publications, 1987.
    Sir~Monier Monier-Williams. A Sanskrit-English Dictionary. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1993.
+
*    Sir~Monier {{Wiki|Monier-Williams}}. A Sanskrit-English {{Wiki|Dictionary}}. {{Wiki|Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1993.
    T.R.V. Murti. The Central Philosophy of Buddhism. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1960.
+
*    {{Wiki|T.R.V. Murti}}. The Central [[Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|London}}: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1960.
    Gadjin~M. Nagao. The Foundational Standpoint of Madhyamika Philosophy. New York: State University of New York Press, 1989.
+
*    Gadjin~M. [[Nagao]]. The Foundational Standpoint of [[Madhyamika]] [[Philosophy]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: [[State]] {{Wiki|University}} of {{Wiki|New York}} Press, 1989.
    Gadjin~M. Nagao. Madhyamika and Yogacara. New York: State University of New York Press, 1991.
+
*    Gadjin~M. [[Nagao]]. [[Madhyamika]] and [[Yogacara]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: [[State]] {{Wiki|University}} of {{Wiki|New York}} Press, 1991.
    Geoffrey Parrinder, ed. World Religions. New York: Facts on File Publications, 1983.
+
*    Geoffrey Parrinder, ed. [[World]] [[Religions]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Facts on File Publications, 1983.
    Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan. Indian Philosophy, volume I. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1929.
+
*    [[Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan]]. [[Indian Philosophy]], volume I. {{Wiki|London}}: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1929.
    Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan and Charles Moore. A Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957.
+
*    [[Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan]] and Charles Moore. A Sourcebook in [[Indian Philosophy]]. Princeton: {{Wiki|Princeton University}} Press, 1957.
    Walpola~Sri Rahula. What the Buddha Taught. New York: Grove Press, 1959.
+
*    Walpola~Sri [[Rahula]]. What the [[Buddha]] [[Taught]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Grove Press, 1959.
    Regington Rajapakse ``Buddhism as Religion and Philosophy''. Religion. 1986.
+
*    Regington Rajapakse ``[[Buddhism]] as [[Religion]] and [[Philosophy]]''. [[Religion]]. 1986.
    Bhagwan~Shree Rajneesh, trans. Edward Conze. The Diamond Sutra. Poona, India: Ma Yoga Laxmi Rajneesh Foundation, 1979.
+
*    Bhagwan~Shree Rajneesh, trans. [[Edward Conze]]. The [[Diamond Sutra]]. Poona, [[India]]: Ma [[Yoga]] [[Laxmi]] Rajneesh Foundation, 1979.
    K.~Venkata Ramana. Nagarjuna's Philosophy. Rutland, Vermont: Charles E. Tuttle Company, 1966.
+
*    K.~Venkata [[Ramana]]. [[Nagarjuna's]] [[Philosophy]]. Rutland, Vermont: Charles E. Tuttle Company, 1966.
    Paul Reps. Zen Flesh, Zen Bones. Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, (no impress date).
+
*    Paul Reps. [[Zen]] Flesh, [[Zen]] Bones. [[Garden]] City, {{Wiki|New York}}: Anchor [[Books]], (no impress date).
    T.W. Rhys-Davids, ed. and trans. Buddhist Suttas. New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1969.
+
*    T.W. Rhys-Davids, ed. and trans. [[Buddhist]] [[Suttas]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Dover Publications, Inc., 1969.
    Richard~H. Robinson. Early Madhyamika in India and China. Madison, Wisconsin: The University of Wisconsin Press, 1967.
+
*    Richard~H. [[Robinson]]. Early [[Madhyamika]] in [[India]] and [[China]]. Madison, Wisconsin: The {{Wiki|University of Wisconsin}} Press, 1967.
    Peter~Della Santina. Madhyamaka Schools in India. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1986.
+
*    Peter~Della Santina. [[Madhyamaka]] Schools in [[India]]. {{Wiki|Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1986.
    Ninian Smart. The Philosophy of Religion. New York: Random House, 1970.
+
*    Ninian [[Smart]]. The [[Philosophy]] of [[Religion]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Random House, 1970.
    Huston Smith. The World's Religions. San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1991.
+
*    Huston Smith. The World's [[Religions]]. {{Wiki|San Francisco}}: Harper Collins, 1991.
    David Snellgrove. Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. Boston: Shambhala, 1987.
+
*    {{Wiki|David Snellgrove}}. Indo-Tibetan [[Buddhism]]. Boston: [[Shambhala]], 1987.
    Mervyn Sprung. Lucid Exposition of the Middle Way: The Essential Chapters of the Prasannapada of Candrakirti. Boulder: Prajna Press, 1979.
+
*    Mervyn Sprung. Lucid [[Exposition]] of the [[Middle Way]]: The [[Essential]] Chapters of the [[Prasannapada]] of [[Candrakirti]]. Boulder: [[Prajna]] Press, 1979.
    Theodore Stcherbatsky. The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana. London: Mouton & Co, 1965.
+
*    [[Wikipedia:Fyodor Shcherbatskoy|Theodore Stcherbatsky]]. The {{Wiki|Conception}} of [[Buddhist]] [[Nirvana]]. {{Wiki|London}}: Mouton & Co, 1965.
    Frederick Streng. Emptiness: A Study in Religious Meaning. Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1967.
+
*    Frederick Streng. [[Emptiness]]: A Study in [[Religious]] Meaning. Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1967.
    D.T. Suzuki. Outlines of Mahayana Buddhism. New York: Schocken Books, 1967. Shunryu Suzuki. Zen Mind, Beginner's Mind. New York: Weatherhill, 1983.
+
*    [[D.T. Suzuki]]. Outlines of [[Mahayana]] [[Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Schocken [[Books]], 1967. [[Shunryu Suzuki]]. [[Zen]] [[Mind]], Beginner's [[Mind]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Weatherhill, 1983.
    Malaclypse the Younger. Principia Discordia. Port Townsend, WA: Loompanics Unlimited, (no impress date).
+
*    Malaclypse the Younger. Principia Discordia. Port Townsend, WA: Loompanics [[Unlimited]], (no impress date).
    Frank Thilly. A History of Philosophy. New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1951.
+
*    Frank Thilly. A History of [[Philosophy]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Henry Holt and Company, 1951.
    L.~Austin Waddell. Tibetan Buddhism. New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1972.
+
*    L.~Austin [[Wikipedia:Laurence Waddell|Waddell]]. [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Dover Publications, Inc., 1972.
    A.~K. Warder. Indian Buddhism. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1980.
+
*    A.~K. Warder. [[Indian Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1980.
    Henry~Clarke Warren, ed. and trans. Buddhism in Translations. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987.
+
*    Henry~Clarke Warren, ed. and trans. [[Buddhism]] in Translations. {{Wiki|Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1987.
    Paul Williams. Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. London: Routledge, 1989.
+
*    [[Paul Williams]]. [[Mahayana]] [[Buddhism]]: The [[Doctrinal]] Foundations. {{Wiki|London}}: Routledge, 1989.
    Kajiyama Yuichi. Madhyamika. The Encyclopedia of Religion, 1987.
+
*    Kajiyama Yuichi. [[Madhyamika]]. The {{Wiki|Encyclopedia}} of [[Religion]], 1987.
        The whole of Nagarjuna's philosophy is dependent upon convention, for it all presupposes the perception of everyday things and their phenomenal reality. It is vital that one following his philosophy understand that it, every bit as much as the things it describes, is relative.
+
 
 +
The whole of [[Nagarjuna's]] [[philosophy]] is [[dependent upon]] convention, for it all presupposes the [[perception]] of everyday things and their [[phenomenal]] [[reality]]. It is [[vital]] that one following his [[philosophy]] understand that it, every bit as much as the things it describes, is [[relative]].
  
  

Latest revision as of 15:50, 30 January 2016

Black-3d40.jpg

As with any subject, much more could be said about Madhyamika, and often has been. Candrakirti's commentary, for example, runs to many hundreds of pages. This thesis, too, far exceeds the normal length of bachelor's theses. In light of Nagarjuna's teaching that excessive theorizing is one of the main causes of suffering and bondage, it may seem that lengthy commentary is self- negating. This objection would be quite valid, were the intent of these research projects to express truth and the nature of reality. However, as exemplified in the Introduction, were that the intent of these works, they likely would have said no more than "this flax weighs three pounds." (SHOWING THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTS) The purpose of the philosophy of Madhyamika, with its stress on emptiness, is not to discard all theorizing. Rather, the point is to demonstrate that theories are not ultimately valid. Ascribing excessive validity to the products of thought will cause one to grasp onto them and lose sight of the true nature of things, which is empty. The truest conceptual expression of reality will always be a paradox. "A saint (bodhisattva) is a saint because there is no saint," says the Perfection of Wisdom school, "and that is why there is a saint!"

Note: quoted in Nagao 1989, vii

Concepts are applicable in the conventional sphere only. This is the place of commentary and research: such projects can clarify the nature of the phenomenal world and discuss the relative validity of various theories within that plane. Neither the Buddha nor Nagarjuna would have said that the rational faculty has no function, for, though no theory is absolutely true, some theories are certainly better than others.

When one wishes to speak of the ultimate sphere, thoughts can point the way towards a proper understanding of it and teach one how to achieve the Perfect Wisdom which can perceive it, but theories themselves cannot express its nature. (A CONCEPT / A DUALITY / A SKILFUL MEAN) As a conventional truth, the Madhyamika philosophy propounds a system of ordering one's thought, and then it shows where such thought must end. This system includes

the theory of dependent arising,
the four Noble Truths,
the constitution of the {{Wiki|psychophysical]] personality,
and the Noble Eightfold Path;
the theory of emptiness points out the limit of the mental faculty.

Nagarjuna demonstrates that all of his ideas are pragmatic only in one of the most famous verses of his treatise:

"We state that whatever is dependent arising, that is emptiness.
That is dependent upon convention.
That itself is the middle path."
Note: karika XXIV.18
Bu a.jpg

This verse succinctly ties together his entire philosophy, shows where it comes to an end, and defines the point of it all. Nagarjuna's thought can be summed up in the first two terms of the verse: dependent arising and emptiness. From these all other elements of his philosophy are derived. Dependent arising explains all aspects of the relative world, for it details the process of causation and, hence, the ontology of the world. Emptiness is the only possible description of ultimate truth, for it demonstrates relativity and provides a sort of anti-theory on which the rational faculty can focus.

Neither of these, though, should be relied on as valid in themselves, for they are both "dependent upon convention."

Note: The original of this latter phrase, sa prajnaptir upadaya, is a famously difficult one to translate. For example, Nagao renders it "a designation based upon (some material)," Ramana as "derived name," and Sprung as "a guiding, not a cognitive, notion, presupposing the everyday." Kalupahana's translation was used here because, while not necessarily more accurate than any others, it is clearer and more succinct.

Any theory, even one as all-encompassing as emptiness, is still a theory based on convention.
Were there no dependently arisen things, there would be no theory of dependent arising.
Further, even though these things are empty, they are at least phenomenally real; if they were not, there would be no theory of emptiness, for there would be nothing on which to base it.

Heinrich Zimmer. Philosophies of India. New York: Meridian Books, 1957

Dependent arising and emptiness are relative to each other, and both are relative to the perceived world. They thus constitute a middle path.
One must remember that dependent arising would be no more proper a description of ultimate truth than emptiness, and vice-versa, else either materialism or nihilism would result.
Likewise, one must find a middle ground between theorizing and refraining from doing so.

The philosophy of Madhyamika is of vital importance, for it explains reality and points the way to an escape from it. Were one to accept no philosophy, the mental faculties would be ungrounded and directionless. On the other hand, one must remember the proper place of philosophies as based on convention only; they have no final validity. This, Nagarjuna says, is the middle path of the Buddha. (INDESCRIPTIBLE) Perhaps the most important thing demonstrated by the equation Nagarjuna presents in the above verse is that the Madhyamika philosophy is, in its essence, very simple. "Independently realized, peaceful, unobsessed by obsessions, without discriminations and a variety of meaning: such is the characteristic of truth," he says. [Note: karika XVIII.9 ] The one clear perception underlying Madhyamika is the interconnectedness and complete dependence of all things. Becoming and being, past and future, reality and emptiness, subject and object, arising and ceasing are all real things, but only in relation to each other. None exist absolutely. Unfortunately, this insight, while utterly simple and clear, is not so easily explained. The function of language and concepts is to make distinctions and impose artificial boundaries. The very word "define" has in its roots the connotation of creating boundaries (de + finis). The Buddha and Nagarjuna had no choice but to explain their insight into the nature of reality in philosophical terms, formulas, and theories. Nagarjuna's brilliance lay in his ability to explain it so clearly, and then to build such effective safeguards against excessive philosophizing into his system. Ultimately, the one thing that is of importance is the Buddha's three-faceted teaching of transitoriness, soullessness, and suffering, the goal of which teaching being freedom. Only in light of this can Buddhism and Nagarjuna's enterprise be understood correctly. Rejecting all conceptual extremes and advocating a middle path is not an exercise in philosophy, but an aid to help people escape suffering and become free. The Visuddhimagga expresses poetically but succinctly the reality that remains when the Buddha's teachings are truly understood:

"Misery only doth exist, none miserable,
No doer is there; naught save the deed is found.
Nirvana is, but not the man who seeks it.
The Path exists, but not the traveler on it."
Note: Visuddhimagga, quoted in Warren, 146
C.jpga6e7114e.jpg

Epilogue

This research project was not merely an academic exercise. I would like to address briefly what I consider to be the importance of Madhyamika to our modern world, Occidental or otherwise. To my knowledge, there has never been in recorded history a philosophical system so exhaustively apophatic as Nagarjuna's that was not also a nihilism. Even Zen, the champion of paradox, is not really either apophatic or a system. I have defended the value of Madhyamika within the Buddhist tradition as being a defense of and an explanation of the twin doctrines of soullessness and transitoriness, the purpose of which being an aid to escape suffering. Outside the Buddhist tradition the importance of Madhyamika is slightly different, for it is not likely that the Western undercurrents of essentialism could easily be unseated — -nor would I want to.

One value of this philosophy for the West lies in its potential to undercut the habits of "I-making" and grasping, both grasping onto the things of the world and grasping onto the products of rationality.

Another value is the contribution Madhyamika could make to Western philosophy and theology.

Many of the structures of the modern world are based, in some way or other, on distrust of individual authority. For example, that which has become American democracy is rooted in a party system. The hope is that, if two or more parties compete for election and for legislation, then compromises will emerge in the long run, and no individual will have too much power. The method on which science is based is founded on a similar safeguard. One can never prove, but only disprove. Third, the quest for objectivity underlying all academia certainly betrays this distrust. There is a strong emphasis on removing all personal reference from research and attempting to make it uninfluenced by any personal emotions or prejudices. These safeguards are necessary components of the structures we have. However, it is not certain that these structures are the only option. The Buddha's teachings demonstrate that, in a way, emphasis on the self is the root of all evil. It is an excessive "self-ishness" that causes one to desire passionately, to assert forcefully one's opinions and thoughts, to want to be right, to desire to possess. "Self-ishness" is that which, in whatever situation, causes one to seek one's own well-being and ignore the thoughts and needs of others. The Buddha's path, especially as enunciated so radically by Nagarjuna, subverts this "I-making." I do not know what the result would be if the doctrine of soullessness were introduced into our systems of politics, science, and academia, but my suspicion is that the results would be beneficial. The other importance of Nagarjuna's agenda for me is the impact it could have on our rational structures of philosophy and theology. There are many discerning thinkers in these fields whose philosophies are in no way simplistic, but there are far too few. A study of Madhyamika philosophy has not forced me to abandon my belief in concepts like God, the soul, and the afterlife. What it has done is shown me, if I am to retain those beliefs, of what they may and may not consist. Nagarjuna's teaching of emptiness can vastly deepen and enrich one's religious and philosophical notions. Further, his teachings can demonstrate to what extent those notions are self-created and, thus, which notions may be true, which false, and which merely helpful guides that must ultimately be abandoned. The philosophies of the Buddha and Nagarjuna offer trenchant explanations of the constitution of reality, the function of the human mind, and the purpose to which an individual's life and, in some cases, academic career should be devoted. A study of Madhyamika, if approached with a receptive attitude, will complement any philosophy, no matter how antithetical.

BuddhaToBe.jpg

Bibliography

The whole of Nagarjuna's philosophy is dependent upon convention, for it all presupposes the perception of everyday things and their phenomenal reality. It is vital that one following his philosophy understand that it, every bit as much as the things it describes, is relative.

Source

bahai-library.com