Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "The Paradox of Causality in Mādhyamika By David Loy"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
m (1 revision: Robo text replace 30 sept)
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
[[File:Ess.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Ess.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
THE PROBLEM of [[causality]] is central to all schools of [[Buddhism]], and this is especially true of [[Mādhyamika]]. But at first glance there seems to be a contradiction in the [[Mādhyamika]] analysis. On the one hand, [[causal]] [[interdependence]] is clearly a crucial {{Wiki|concept}}, so important that [[Nāgārjuna]] identifies it with the most important {{Wiki|concept}}, [[śunyatā]]: "We interpret the [[dependent arising]] of all things ([[pratītyasamutpāda]]) as the absence of [[being]] in them ([[śunyatā]])." [1] This emphasis on [[interdependence]] develops to completion the early [[Buddhist doctrine]] of [[impermanence]]: there are no [[unconditioned]] [[elements]] of [[existence]] ([[dharmas]]), for all things arise and pass away according to [[conditions]]. The undeniable relativity of everything is the means by which self-existence ([[svabhāva]]) is refuted.
+
THE PROBLEM of [[causality]] is central to all schools of [[Buddhism]], and this is especially true of [[Mādhyamika]]. But at first glance there seems to be a {{Wiki|contradiction}} in the [[Mādhyamika]] analysis. On the one hand, [[causal]] [[interdependence]] is clearly a crucial {{Wiki|concept}}, so important that [[Nāgārjuna]] identifies it with the most important {{Wiki|concept}}, [[śunyatā]]: "We interpret the [[dependent arising]] of all things ([[pratītyasamutpāda]]) as the absence of [[being]] in them ([[śunyatā]])." [1] This {{Wiki|emphasis}} on [[interdependence]] develops to completion the early [[Buddhist doctrine]] of [[impermanence]]: there are no [[unconditioned]] [[elements]] of [[existence]] ([[dharmas]]), for all things arise and pass away according to [[conditions]]. The undeniable [[relativity]] of everything is the means by which self-existence ([[svabhāva]]) is refuted.
  
   At the same [[time]], [[Nāgārjuna]] redefines [[pratītyasamutpāda]] in such a way as to negate [[causality]] altogether. This is apparent even in the prefatory [[dedication]] of the Mūlamādhyamikakārikās, in the eight negations which [[Nāgārjuna]] attributes to the [[Buddha]]:
+
   At the same [[time]], [[Nāgārjuna]] redefines [[pratītyasamutpāda]] in such a way as to negate [[causality]] altogether. This is apparent even in the prefatory [[dedication]] of the Mūlamādhyamikakārikās, in the [[eight negations]] which [[Nāgārjuna]] [[attributes]] to the [[Buddha]]:
  
Neither perishing nor arising in [[time]],
+
Neither perishing nor [[arising]] in [[time]],
  
 
         neither terminable nor [[eternal]],
 
         neither terminable nor [[eternal]],
Line 15: Line 15:
 
Such [[pratītyasamutpāda]].. . .[2]
 
Such [[pratītyasamutpāda]].. . .[2]
  
Consistent with this, the first and most important chapter of the Kārikās concludes that the [[causal]] relation is inexplicable, and later chapters go further to claim that [[causation]] is like [[māyā]]. "Origination, [[existence]], and [[destruction]] are of the nature of [[māyā]], [[dreams]], or a fairy castle." [3] The last chapters seize on this issue as one way to crystallize the [[difference]] between [[saṁsāra]] and [[nirvāna]]. The [[nirvāna]] chapter distinguishes between them by attributing [[causal]] relations only to [[saṁsāra]]: "That which, taken as [[causal]] or dependent, is the process of [[being]] born and passing on, is, taken non-causally and beyond all dependence, declared to be [[nirvāna]]." [4] In his commentary on the previous chapter, [[Candrakirti]] defines saṁvṛti and [[duḥkha]] in the same way: ". . .to be reciprocally dependent in [[existence]], that is, for things to be based on
+
Consistent with this, the first and most important [[chapter]] of the [[Kārikās]] concludes that the [[causal]] [[relation]] is inexplicable, and later chapters go further to claim that [[causation]] is like [[māyā]]. "Origination, [[existence]], and [[destruction]] are of the [[nature]] of [[māyā]], [[dreams]], or a fairy castle." [3] The last chapters seize on this issue as one way to crystallize the [[difference]] between [[saṁsāra]] and [[nirvāna]]. The [[nirvāna]] [[chapter]] distinguishes between them by attributing [[causal]] relations only to [[saṁsāra]]: "That which, taken as [[causal]] or dependent, is the process of [[being]] born and passing on, is, taken non-causally and beyond all [[dependence]], declared to be [[nirvāna]]." [4] In his commentary on the previous [[chapter]], [[Candrakirti]] defines saṁvṛti and [[duḥkha]] in the same way: ". . .to be reciprocally dependent in [[existence]], that is, for things to be based on
  
 
[[File:F1qz6.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:F1qz6.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
[1] Mūlamādhyamikakārikās (hereafter "MMK') XXIV 18, in Lucid Exposition of the [[Middle Way]]: The [[Essential]] Chapters from [he Prasannapada of andrakirti, trans. Mervyn Sprung (Boulder: [[Prajña]] Press, 1979), p. 238. This identification must be kept in [[mind]] to avoid Śaṅkara's error of misinterpreting sunyaia as non-being and making [[Mādhyamika]] into a [[nihilism]].
+
[1] Mūlamādhyamikakārikās (hereafter "MMK') XXIV 18, in Lucid [[Exposition]] of the [[Middle Way]]: The [[Essential]] Chapters from [he [[Prasannapada]] of andrakirti, trans. Mervyn Sprung (Boulder: [[Prajña]] Press, 1979), p. 238. This identification must be kept in [[mind]] to avoid [[Śaṅkara's]] error of misinterpreting sunyaia as [[non-being]] and making [[Mādhyamika]] into a [[nihilism]].
  
 
[2] I bid., pp. 32-33, 35. For [[pratītyasamutpāda]] Sprung gives "the true way of things."
 
[2] I bid., pp. 32-33, 35. For [[pratītyasamutpāda]] Sprung gives "the true way of things."
  
[3] MMK VII 34, as quoted in T. R. V. Murti, The Central [[Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]] ({{Wiki|London}}: Allen and Unwin, 1960), p. 177.
+
[3] MMK VII 34, as quoted in T. R. V. [[Murti]], The Central [[Philosophy]] of [[Buddhism]] ({{Wiki|London}}: Allen and Unwin, 1960), p. 177.
  
[4] MMK XXV 9, in Sprung, p. 255. In my opinion this is the most important verse in the Kārikās.
+
[4] MMK XXV 9, in Sprung, p. 255. In my opinion this is the most important verse in the [[Kārikās]].
  
 
  p64
 
  p64
  
each other in utter reciprocity, is saṁvṛti." ". . it is precisely what arises in dependence that constitutes [[duḥkha]], not what does not arise in dependence." [5]
+
each other in utter reciprocity, is saṁvṛti." ". . it is precisely what arises in [[dependence]] that constitutes [[duḥkha]], not what does not arise in [[dependence]]." [5]
  
How are we to understand this obvious contradiction? That is, how do we get from interpreting [[pratītyasamutpāda]] as "[[dependent origination]]" to "non-dependent non-origination," and, what is more, reconcile the two? Explanations which differentiate between two different types of [[sutras]] ([[exoteric]] [[neyārtha]] and [[esoteric]] [[nītārtha]]), or which refer to the two-truths {{Wiki|theory}}, just raise the same question in a different [[form]], for we need to know how such contradictory [[truths]] can both be true, i.e., how these two are related to each other.
+
How are we to understand this obvious {{Wiki|contradiction}}? That is, how do we get from interpreting [[pratītyasamutpāda]] as "[[dependent origination]]" to "non-dependent [[non-origination]]," and, what is more, reconcile the two? Explanations which differentiate between two different types of [[sutras]] ([[exoteric]] [[neyārtha]] and [[esoteric]] [[nītārtha]]), or which refer to the two-truths {{Wiki|theory}}, just raise the same question in a different [[form]], for we need to know how such [[contradictory]] [[truths]] can both be true, i.e., how these two are related to each other.
  
     This paper will offer one way (perhaps not the only way) of resolving this problem, which may more properly be said to be a [[paradox]]. I shall argue that complete conditionality is phenomenologically equivalent to a denial of all [[causal]] [[conditions]]. That is, a [[view]] which is so radical as to analyze things away into "their" [[conditions]] is [[offering]] an interpretation of [[experience]] which becomes indistinguishable from a [[view]] that negates [[causality]] altogether. If this is true, we have another instance where it becomes very difficult to distinguish the [[Mādhyamika]] [[nonduality]] from that of Śaṅkara's {{Wiki|Advaita Vedānta}}. [6] The argument will be made in two steps. We shall see that there is a [[dialectic]] inherent in the [[Mādhyamika]] analysis. The first stage (discussed in Part I) is apparent: looking at the {{Wiki|common-sense}} distinction between things and their [[cause-and-effect]] relationships, [[Nāgārjuna]] uses the latter to "dissolve" the former and deny that there are things. Less obvious is the second stage (Part II), which reverses the analysis: as we shall see, the lack of "thingness" in things implies a way of experiencing in which there is no [[awareness]] of [[cause and effect]]. Things and their [[causal]] relations stand and fall together, because our notion of [[cause-and-effect]] is dependent on that of things, which [[cause]] and are affected. If one collapses, so does the other. The basic problem is that any [[dualism]] between them is untenable. It is the delusive bifurcation between them that [[Nāgārjuna]] is concerned to negate, and the two ways to do this are to use each pole to "deconstruct" the other. Consistent with the general [[Mādhyamika]] project, this is {{Wiki|criticism}} without affirming any [[philosophical]] position: having conflated the [[duality]], [[Nāgārjuna]] does not offer any [[view]] about [[causality]], because [[nothing]] remains to be related to anything else. Part III compares this conclusion with the Advaitic position regarding [[causality]].
+
     This paper will offer one way (perhaps not the only way) of resolving this problem, which may more properly be said to be a [[paradox]]. I shall argue that complete [[conditionality]] is phenomenologically {{Wiki|equivalent}} to a {{Wiki|denial}} of all [[causal]] [[conditions]]. That is, a [[view]] which is so radical as to analyze things away into "their" [[conditions]] is [[offering]] an [[interpretation]] of [[experience]] which becomes indistinguishable from a [[view]] that negates [[causality]] altogether. If this is true, we have another instance where it becomes very difficult to distinguish the [[Mādhyamika]] [[nonduality]] from that of [[Śaṅkara's]] {{Wiki|Advaita Vedānta}}. [6] The argument will be made in two steps. We shall see that there is a [[dialectic]] [[inherent]] in the [[Mādhyamika]] analysis. The first stage (discussed in Part I) is apparent: looking at the {{Wiki|common-sense}} {{Wiki|distinction}} between things and their [[cause-and-effect]] relationships, [[Nāgārjuna]] uses the [[latter]] to "dissolve" the former and deny that there are things. Less obvious is the second stage (Part II), which reverses the analysis: as we shall see, the lack of "thingness" in things implies a way of experiencing in which there is no [[awareness]] of [[cause and effect]]. Things and their [[causal]] relations stand and fall together, because our notion of [[cause-and-effect]] is dependent on that of things, which [[cause]] and are affected. If one collapses, so does the other. The basic problem is that any [[dualism]] between them is untenable. It is the delusive [[bifurcation]] between them that [[Nāgārjuna]] is concerned to negate, and the two ways to do this are to use each pole to "deconstruct" the other. Consistent with the general [[Mādhyamika]] project, this is {{Wiki|criticism}} without [[affirming]] any [[philosophical]] position: having conflated the [[duality]], [[Nāgārjuna]] does not offer any [[view]] about [[causality]], because [[nothing]] remains to be related to anything else. Part III compares this conclusion with the [[Advaitic]] position regarding [[causality]].
  
 
I
 
I
 
[[File:Gns.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Gns.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
   In [[order]] to understand the [[Mādhyamika]] critique, we must begin with a clear [[sense]] of what it is that is [[being]] criticized. This is our {{Wiki|common-sense}} understanding of the [[world]], which sees it as a collection of discrete entities (including myself) interacting [[causally]] "in" {{Wiki|space and time}}. Just as {{Wiki|space and time}}, if they are to [[function]] as "containers," require something understood as nonspatial and nontemporal to "contain," so the [[causal]] relation is normally used to explain the interaction between things which
+
   In [[order]] to understand the [[Mādhyamika]] critique, we must begin with a clear [[sense]] of what it is that is [[being]] criticized. This is our {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[understanding]] of the [[world]], which sees it as a collection of discrete entities (including myself) interacting [[causally]] "in" {{Wiki|space and time}}. Just as {{Wiki|space and time}}, if they are to [[function]] as "containers," require something understood as nonspatial and nontemporal to "contain," so the [[causal]] [[relation]] is normally used to explain the interaction between things which
  
 
[5] Sprung,pp. 230, 236.
 
[5] Sprung,pp. 230, 236.
  
[6] I have argued for this equivalence in two other papers. "[[Enlightenment in Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Advaita Vedanta}}: Are [[Nirvāna]] and [[Moksha]] the Same?" International [[Philosophical]] Quarterly, 22 (1982), 65-74, claims that the [[no-self]] modal-view of [[Buddhism]] is indistinguishable from the all-Self substance-view of [[Advaita]]. See my paper "The [[Mahayana]] Deconstruction of [[Time]]" (unpublished) which maintains that the [[nonduality]] between things and [[time]] amounts to making the same claim regarding temporality: if there is only [[time]], this is phenemenologically equivalent to a nunc stans ("[[eternal]] now").
+
[6] I have argued for this equivalence in two other papers. "[[Enlightenment in Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Advaita Vedanta}}: Are [[Nirvāna]] and [[Moksha]] the Same?" International [[Philosophical]] Quarterly, 22 (1982), 65-74, claims that the [[no-self]] modal-view of [[Buddhism]] is indistinguishable from the all-Self substance-view of [[Advaita]]. See my paper "The [[Mahayana]] Deconstruction of [[Time]]" (unpublished) which maintains that the [[nonduality]] between things and [[time]] amounts to making the same claim regarding temporality: if there is only [[time]], this is phenemenologically {{Wiki|equivalent}} to a nunc stans ("[[eternal]] now").
  
  
Line 47: Line 47:
 
p65
 
p65
  
are distinct from each other. [[Nāgārjuna]] attacks more than the [[philosophical]] fancies of [[Indian]] metaphysicians, for there is a [[metaphysics]] inherent in our {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[view]]. This {{Wiki|common-sense}} understanding (one or the other aspect of which is absolutized in systematic [[metaphysics]]) is what makes the everyday [[world]] saṁsara for us, and it is this saṁsara that [[Nāgārjuna]] is concerned to "deconstruct." This is why one must beware of making [[Mādhyamika]] into an "ordinary [[language]]" [[philosophy]] by interpreting [[śunyatā]] merely as a "meta-system" term denying a correspondence {{Wiki|theory}} of [[truth]]. By no means does the end of [[philosophical]] language-games "leave everything as it is" for [[Nāgārjuna]], except in the [[sense]] that saṁsara has always really been [[nirvāṇa]].
+
are {{Wiki|distinct}} from each other. [[Nāgārjuna]] attacks more than the [[philosophical]] fancies of [[Indian]] {{Wiki|metaphysicians}}, for there is a [[metaphysics]] [[inherent]] in our {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[view]]. This {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[understanding]] (one or the other aspect of which is absolutized in systematic [[metaphysics]]) is what makes the everyday [[world]] [[saṁsara]] for us, and it is this [[saṁsara]] that [[Nāgārjuna]] is concerned to "deconstruct." This is why one must beware of making [[Mādhyamika]] into an "ordinary [[language]]" [[philosophy]] by interpreting [[śunyatā]] merely as a "meta-system" term denying a [[correspondence]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[truth]]. By no means does the end of [[philosophical]] language-games "leave everything as it is" for [[Nāgārjuna]], except in the [[sense]] that [[saṁsara]] has always really been [[nirvāṇa]].
 
[[File:Gold.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Gold.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
     Why do we [[experience]] the [[world]] as saṁsara, if that is delusive? Why don't we [[experience]] it as it is? The [[traditional]] [[Buddhist]] answer points to [[craving]] and [[ignorance]], but [[Nāgārjuna]] focuses on a particular type of [[mental]] [[attachment]], that which makes all other [[attachment]] possible: [[prapañca]]. The [[nirvāṇa]] chapter of the Kārikās concludes by characterizing [[nirvāṇa]], negatively, as "the coming to rest of all ways of taking things, the [[repose]] of named things (prapañcopaśama)The precise meaning of [[prapañca]] is, unfortunately, unclear. Sprung defines it as "the [[world]] of named things; the [[visible]] manifold." [8] It refers to some {{Wiki|indeterminate}} "interface" between our concepts and our [[perceptions]]: that our categories of [[thinking]] are somehow responsible for our perceiving "the [[visible]] [[world]]" as "manifold." The consequence of [[prapañca]] is that I now perceive the room I am [[writing]] in, not as it really is, nondually, but as a collection of [[books]] and chair and pens and paper. . .and me, each of which is in some {{Wiki|naive}} fashion taken to (1) be distinct from the others and (2) persist unchanged unless affected by something else.[9]
+
     Why do we [[experience]] the [[world]] as [[saṁsara]], if that is delusive? Why don't we [[experience]] it as it is? The [[traditional]] [[Buddhist]] answer points to [[craving]] and [[ignorance]], but [[Nāgārjuna]] focuses on a particular type of [[mental]] [[attachment]], that which makes all other [[attachment]] possible: [[prapañca]]. The [[nirvāṇa]] [[chapter]] of the [[Kārikās]] concludes by characterizing [[nirvāṇa]], negatively, as "the coming to rest of all ways of taking things, the [[repose]] of named things (prapañcopaśama)The precise meaning of [[prapañca]] is, unfortunately, unclear. Sprung defines it as "the [[world]] of named things; the [[visible]] manifold." [8] It refers to some {{Wiki|indeterminate}} "interface" between our [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] and our [[perceptions]]: that our categories of [[thinking]] are somehow responsible for our perceiving "the [[visible]] [[world]]" as "manifold." The consequence of [[prapañca]] is that I now {{Wiki|perceive}} the room I am [[writing]] in, not as it really is, nondually, but as a collection of [[books]] and chair and pens and paper. . .and me, each of which is in some {{Wiki|naive}} fashion taken to (1) be {{Wiki|distinct}} from the others and (2) persist unchanged unless affected by something else.[9]
  
This point about [[prapañca]] is important because without it one might conclude that [[Nāgārjuna's]] critique of self-existence ([[svabhāva]]) is a refutation of something that no one believes in anyway. But one does not escape his critique by defining entities in a more {{Wiki|common-sense}} fashion as coming-into and passing-out-of [[existence]]. There is no tenable middle ground between self-existence independent of all conditions—an [[empty]] set, for there are no such entities—and the complete conditionality of [[śunyatā]]. The implication of [[Nāgārjuna's]] arguments against self-existence (e.g., MMK chapters I, XV) is to point out the inconsistency in our everyday way of "taking" the [[world]]: we accept that things change, and at the same [[time]] we assume that somehow they also remain the same—which is necessary if there are to be "things" at all. Other [[philosophers]], recognizing this inconsistency, have tried to solve it by absolutizing one of these at the expense of the other; so the satkāryavāda substance-view of {{Wiki|Samkhya}} emphasizes permanence at the price of not being able to account for change, and the asatkāryavāda modal-view of [[early Buddhism]] has the opposite problem of not being able to account for continuity. [[Nāgārjuna]] arranges these and the other solutions that have been proposed into a "[[tetralemma]]" which exhausts the possible [[philosophical]] alternatives; then he proceeds to refute them all. The basic difficulty is that any understanding of [[cause and effect]] which tries to relate two separate things together can be reduced to the contradiction of both asserting and denying identity. Nor can one respond to this simply by denying [[causality]], for that is likewise contradicted by our [[experience]]. So [[Nāgārjuna]] concludes that the "relationship" between [[cause and effect]] is incomprehensible.
+
This point about [[prapañca]] is important because without it one might conclude that [[Nāgārjuna's]] critique of self-existence ([[svabhāva]]) is a refutation of something that no one believes in anyway. But one does not escape his critique by defining entities in a more {{Wiki|common-sense}} fashion as coming-into and passing-out-of [[existence]]. There is no tenable middle ground between self-existence {{Wiki|independent}} of all conditions—an [[empty]] set, for there are no such entities—and the complete [[conditionality]] of [[śunyatā]]. The implication of [[Nāgārjuna's]] arguments against self-existence (e.g., MMK chapters I, XV) is to point out the inconsistency in our everyday way of "taking" the [[world]]: we accept that things change, and at the same [[time]] we assume that somehow they also remain the same—which is necessary if there are to be "things" at all. Other [[philosophers]], [[recognizing]] this inconsistency, have tried to solve it by absolutizing one of these at the expense of the other; so the satkāryavāda substance-view of {{Wiki|Samkhya}} emphasizes [[permanence]] at the price of not being able to account for change, and the asatkāryavāda modal-view of [[early Buddhism]] has the opposite problem of not being able to account for continuity. [[Nāgārjuna]] arranges these and the other solutions that have been proposed into a "[[tetralemma]]" which exhausts the possible [[philosophical]] alternatives; then he proceeds to refute them all. The basic difficulty is that any [[understanding]] of [[cause and effect]] which tries to relate two separate things together can be reduced to the {{Wiki|contradiction}} of both asserting and denying [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]. Nor can one respond to this simply by denying [[causality]], for that is likewise contradicted by our [[experience]]. So [[Nāgārjuna]] concludes that the "relationship" between [[cause and effect]] is incomprehensible.
 
[[File:Goldenbuddha.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Goldenbuddha.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[7]''MMKXXV 24, in Sprung p. 264.
 
[7]''MMKXXV 24, in Sprung p. 264.
Line 57: Line 57:
 
[8]"Ibid., p. 273.
 
[8]"Ibid., p. 273.
  
[9] The role of [[prapañca]] in our [[experience]] cannot be fully understood without relating it to our intentions. The relations among [[craving]], [[conceptualizing]], and [[causality]] have been discussed in "The [[Difference]] between saṁsara and [[Nirvāṇa]]," [[Philosophy]] East and West, 33 (1983), 355-365.
+
[9] The role of [[prapañca]] in our [[experience]] cannot be fully understood without relating it to our {{Wiki|intentions}}. The relations among [[craving]], [[conceptualizing]], and [[causality]] have been discussed in "The [[Difference]] between [[saṁsara]] and [[Nirvāṇa]]," [[Philosophy]] [[East]] and [[West]], 33 (1983), 355-365.
  
 
p66
 
p66
  
     But the problem is not resolved simply by criticizing such positions, for the difficulty is fundamentally not abstract and [[philosophical]] but very personal: it is our [[lives]], not just our theories, which are inconsistent in "taking" the [[world]] as a collection of discrete "self-existing" things which yet change. Although during, a [[philosophy]] seminar I may accept the complete conditionality and contingency of all [[experience]], as soon as the seminar ends I {{Wiki|unconsciously}} assume that the colleague I join for lunch is the same [[person]] whom I spoke with before the seminar—although ever-so-slightly different, due to a relatively extraneous change of mood, etc. This constitutes saṁsara because it is by reifying such "thingness" out of the flux of [[experience]] that we become attached to things. (Of course, other hypostatizations of self-existence— my wife, my car and, most of all, myself—tend to be more problematic loci for [[attachment]], but the problem is the same in each case: we [[cling]] to things which dissolve as we try to [[grasp]] them.)
+
     But the problem is not resolved simply by criticizing such positions, for the difficulty is fundamentally not abstract and [[philosophical]] but very personal: it is our [[lives]], not just our theories, which are inconsistent in "taking" the [[world]] as a collection of discrete "[[self-existing]]" things which yet change. Although during, a [[philosophy]] seminar I may accept the complete [[conditionality]] and contingency of all [[experience]], as soon as the seminar ends I {{Wiki|unconsciously}} assume that the colleague I join for lunch is the same [[person]] whom I spoke with before the seminar—although ever-so-slightly different, due to a relatively extraneous change of [[mood]], etc. This constitutes [[saṁsara]] because it is by reifying such "thingness" out of the flux of [[experience]] that we become [[attached]] to things. (Of course, other hypostatizations of self-existence— my wife, my car and, most of all, myself—tend to be more problematic loci for [[attachment]], but the problem is the same in each case: we [[cling]] to things which dissolve as we try to [[grasp]] them.)
  
     It does not suffice to answer this Humean critique of identity [10] with an "ordinary [[language]]" rejoinder that we should become more sensitive to the ways we use our permanence-and-change vocabulary, for the [[Mādhyamika]] position is that our usual everyday [[experience]] is deluded and this ordinary use of [[language]] is deluding. As the first prong of his attack, [[Nāgārjuna]] refutes our {{Wiki|common-sense}} distinction between things and their [[causal]] relations simply by sharpening the distinction to absurdity: if things are to be "self-existent" then they must be separable from their [[conditions]], but their [[existence]] is clearly contingent upon the [[conditions]] that bring them into [[being]] and eventually (when those [[conditions]] no longer operate) [[cause]] them to disappear. If it is objected that one cannot [[live]] without reifying such fictitious entities, at least to some extent, then the [[Mādhyamika]] response is to agree. The "lower [[truth]]", saṁvṛti, is not negated altogether—it is a truth—but it must not be taken as "the higher [[truth]]," as a correct understanding of the way things really are.
+
     It does not suffice to answer this Humean critique of [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] [10] with an "ordinary [[language]]" rejoinder that we should become more [[sensitive]] to the ways we use our permanence-and-change vocabulary, for the [[Mādhyamika]] position is that our usual everyday [[experience]] is deluded and this ordinary use of [[language]] is deluding. As the first prong of his attack, [[Nāgārjuna]] refutes our {{Wiki|common-sense}} {{Wiki|distinction}} between things and their [[causal]] relations simply by sharpening the {{Wiki|distinction}} to absurdity: if things are to be "[[self-existent]]" then they must be separable from their [[conditions]], but their [[existence]] is clearly contingent upon the [[conditions]] that bring them into [[being]] and eventually (when those [[conditions]] no longer operate) [[cause]] them to disappear. If it is objected that one cannot [[live]] without reifying such fictitious entities, at least to some extent, then the [[Mādhyamika]] response is to agree. The "lower [[truth]]", saṁvṛti, is not negated altogether—it is a truth—but it must not be taken as "the higher [[truth]]," as a correct [[understanding]] of [[the way things really are]].
 
[[File:GoldenChild JadeOne.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:GoldenChild JadeOne.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
     So the first stage of the [[Mādhyamika]] critique uses the complete [[interdependence]] of all things to refute their "thingness." The distinction between things and their [[causal]] relations is negated by adopting the latter as a means to "deconstruct" the former. This completes the early [[Buddhist]] attack on [[substance]]. But this absolutizing of [[conditions]] is only the first step. Now the critique dialectically reverses to use the perspective of the deconstructed thing in [[order]] to deny the [[reality]] of [[causal]] [[conditions]]. In the delusive bifurcation between things and their [[causal]] relations, the category of [[causality]] turns out to be just as dependent on things as things are on their [[causal]] [[conditions]]. Our {{Wiki|concept}} of [[causality]] presupposes a set of discrete entities, whose interrelation we explain as [[causation]]. Cause-and-effect requires something to [[cause]] and something to be effected. If this is so, then a complete conditionality which is so radical that it "dissolves" all things must also dissolve itself.
+
     So the first stage of the [[Mādhyamika]] critique uses the complete [[interdependence]] of all things to refute their "thingness." The {{Wiki|distinction}} between things and their [[causal]] relations is negated by adopting the [[latter]] as a means to "deconstruct" the former. This completes the early [[Buddhist]] attack on [[substance]]. But this absolutizing of [[conditions]] is only the first step. Now the critique dialectically reverses to use the {{Wiki|perspective}} of the deconstructed thing in [[order]] to deny the [[reality]] of [[causal]] [[conditions]]. In the delusive [[bifurcation]] between things and their [[causal]] relations, the category of [[causality]] turns out to be just as dependent on things as things are on their [[causal]] [[conditions]]. Our {{Wiki|concept}} of [[causality]] presupposes a set of discrete entities, whose interrelation we explain as [[causation]]. [[Cause-and-effect]] requires something to [[cause]] and something to be effected. If this is so, then a complete [[conditionality]] which is so radical that it "dissolves" all things must also dissolve itself.
  
       In [[order]] to make this point, it is helpful to transpose the argument from the too-general category of [[causal]] [[conditions]] to the more specific one of motion-and-rest. [[Nāgārjuna]] analyzes motion and rest in chapter two of the Kārikās, immediately after his initial treatment of [[conditions]], and it is clear that the second chapter is meant to apply the general {{Wiki|conclusions}} of chapter one to a particular case. The additional advantage of shifting to motion-and-rest is that we [[illuminate]] what is otherwise a very puzzling chapter. The basic problem is that it is not clear what [[Nāgārjuna]] is actually doing in chapter two. Like Zeno, he denies the [[reality]] of motion, but this is not done
+
       In [[order]] to make this point, it is helpful to transpose the argument from the too-general category of [[causal]] [[conditions]] to the more specific one of motion-and-rest. [[Nāgārjuna]] analyzes {{Wiki|motion}} and rest in [[chapter]] two of the [[Kārikās]], immediately after his initial treatment of [[conditions]], and it is clear that the second [[chapter]] is meant to apply the general {{Wiki|conclusions}} of [[chapter]] one to a particular case. The additional advantage of shifting to motion-and-rest is that we [[illuminate]] what is otherwise a very puzzling [[chapter]]. The basic problem is that it is not clear what [[Nāgārjuna]] is actually doing in [[chapter]] two. Like Zeno, he denies the [[reality]] of {{Wiki|motion}}, but this is not done
  
[10] See Hume's Enquiry Concerning [[Human]] Understanding, Section IV, Parts I and II.
+
[10] See [[Hume's]] Enquiry Concerning [[Human]] [[Understanding]], Section IV, Parts I and II.
  
 
p67
 
p67
  
to assert an [[unchanging]] Parmenidean "block-universe," for {{Wiki|Vedantic}} permanence (i.e., "rest") is also denied. As a result, [[Nāgārjuna]] has been criticized for an arid play on words which "resembles the shell game" in [[being]] a [[logical]] sleight-of-hand" [11]— that is, for basing his argument on a subtle distinction between words which are meaningless because they have no [[empirical]] referent—and for committing the [[fallacy]] of composition in arguing that what is true for the parts (in this case, traversed, traversing, and to-be-traversed) must be true for the whole. [12] But I think such criticisms miss the point of [[Nāgārjuna's]] arguments. Their import is that our usual way of understanding motion, which distinguishes the "mover" from "the act of moving," simply does not make [[sense]], because the [[interdependence]] of "mover" and "motion" shows that the {{Wiki|hypostatization}} of either is delusive. (Here "mover" means, not "that which [[causes]] motion", but "that thing which moves"; and "motion" is "the movement that happens to the thing") [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[logic]] in [[stanzas]] two through eleven demonstrates that once we have reified a distinction between them, it becomes impossible to relate them back together again—a quandary familiar to students of the Western {{Wiki|mind-body problem}}, which is the result of another reified bifurcation. The difficulty is shown by isolating this hypostatized mover and inquiring into its status. [[Nāgārjuna]] asks: In itself, is it a mover, or not? That is, is the predicate "moves" intrinsic to this mover, or contingent? The dilemma is that neither way of understanding the situation is satisfactory. If the "mover" in and of itself already moves, then there is no need to add an "act of motion" later; the predication of such a "second motion" would be redundant. But the other alternative—that the "mover" by itself is a non-mover—does not work either because we cannot thereafter add the predicate: it is a contradiction for a non-mover to move. In neither way can we make [[sense]] out of the relation between them. It follows that the "mover" cannot have an [[existence]] of its own apart from the "moving," which means that our usual [[dualistic]] way of understanding motion is untenable. To summarize this in contemporary terms, [[Nāgārjuna]] is pointing out a flaw in the everyday [[language]] we use to describe (and hence our ways of [[thinking]] about) motion: our ascription of motion predicates to substantive [[objects]] is unintelligible.
+
to assert an [[unchanging]] [[Wikipedia:Parmenides|Parmenidean]] "block-universe," for {{Wiki|Vedantic}} [[permanence]] (i.e., "rest") is also denied. As a result, [[Nāgārjuna]] has been criticized for an arid play on words which "resembles the shell game" in [[being]] a [[logical]] sleight-of-hand" [11]— that is, for basing his argument on a {{Wiki|subtle}} {{Wiki|distinction}} between words which are meaningless because they have no [[empirical]] referent—and for committing the [[fallacy]] of composition in arguing that what is true for the parts (in this case, traversed, traversing, and to-be-traversed) must be true for the whole. [12] But I think such {{Wiki|criticisms}} miss the point of [[Nāgārjuna's]] arguments. Their import is that our usual way of [[understanding]] {{Wiki|motion}}, which distinguishes the "mover" from "the act of moving," simply does not make [[sense]], because the [[interdependence]] of "mover" and "{{Wiki|motion}}" shows that the {{Wiki|hypostatization}} of either is delusive. (Here "mover" means, not "that which [[causes]] {{Wiki|motion}}", but "that thing which moves"; and "{{Wiki|motion}}" is "the {{Wiki|movement}} that happens to the thing") [[Nāgārjuna's]] [[logic]] in [[stanzas]] two through eleven demonstrates that once we have reified a {{Wiki|distinction}} between them, it becomes impossible to relate them back together again—a quandary familiar to students of the [[Western]] {{Wiki|mind-body problem}}, which is the result of another reified [[bifurcation]]. The difficulty is shown by isolating this [[Wikipedia:Hypostasis (philosophy and religion)|hypostatized]] mover and inquiring into its {{Wiki|status}}. [[Nāgārjuna]] asks: In itself, is it a mover, or not? That is, is the predicate "moves" intrinsic to this mover, or contingent? The {{Wiki|dilemma}} is that neither way of [[understanding]] the situation is satisfactory. If the "mover" in and of itself already moves, then there is no need to add an "act of {{Wiki|motion}}" later; the predication of such a "second {{Wiki|motion}}" would be redundant. But the other alternative—that the "mover" by itself is a non-mover—does not work either because we cannot thereafter add the predicate: it is a {{Wiki|contradiction}} for a non-mover to move. In neither way can we make [[sense]] out of the [[relation]] between them. It follows that the "mover" cannot have an [[existence]] of its [[own]] apart from the "moving," which means that our usual [[dualistic]] way of [[understanding]] {{Wiki|motion}} is untenable. To summarize this in contemporary terms, [[Nāgārjuna]] is pointing out a flaw in the everyday [[language]] we use to describe (and hence our ways of [[thinking]] about) {{Wiki|motion}}: our ascription of {{Wiki|motion}} predicates to substantive [[objects]] is unintelligible.
 
[[File:Graph2.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Graph2.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
     At first encounter the above argument may be unconvincing. The options seem so extreme that we suspect there must be some middle ground between them. Of course we can't accept a double movement, but is it really a contradiction for a non-mover to move? What else could move? But, again, no such appeal to our everyday intuitions, or to the ordinary [[language]] which shapes and [[embodies]] them, is successful against the [[Mādhyamika]] critique of those intuitions, which seizes on the inconsistency that is ignored (and to some extent must be ignored) in daily [[life]]. We can elaborate upon this by applying the [[logic]] that was used earlier to deconstruct the [[difference]] between things and their [[causal]] relations. Just as (general rule) complete [[interdependence]] dissolves the thing into its [[rational]] [[conditions]], with no residue of [[substance]] remaining, so (specific case) the [[completeness]] of movement—the fact that no part of "me" stays unmoved in the chair when "I" go to lunch—means that no self-existing and hence [[unchanging]] "thing" remains to move. As with [[time]] and with [[space]], we think of the relation between mover and moving with the {{Wiki|metaphor}} of container and contained, and in all three instances the bifurcation is delusive. In [[order]] to expose the absurdity of this, [[Nāgārjuna]] needs only to sharpen the dichotomy. Despite our intuitions, which
+
     At first encounter the above argument may be unconvincing. The options seem so extreme that we suspect there must be some middle ground between them. Of course we can't accept a double {{Wiki|movement}}, but is it really a {{Wiki|contradiction}} for a non-mover to move? What else could move? But, again, no such appeal to our everyday intuitions, or to the ordinary [[language]] which shapes and [[embodies]] them, is successful against the [[Mādhyamika]] critique of those intuitions, which seizes on the inconsistency that is ignored (and to some extent must be ignored) in daily [[life]]. We can elaborate upon this by applying the [[logic]] that was used earlier to deconstruct the [[difference]] between things and their [[causal]] relations. Just as (general {{Wiki|rule}}) complete [[interdependence]] dissolves the thing into its [[rational]] [[conditions]], with no residue of [[substance]] remaining, so (specific case) the [[completeness]] of movement—the fact that no part of "me" stays unmoved in the chair when "I" go to lunch—means that no [[self-existing]] and hence [[unchanging]] "thing" remains to move. As with [[time]] and with [[space]], we think of the [[relation]] between mover and moving with the {{Wiki|metaphor}} of container and contained, and in all three instances the [[bifurcation]] is delusive. In [[order]] to expose the absurdity of this, [[Nāgārjuna]] needs only to sharpen the {{Wiki|dichotomy}}. Despite our intuitions, which
  
[11] "Richard Robinson, "Did [[Nāgārjuna]] Really Refute All [[Philosophical]] [[Views]]?" [[Philosophy]] East and West, 22 (1972), 325.
+
[11] "Richard Robinson, "Did [[Nāgārjuna]] Really Refute All [[Philosophical]] [[Views]]?" [[Philosophy]] [[East]] and [[West]], 22 (1972), 325.
  
[12] Hsueh-li Cheng, "Motion and Rest in the Middle Treatise," J. of [[Chinese Philosophy]], 1 (1980) 235 ff.
+
[12] Hsueh-li Cheng, "{{Wiki|Motion}} and Rest in the [[Middle Treatise]]," J. of [[Chinese Philosophy]], 1 (1980) 235 ff.
  
  
Line 85: Line 85:
 
p68
 
p68
  
inconsistently want to postulate some "[[unchanging]] core" in [[order]] to save the mover, there is no middle ground between a self-existent and hence unmoving thing, and the complete [[dissolution]] of the thing that does the moving. Understood in this way, it becomes obvious why his arguments also work just as well against the intelligibility of rest: the bifurcation between the thing and its [[being]] at rest is just as delusive, and for precisely the same [[reason]].
+
inconsistently want to postulate some "[[unchanging]] core" in [[order]] to save the mover, there is no middle ground between a [[self-existent]] and hence unmoving thing, and the complete [[dissolution]] of the thing that does the moving. Understood in this way, it becomes obvious why his arguments also work just as well against the intelligibility of rest: the [[bifurcation]] between the thing and its [[being]] at rest is just as delusive, and for precisely the same [[reason]].
 
[[File:Great Departure.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Great Departure.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
II
 
II
  
So far, we have effected only the first stage of the [[dialectic]], both in the general analysis of [[causal]] [[conditions]] and this more specific case of motion-and-rest. We have dissolved the thing which moves / is [[caused]] and are left with a changing [[world]] of [[causal]] [[conditions]]. The second stage of the [[dialectic]] is easy to state but harder to understand: granted, if there is only movement, then there is no mover; but if there is [[nothing]] to move, then likewise there can be no movement. Implicit in our {{Wiki|concept}} of change is the notion that a thing is becoming other than it was, so unless one reifies something self-existent (cf. atemporal) in [[order]] to provide continuity between these different [[conditioned]] (temporal) states, there is [[nothing]] outside the changing [[conditions]] to be changed. The {{Wiki|concept}} of change (here a general term to include both conditionality and movement) needs something to "bite" on, but the first stage of the [[dialectic]] leaves [[nothing]] [[unconditioned]] to chew. If the colleague I join for lunch is not in any [[sense]] the same [[person]] I spoke with earlier, because there is no [[substratum]] of permanence to "him," then it makes no [[sense]] to say that "he" has changed. Without a contained, there can be no container; as the bifurcation dissolves, the poles conflate into a whole which, as [[Nāgārjuna]] knew, cannot be represented but remains {{Wiki|philosophically}} {{Wiki|indeterminate}}, since [[language]], in [[order]] to describe at all, must dualize between [[subject]] and predicate, mover and moved, [[cause and effect]].
+
So far, we have effected only the first stage of the [[dialectic]], both in the general analysis of [[causal]] [[conditions]] and this more specific case of motion-and-rest. We have dissolved the thing which moves / is [[caused]] and are left with a changing [[world]] of [[causal]] [[conditions]]. The second stage of the [[dialectic]] is easy to [[state]] but harder to understand: granted, if there is only {{Wiki|movement}}, then there is no mover; but if there is [[nothing]] to move, then likewise there can be no {{Wiki|movement}}. Implicit in our {{Wiki|concept}} of change is the notion that a thing is becoming other than it was, so unless one reifies something [[self-existent]] (cf. atemporal) in [[order]] to provide continuity between these different [[conditioned]] ({{Wiki|temporal}}) states, there is [[nothing]] outside the changing [[conditions]] to be changed. The {{Wiki|concept}} of change (here a general term to include both [[conditionality]] and {{Wiki|movement}}) needs something to "bite" on, but the first stage of the [[dialectic]] leaves [[nothing]] [[unconditioned]] to chew. If the colleague I join for lunch is not in any [[sense]] the same [[person]] I spoke with earlier, because there is no [[substratum]] of [[permanence]] to "him," then it makes no [[sense]] to say that "he" has changed. Without a contained, there can be no container; as the [[bifurcation]] dissolves, the poles conflate into a whole which, as [[Nāgārjuna]] knew, cannot be represented but remains {{Wiki|philosophically}} {{Wiki|indeterminate}}, since [[language]], in [[order]] to describe at all, must dualize between [[subject]] and predicate, mover and moved, [[cause and effect]].
  
       But nonetheless, unless we can get a [[sense]] of what such a way of experiencing would be like, the above argument will be at best {{Wiki|philosophically}} {{Wiki|persuasive}} yet will seem irrelevant to daily [[life]]. What consequences does all this have for the way we actually [[experience]] the [[world]]? In particular, it is still unclear how, except by some "[[logical]] sleight of hand," all-conditionality can be phenomenologically identified with no-conditionality, as we claimed at the beginning of this paper.
+
       But nonetheless, unless we can get a [[sense]] of what such a way of experiencing would be like, the above argument will be at best {{Wiki|philosophically}} {{Wiki|persuasive}} yet will seem irrelevant to daily [[life]]. What {{Wiki|consequences}} does all this have for the way we actually [[experience]] the [[world]]? In particular, it is still unclear how, except by some "[[logical]] sleight of hand," all-conditionality can be phenomenologically identified with no-conditionality, as we claimed at the beginning of this paper.
  
     Let me try to satisfy these questions with the help of a well-known [[Ch'an]] ([[Zen]]) story.[13] The following example discusses the [[causal]] relations of a [[physical]] [[action]], but what is said may be applied just as well to sense-perception (e.g., to the [[nondual]] [[sound]] of a pebble striking {{Wiki|bamboo}}, which [[awakened]] Hsiang-yen, or to the [[nondual]] [[pain]] when Yün-mên broke his ankle) and to [[thought]] (Hui Neng: "If we allow our [[thoughts]], past, present and future, to link up in a series, we put ourselves under re­straint. On the other hand, if we never let our [[mind]] attach to anything, we shall gain [[liberation]].").
+
     Let me try to satisfy these questions with the help of a well-known [[Ch'an]] ([[Zen]]) story.[13] The following example discusses the [[causal]] relations of a [[physical]] [[action]], but what is said may be applied just as well to [[sense-perception]] (e.g., to the [[nondual]] [[sound]] of a pebble striking {{Wiki|bamboo}}, which [[awakened]] Hsiang-yen, or to the [[nondual]] [[pain]] when Yün-mên broke his ankle) and to [[thought]] ([[Hui Neng]]: "If we allow our [[thoughts]], {{Wiki|past}}, {{Wiki|present}} and {{Wiki|future}}, to link up in a series, we put ourselves under re­straint. On the other hand, if we never let our [[mind]] attach to anything, we shall gain [[liberation]].").
 
[[File:Guides.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Guides.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
     Lin-chi was a [[monk]] in the [[monastery]] of Huang-po. Three times Lin-chi asked the [[Master]]: "What is the real meaning of [[Bodhidharma]] coming from the West?" and each [[time]] Huang-po immediately struck him. Thereupon, discouraged, he decided to leave
+
     [[Lin-chi]] was a [[monk]] in the [[monastery]] of [[Huang-po]]. Three times [[Lin-chi]] asked the [[Master]]: "What is the real meaning of [[Bodhidharma]] coming from the [[West]]?" and each [[time]] [[Huang-po]] immediately struck him. Thereupon, discouraged, he decided to leave
  
[13]The direct relevance of [[Ch'an]] [[experience]] to this issue cannot be questioned. While it is true that [[Ch'an]] is not. and does not have, any [[philosophy]], yet it is also the case that [[Mādhyamika]], as a [[philosophical]] exposition of the Prajñāparamīta, may be said to be the [[philosophy]] that most made [[Ch'an]] possible.
+
[13]The direct relevance of [[Ch'an]] [[experience]] to this issue cannot be questioned. While it is true that [[Ch'an]] is not. and does not have, any [[philosophy]], yet it is also the case that [[Mādhyamika]], as a [[philosophical]] [[exposition]] of the Prajñāparamīta, may be said to be the [[philosophy]] that most made [[Ch'an]] possible.
  
 
p69
 
p69
  
and was advised to go to [[Master]] Ta-yü. Arriving at his [[monastery]], Lin-chi told Ta-yü of his encounters with Huang-po, adding that he didn't [[know]] where he was at fault.
+
and was advised to go to [[Master]] Ta-yü. Arriving at his [[monastery]], [[Lin-chi]] told Ta-yü of his encounters with [[Huang-po]], adding that he didn't [[know]] where he was at fault.
  
       [[Master]] Ta-yü exclaimed; "Your [[master]] treated you entirely with grandmotherly [[kindness]], and yet you say you don't [[know]] your fault." [[Hearing]] this, Lin-chi was suddenly [[awakened]] and said; "After all, there isn't much in Huang-po's [[Buddhism]]!" [14]
+
       [[Master]] Ta-yü exclaimed; "Your [[master]] treated you entirely with grandmotherly [[kindness]], and yet you say you don't [[know]] your fault." [[Hearing]] this, [[Lin-chi]] was suddenly [[awakened]] and said; "After all, there isn't much in Huang-po's [[Buddhism]]!" [14]
  
       What did Lin-chi realize that [[awakened]] him? If (rushing in where [[Ch'an]] [[masters]] will not tread) we distort his [[experience]] into an [[idea]] in [[order]] to gloss this story, we may say that Lin-chi must have [[realized]] that Huang-po had been answering his question. The blows he received were not punishment but a demonstration of why [[Bodhidharma]] came from the West. On the {{Wiki|common-sense}} level, the answer to Lin-chi's question is obvious: [[Bodhidharma]] was bringing [[Buddhism]] to [[China]]. But this is a [[relative]], "lower [[truth]]" explanation. As a standard [[Ch'an]] question designed to initiate a dialogue, it goes without saying that what is sought is the "higher [[truth]]," and on this level there is no "why." For the [[enlightened]] [[person]], each [[experience]] is complete in itself, the only thing in the whole [[universe]]; for each [[action]] is [[tathata]]. [[Nothing]] changes because without prapañca-reification everything is [[perceived]] afresh, for the first [[time]]. As [[Bodhidharma]] walked from [[India]] there was no [[thought]] of "why" in his head; "he" was each step. In the same way, there was no "why" to Huang-po's blows; "he" was that spontaneous, unselfconscious [[action]]. Lin-chi's sudden [[realization]] of this overflowed into his exclamation: "So, there isn't much to [[Buddhism]] after all!" (Only "just 'this'!") Upon returning to Huang-po, he revealed the depth of his understanding—more than just an [[intellectual]] insight—by not hesitating to give Huang-po a dose of his own [[medicine]].
+
       What did [[Lin-chi]] realize that [[awakened]] him? If (rushing in where [[Ch'an]] [[masters]] will not tread) we distort his [[experience]] into an [[idea]] in [[order]] to gloss this story, we may say that [[Lin-chi]] must have [[realized]] that [[Huang-po]] had been answering his question. The blows he received were not {{Wiki|punishment}} but a demonstration of why [[Bodhidharma]] came from the [[West]]. On the {{Wiki|common-sense}} level, the answer to Lin-chi's question is obvious: [[Bodhidharma]] was bringing [[Buddhism]] to [[China]]. But this is a [[relative]], "lower [[truth]]" explanation. As a standard [[Ch'an]] question designed to initiate a {{Wiki|dialogue}}, it goes without saying that what is sought is the "higher [[truth]]," and on this level there is no "why." For the [[enlightened]] [[person]], each [[experience]] is complete in itself, the only thing in the whole [[universe]]; for each [[action]] is [[tathata]]. [[Nothing]] changes because without prapañca-reification everything is [[perceived]] afresh, for the first [[time]]. As [[Bodhidharma]] walked from [[India]] there was no [[thought]] of "why" in his head; "he" was each step. In the same way, there was no "why" to Huang-po's blows; "he" was that spontaneous, unselfconscious [[action]]. Lin-chi's sudden [[realization]] of this overflowed into his exclamation: "So, there isn't much to [[Buddhism]] after all!" (Only "just 'this'!") Upon returning to [[Huang-po]], he revealed the depth of his understanding—more than just an [[intellectual]] insight—by not hesitating to give [[Huang-po]] a dose of his [[own]] [[medicine]].
 
[[File:H1qh.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:H1qh.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
       The [[paradox]] which makes the above story relevant to this paper is the fact that, at the same [[time]], Bodhidharma's and Huang-po's [[actions]] are intentional. Huang-po's blow may be immediate and spontaneous, but there is also a "[[reason]]" for it; it is not a random or irrelevant gesture, but a very appropriate response to that particular question, drawn forth by that situation. If we translate this point about {{Wiki|intention}} back into our more general category of [[causality]], here we have a case of an act which is both completely [[caused]] (perfect [[upāya]]: glove fitting hand tightly, to use the [[Ch'an]] analogy) and yet is also uncaused. This [[paradox]] is a contradiction only according to our usual understanding of [[causality]], which uses that category-of-thought to relate together the supposedly discrete [[objects]] into which [[prapañca]] carves the [[world]]. The first and most important of these hypostatized "things" is me, the subject who craves some of these [[objects]] and thus needs an understanding of [[cause-and-effect]] relationships in [[order]] to manipulate circumstances and obtain them. (It has been argued that the [[desire]] for such manipulation is the very [[root]] of our {{Wiki|concept}} of [[causality]]. [15] ) This would apply to the story in question if Huang-po, prapañca-deluded, were to perceive Lin-chi dualistically: Lin-chi is sitting there, a person-object that needs to be [[enlightened]], and I,
+
       The [[paradox]] which makes the above story relevant to this paper is the fact that, at the same [[time]], [[Bodhidharma's]] and Huang-po's [[actions]] are intentional. Huang-po's blow may be immediate and spontaneous, but there is also a "[[reason]]" for it; it is not a random or irrelevant gesture, but a very appropriate response to that particular question, drawn forth by that situation. If we translate this point about {{Wiki|intention}} back into our more general category of [[causality]], here we have a case of an act which is both completely [[caused]] ({{Wiki|perfect}} [[upāya]]: glove fitting hand tightly, to use the [[Ch'an]] analogy) and yet is also uncaused. This [[paradox]] is a {{Wiki|contradiction}} only according to our usual [[understanding]] of [[causality]], which uses that category-of-thought to relate together the supposedly discrete [[objects]] into which [[prapañca]] carves the [[world]]. The first and most important of these [[Wikipedia:Hypostasis (philosophy and religion)|hypostatized]] "things" is me, the [[subject]] who craves some of these [[objects]] and thus needs an [[understanding]] of [[cause-and-effect]] relationships in [[order]] to {{Wiki|manipulate}} circumstances and obtain them. (It has been argued that the [[desire]] for such manipulation is the very [[root]] of our {{Wiki|concept}} of [[causality]]. [15] ) This would apply to the story in question if [[Huang-po]], prapañca-deluded, were to {{Wiki|perceive}} [[Lin-chi]] [[dualistically]]: [[Lin-chi]] is sitting there, a person-object that needs to be [[enlightened]], and I,
  
[14] This version of the story, from the [[Transmission]] of the [[Lamp]], is given in Chang Chung-yuan, Original Teachings of [[Ch'an]] [[Buddhism]] ({{Wiki|New York}}; Vintage, 1971), pp. 116-17.
+
[14] This version of the story, from the [[Transmission]] of the [[Lamp]], is given in [[Chang]] Chung-yuan, Original Teachings of [[Ch'an]] [[Buddhism]] ({{Wiki|New York}}; Vintage, 1971), pp. 116-17.
  
[15] The [[idea]] of [[cause]] has its [[roots]] in purposive [[activity]] and is employed in the first instance when we are concerned to produce or to prevent something. To discover the [[cause]] of something is to discover what has to be attested by our [[activity]] in [[order]] to produce or to prevent that thing; but once the [[word]] '[[cause]]' comes to be applied to natural events, the notion of altering the course of events lends to be dropped. '[[Cause]]' is then used in a nonpractical, purely diagnostic way in cases where we have no interest in altering events or [[power]] to alter them." (P. H. Nowell-Smith, "[[Causality]] or [[Causation]]." I have a cyclostyled copy of this article but have not been able to trace its source.)
+
[15] The [[idea]] of [[cause]] has its [[roots]] in purposive [[activity]] and is employed in the first instance when we are concerned to produce or to prevent something. To discover the [[cause]] of something is to discover what has to be attested by our [[activity]] in [[order]] to produce or to prevent that thing; but once the [[word]] '[[cause]]' comes to be applied to natural events, the notion of altering the course of events lends to be dropped. '[[Cause]]' is then used in a nonpractical, purely {{Wiki|diagnostic}} way in cases where we have no [[interest]] in altering events or [[power]] to alter them." (P. H. Nowell-Smith, "[[Causality]] or [[Causation]]." I have a cyclostyled copy of this article but have not been able to trace its source.)
  
 
p70
 
p70
  
Huang-po sitting here, am the [[person]] who will try to [[enlighten]] him. Then "my" blow is reified into a deliberated effect which I hope will [[cause]] Lin-chi's [[awakening]].
+
[[Huang-po]] sitting here, am the [[person]] who will try to [[enlighten]] him. Then "my" blow is reified into a deliberated effect which I {{Wiki|hope}} will [[cause]] Lin-chi's [[awakening]].
 
[[File:Ha1r.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Ha1r.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
       But if, as all schools of [[Buddhism]] agree, there is no [[self]] to do this causal-relating-between-things, then the above understanding of the situation must be delusive. So Huang-po must have [[experienced]] it differently, and [[causality]] too must be under­stood differently. It is not denied: on the contrary, without the [[sense]] of [[self]] and other [[prapañca]]- reified [[objects]] as a counterfoil, it expands to include everything, as Nagar-juna has already shown. (So the [[doctrine]] of [[karma]] can be understood simply by applying something like Newton's third law of [[physical]] motion to the [[mental]] [[realm]] as well.) From the perspective of Mādhyamika's "all-conditionality" which deconstructs all things, Huang-po's blow is part of a seamless web of [[conditions]] which can be extended, as Hwa Yen does, to encompass the entire [[universe]]. As one [[jewel]] in the [[infinite]] web of lndra, the blow reflects everything everywhere, at all times. But if every event that happens is interdependent with everything else in the whole [[universe]], what a different way of experiencing this involves! It suggests a Spinozistic acceptance of whatever happens, as a product of the whole, but more than this it implies the irrelevance of [[causality]] as usually understood. "All-conditionality," in its complete {{Wiki|negation}} of anything to be attached to, offers no practical utility, because there is no longer any [[object]] to be obtained or any [[self]] that craves it; whereas a [[self]] that wants to obtain some thing will need to isolate some discrete [[object]] or [[action]] as the [[cause]] which leads to obtaining it.
+
       But if, as all schools of [[Buddhism]] agree, there is no [[self]] to do this causal-relating-between-things, then the above [[understanding]] of the situation must be delusive. So [[Huang-po]] must have [[experienced]] it differently, and [[causality]] too must be under­stood differently. It is not denied: on the contrary, without the [[sense]] of [[self]] and other [[prapañca]]- reified [[objects]] as a counterfoil, it expands to include everything, as Nagar-juna has already shown. (So the [[doctrine]] of [[karma]] can be understood simply by applying something like Newton's third law of [[physical]] {{Wiki|motion}} to the [[mental]] [[realm]] as well.) From the {{Wiki|perspective}} of [[Mādhyamika's]] "all-conditionality" which deconstructs all things, Huang-po's blow is part of a seamless web of [[conditions]] which can be extended, as [[Hwa Yen]] does, to encompass the entire [[universe]]. As one [[jewel]] in the [[infinite]] web of lndra, the blow reflects everything everywhere, at all times. But if every event that happens is [[interdependent]] with everything else in the whole [[universe]], what a different way of experiencing this involves! It suggests a Spinozistic [[acceptance]] of whatever happens, as a product of the whole, but more than this it implies the irrelevance of [[causality]] as usually understood. "All-conditionality," in its complete {{Wiki|negation}} of anything to be [[attached]] to, offers no {{Wiki|practical}} utility, because there is no longer any [[object]] to be obtained or any [[self]] that craves it; whereas a [[self]] that wants to obtain some thing will need to isolate some discrete [[object]] or [[action]] as the [[cause]] which leads to obtaining it.
  
       What does all this imply about the way Huang-po [[experienced]] his own [[action]]? Because he did not perceive the situation dualistically, the [[action]] was not "his." That the blow was appropriate to the situation was not due to any prior {{Wiki|deliberation}}, however quick. On the contrary, the [[action]] was so appropriate precisely because it was not deliberated, just as the best responses in "dharma-combat" are unmediated by any self-conscious "[[hindrance]] in the [[mind]]." Then why did Huang-po strike, rather than shout "ho!" as Ma-tsu often did, or utter a few soft words, as Chao-chou probably would have done? This is the crucial point: He does not [[know]] and cannot [[know]]. ("Not-knowing is very profound" said [[Master]] Lo-han, precipitating Wên-i's [[awakening]].) His spontaneous [[actions]] are traceless, "like the tracks of a bird in the sky." [16] They respond to a situation like a glove fits on a hand because whatever "decisions are made" (if this phrase can be used here) are not made by him. If one nondualistically is the [[cause]] (or effect, or both), rather than [[being]] a hypostatized [[self]] that dualistically uses it, then there is not the [[awareness]] that it is a [[cause]] (or effect, or both);  it is [[experienced]] as whole, complete, and "traceless." In this way there turn out to be only two alternatives: either [[cause-and-effect]] relationships between discrete prapañca-objects, manipulated by the prapañca-subject, or [[nondual]] "all-conditionality" which amounts to an [[experience]] of complete [[unconditioned]] freedom. Without the interference that the [[self]] creates, Indra's all-encompassing web of [[causal]] [[conditions]] is indeed seamless. In [[psychological]] terms, the barrier between [[consciousness]] ("[[ego]]") and subconsciousness dissolves ("the bottom falls out of the bucket") and thereafter [[thoughts]] and [[actions]] are [[experienced]] as welling-up nondually from a source
+
       What does all this imply about the way [[Huang-po]] [[experienced]] his [[own]] [[action]]? Because he did not {{Wiki|perceive}} the situation [[dualistically]], the [[action]] was not "his." That the blow was appropriate to the situation was not due to any prior {{Wiki|deliberation}}, however quick. On the contrary, the [[action]] was so appropriate precisely because it was not deliberated, just as the best responses in "dharma-combat" are unmediated by any self-conscious "[[hindrance]] in the [[mind]]." Then why did [[Huang-po]] strike, rather than shout "ho!" as [[Ma-tsu]] often did, or utter a few soft words, as [[Chao-chou]] probably would have done? This is the crucial point: He does not [[know]] and cannot [[know]]. ("Not-knowing is very profound" said [[Master]] Lo-han, precipitating Wên-i's [[awakening]].) His spontaneous [[actions]] are traceless, "like the tracks of a bird in the sky." [16] They respond to a situation like a glove fits on a hand because whatever "decisions are made" (if this [[phrase]] can be used here) are not made by him. If one nondualistically is the [[cause]] (or effect, or both), rather than [[being]] a [[Wikipedia:Hypostasis (philosophy and religion)|hypostatized]] [[self]] that [[dualistically]] uses it, then there is not the [[awareness]] that it is a [[cause]] (or effect, or both);  it is [[experienced]] as whole, complete, and "traceless." In this way there turn out to be only two alternatives: either [[cause-and-effect]] relationships between discrete prapañca-objects, manipulated by the prapañca-subject, or [[nondual]] "all-conditionality" which amounts to an [[experience]] of complete [[unconditioned]] freedom. Without the interference that the [[self]] creates, [[Indra's]] all-encompassing web of [[causal]] [[conditions]] is indeed seamless. In [[psychological]] terms, the barrier between [[consciousness]] ("[[ego]]") and [[subconsciousness]] dissolves ("the bottom falls out of the bucket") and thereafter [[thoughts]] and [[actions]] are [[experienced]] as welling-up nondually from a source
 
[[File:Hell re.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Hell re.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
[16] Tung-shan told his students to walk "in the bird's track," which is of course trackless, having no deliberative traces before ("Should I do this or that?") and leaving none after ("Should I have done that?"). For further [[discussion]] of the relations among [[action]], {{Wiki|intention}}, and [[nonduality]], see "Wei-wu-wei: [[Nondual]] [[Action]]," [[Philosophy]] East and West, 35 (Jan. 1985).
+
[16] [[Tung-shan]] told his students to walk "in the bird's track," which is of course trackless, having no deliberative traces before ("Should I do this or that?") and leaving none after ("Should I have done that?"). For further [[discussion]] of the relations among [[action]], {{Wiki|intention}}, and [[nonduality]], see "Wei-wu-wei: [[Nondual]] [[Action]]," [[Philosophy]] [[East]] and [[West]], 35 (Jan. 1985).
  
 
p71
 
p71
Line 129: Line 129:
 
III
 
III
  
     At first glance, the Advaitic account of [[causality]] is very different from the [[Mādhyamika]] {{Wiki|conclusions}} and [[Ch'an]] [[experience]] which have been discussed above. Śaṅkara's position regarding [[causality]] constitutes part of his more general [[māyā]] [[doctrine]], according to which all [[phenomena]] are the indescribable and indefinable ajñana which is superimposed (adhyāsa) upon [[Brahman]]. But if we delve beneath the surface of {{Wiki|terminology}} and ask what [[experience]] this describes, it becomes difficult to find any {{Wiki|phenomenological}} basis for the distinction between the [[Mādhyamika]] and Advaitic accounts.
+
     At first glance, the [[Advaitic]] account of [[causality]] is very different from the [[Mādhyamika]] {{Wiki|conclusions}} and [[Ch'an]] [[experience]] which have been discussed above. [[Śaṅkara's]] position regarding [[causality]] constitutes part of his more general [[māyā]] [[doctrine]], according to which all [[phenomena]] are the [[indescribable]] and indefinable ajñana which is {{Wiki|superimposed}} (adhyāsa) upon [[Brahman]]. But if we delve beneath the surface of {{Wiki|terminology}} and ask what [[experience]] this describes, it becomes difficult to find any {{Wiki|phenomenological}} basis for the {{Wiki|distinction}} between the [[Mādhyamika]] and [[Advaitic]] accounts.
  
     Perhaps this similarity should not be surprising, since Śaṅkara's [[dialectic]] was clearly influenced by [[Nāgārjuna's]]. In this regard, it is relevant to compare Śaṅkara's careful critique of [[Vijñānavāda]] with his cursory dismissal of Śunyavāda as nihilistic and unworthy of repudiation. [18] Śaṅkara's main treatment of [[causality]], in Brahma-Sūtra-Bhāsya II.i.14-20, is indebted to the [[Mādhyamika]] [[dialectic]] and reaches a similar conclusion, that we cannot derive the real nature of [[causal]] relations from the series of discrete [[cause-and-effect]] [[phenomena]]. As a Vedantin, Śaṅkara then leaps to the conclusion that the true [[cause]] of all effects must be [[Brahman]], which provides the permanent [[substratum]] that persists unchanged through all [[experience]]. All effect-phenomena are merely [[illusory]] name-and-form superimpositions upon [[Brahman]], the substance-ground. Since [[Brahman]] is the only real ([[svabhāva]]), and [[phenomena]] [[existing]] as distinct from it are [[illusory]], this is a version of satkāryavāda: the effect pre-exists in the [[cause]]. But to distinguish this [[view]] from that of Sāṁkhya, which identifies [[cause and effect]] by granting the [[reality]] of [[prakṛti]], Śaṅkara's {{Wiki|theory}} of [[causality]] is more precisely labelled vivartavāda, since the effect ([[māyā]]) has a different kind of [[being]] from the [[cause]] ([[Brahman]]). [19]
+
     Perhaps this similarity should not be surprising, since [[Śaṅkara's]] [[dialectic]] was clearly influenced by [[Nāgārjuna's]]. In this regard, it is relevant to compare [[Śaṅkara's]] careful critique of [[Vijñānavāda]] with his cursory dismissal of Śunyavāda as [[Wikipedia:Nihilism|nihilistic]] and unworthy of repudiation. [18] [[Śaṅkara's]] main treatment of [[causality]], in Brahma-Sūtra-Bhāsya II.i.14-20, is indebted to the [[Mādhyamika]] [[dialectic]] and reaches a similar conclusion, that we cannot derive the real [[nature]] of [[causal]] relations from the series of discrete [[cause-and-effect]] [[phenomena]]. As a [[Vedantin]], [[Śaṅkara]] then leaps to the conclusion that the true [[cause]] of all effects must be [[Brahman]], which provides the [[permanent]] [[substratum]] that persists unchanged through all [[experience]]. All effect-phenomena are merely [[illusory]] name-and-form superimpositions upon [[Brahman]], the substance-ground. Since [[Brahman]] is the only real ([[svabhāva]]), and [[phenomena]] [[existing]] as {{Wiki|distinct}} from it are [[illusory]], this is a version of satkāryavāda: the effect pre-exists in the [[cause]]. But to distinguish this [[view]] from that of [[Sāṁkhya]], which identifies [[cause and effect]] by granting the [[reality]] of [[prakṛti]], [[Śaṅkara's]] {{Wiki|theory}} of [[causality]] is more precisely labelled vivartavāda, since the effect ([[māyā]]) has a different kind of [[being]] from the [[cause]] ([[Brahman]]). [19]
 
[[File:Hism1.jpeg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Hism1.jpeg|thumb|250px|]]
     Expressed in this way, the [[views]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] and Śaṅkara seem diametrically op-
+
     Expressed in this way, the [[views]] of [[Nāgārjuna]] and [[Śaṅkara]] seem diametrically op-
  
[17]  This [[view]] of [[Mādhyamika]] is important for understanding the [[trisvabhāva]] [[doctrine]] of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]]. The [[prapañca]] [[world]] of discrete [[forms]] corresponds to parikalpita-svabhāva, the "[[imagined]] nature." "All-conditionality" corresponds to parinispanna-svabhāva, the "other-dependent nature." "No-conditionality" corresponds to parinispanna-svabhāva, the absolutely-accomplished [[nondual]] nature. Read in this way, [[Vasubandhu's]] Trisvabhāvanirdeśa, for example, is completely consistent with the [[Mādhyamika]] analysis of [[experience]]. For both [[Mādhyamika]] and [[Yogācāra]], an understanding of "all-conditionality," with its {{Wiki|negation}} of the self-existence of discrete things, is the crucial "hinge" by which we turn from [[avidyā]] to [[prajña]].
+
[17]  This [[view]] of [[Mādhyamika]] is important for [[understanding]] the [[trisvabhāva]] [[doctrine]] of [[Yogācāra]] [[Buddhism]]. The [[prapañca]] [[world]] of discrete [[forms]] corresponds to [[parikalpita-svabhāva]], the "[[imagined]] [[nature]]." "All-conditionality" corresponds to parinispanna-svabhāva, the "[[other-dependent]] [[nature]]." "No-conditionality" corresponds to parinispanna-svabhāva, the absolutely-accomplished [[nondual]] [[nature]]. Read in this way, [[Vasubandhu's]] [[Trisvabhāvanirdeśa]], for example, is completely consistent with the [[Mādhyamika]] analysis of [[experience]]. For both [[Mādhyamika]] and [[Yogācāra]], an [[understanding]] of "all-conditionality," with its {{Wiki|negation}} of the self-existence of discrete things, is the crucial "hinge" by which we turn from [[avidyā]] to [[prajña]].
  
       I think that the [[Mādhyamika]] [[view]] of causality—a [[dialectic]] which equates complete conditionality with no-conditionality—also implies a critique of Derrida's deconstruction. Derrida's use of the open-endedness (différance) of texts to deconstruct the self-as-writer employs only the First movement of the [[dialectic]]; the second and reverse movement (which Derrida does not make) uses the lack of a [[self]] to deconstruct the dissemination of meaning. One ends up with something more like the presence of the late Heidegger, where [[language]] is [[realized]] to be "the house of [[Being]]." The same point can be made by comparing the [[Mādhyamika]] critique of temporal relations with Derrida's critique of "logocentrism."
+
       I think that the [[Mādhyamika]] [[view]] of causality—a [[dialectic]] which equates complete [[conditionality]] with no-conditionality—also implies a critique of Derrida's deconstruction. Derrida's use of the open-endedness (différance) of texts to deconstruct the self-as-writer employs only the First {{Wiki|movement}} of the [[dialectic]]; the second and reverse {{Wiki|movement}} (which [[Derrida]] does not make) uses the lack of a [[self]] to deconstruct the dissemination of meaning. One ends up with something more like the presence of the late [[Wikipedia:Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]], where [[language]] is [[realized]] to be "the house of [[Being]]." The same point can be made by comparing the [[Mādhyamika]] critique of {{Wiki|temporal}} relations with Derrida's critique of "logocentrism."
  
[18] It is not unlikely that Śankara discovered his own [[non-dual]] [[philosophy]] in the system of [[Nāgārjuna]] and left it unexplained. His debt to Śunyata [[doctrine]] was so great that he quietly passed over it." Lal Mani Joshi, Studies in the [[Buddhistic]] Culture of [[India]] (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), p. 234.
+
[18] It is not unlikely that Śankara discovered his [[own]] [[non-dual]] [[philosophy]] in the system of [[Nāgārjuna]] and left it unexplained. His debt to [[Śunyata]] [[doctrine]] was so great that he quietly passed over it." Lal Mani Joshi, Studies in the [[Buddhistic]] {{Wiki|Culture}} of [[India]] ({{Wiki|Delhi}}: {{Wiki|Motilal Banarsidass}}, 1977), p. 234.
  
 
[19] Compare William Blake: "And every Natural Effect has a [[Spiritual]] [[Cause]], and Not a Natural; for a Natural [[Cause]] only seems: it is a [[delusion]]. .. ." (Milton, plate 28, 44-45)
 
[19] Compare William Blake: "And every Natural Effect has a [[Spiritual]] [[Cause]], and Not a Natural; for a Natural [[Cause]] only seems: it is a [[delusion]]. .. ." (Milton, plate 28, 44-45)
Line 145: Line 145:
 
p72
 
p72
  
posed. They draw opposite {{Wiki|conclusions}} from the illogicality and unintelligibility of the [[causal]] relationship: [[Nāgārjuna]], as a [[Buddhist]], denies any substratum-ground to [[phenomena]], and leaves them [[empty]] (śunya) of any [[Being]]; Śaṅkara, as a Vedantin, postulates [[Brahman]] as an imperceptible but necessary [[substratum]]. Phenomenologically, however, these positions turn out to be equivalent. For [[Advaita]], [[Brahman]] is the real [[cause]] of all [[phenomena]], but, in denying the [[reality]] of all changing attributes, Śaṅkara is reduced to defining the [[substratum]] so narrowly that it ceases to have any referent. Absolutely [[nothing]] can be predicated of Nirguna [[Brahman]], and it can be approached only through the via negatives of neti, neti. Although Śaṅkara would deny it, [[Brahman]] ends up as a completely [[empty]] ground, [[unchanging]] only because it is a [[Nothing]] from which all [[phenomena]] arise as an ever-changing and hence deceptive appearance. From the perspective of [[Buddhism]], [[Vedanta]] reifies [[śunyatā]] into an attributeless [[substance]], which, since it has no characteristics of its own, cannot really be said to be at all. From the perspective of [[Vedanta]], however. [[Buddhism]] ignores the fact that such a ground is necessary, for as {{Wiki|Parmenides}} pointed out [[nothing]] can arise from [[nothing]] and it is meaningless to deny all [[substance]]: something must be real. Despite this family quarrel, the descriptions converge; what is perhaps more important than the [[difference]] is that for both the [[emptiness]] of this "ground" (however otherwise understood) is also fullness and limitless richness, for it is lack of any fixed characteristics which makes possible the [[infinite]] diversity of the [[phenomena]] which arise from "it" [20]
+
posed. They draw opposite {{Wiki|conclusions}} from the illogicality and unintelligibility of the [[causal]] relationship: [[Nāgārjuna]], as a [[Buddhist]], denies any substratum-ground to [[phenomena]], and leaves them [[empty]] (śunya) of any [[Being]]; [[Śaṅkara]], as a [[Vedantin]], postulates [[Brahman]] as an imperceptible but necessary [[substratum]]. Phenomenologically, however, these positions turn out to be {{Wiki|equivalent}}. For [[Advaita]], [[Brahman]] is the real [[cause]] of all [[phenomena]], but, in denying the [[reality]] of all changing [[attributes]], [[Śaṅkara]] is reduced to defining the [[substratum]] so narrowly that it ceases to have any referent. Absolutely [[nothing]] can be predicated of [[Nirguna]] [[Brahman]], and it can be approached only through the via negatives of neti, neti. Although [[Śaṅkara]] would deny it, [[Brahman]] ends up as a completely [[empty]] ground, [[unchanging]] only because it is a [[Nothing]] from which all [[phenomena]] arise as an ever-changing and hence deceptive [[appearance]]. From the {{Wiki|perspective}} of [[Buddhism]], [[Vedanta]] reifies [[śunyatā]] into an attributeless [[substance]], which, since it has no [[characteristics]] of its [[own]], cannot really be said to be at all. From the {{Wiki|perspective}} of [[Vedanta]], however. [[Buddhism]] ignores the fact that such a ground is necessary, for as {{Wiki|Parmenides}} pointed out [[nothing]] can arise from [[nothing]] and it is meaningless to deny all [[substance]]: something must be real. Despite this family quarrel, the descriptions converge; what is perhaps more important than the [[difference]] is that for both the [[emptiness]] of this "ground" (however otherwise understood) is also fullness and {{Wiki|limitless}} richness, for it is lack of any fixed [[characteristics]] which makes possible the [[infinite]] diversity of the [[phenomena]] which arise from "it" [20]
 
[[File:HL.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:HL.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
       What is most significant about their argument is that it is no longer a disagreement over the nature of the [[nondual]] [[experience]]. Since [[Brahman]] is qualityless and imperceptible, there is no {{Wiki|phenomenological}} [[difference]] between a [[Mādhyamika]] interpretation of Huang-po's blow and an Advaitic one. In both cases, the arm-movement is [[experienced]] nondually, with no bifurcation between a self-conscious [[subject]] and "his" [[action]]. In both cases that [[action]] is mysterious [[māyā]], inexplicable in terms of efficient [[causality]] and having no [[svabhāva]] [[reality]] of its own (nor, of course, does Huang-po, or anything else). The importance of this agreement is great. The only [[difference]] is that [[Mādhyamika]] stops here, while [[Advaita]] assumes that there must be an [[unchanging]] ground as the source of all the changing [[phenomena]]. But since this source is by definition imperceptible, the [[difference]] is reduced to a far more abstract, although not [[trivial]], one of emphasis: concluding that [[phenomena]] are [[illusory]] [[māyā]] seems to devalue them somewhat more than if [[phenomena]] are merely śunya without any [[Brahman]] "behind" them. In other words, the [[difference]] becomes one of [[attitude]] towards the [[nondual]] [[experience]] rather than anything in the [[experience]] itself: the Advaitin, with his [[dualistic]] distinction between [[Brahman]] and [[māyā]] will be more eager to negate the [[phenomenal]] [[world]] than the [[Buddhist]] [[bodhisattva]], for whom there are only [[empty]] [[forms]]. [21]
+
       What is most significant about their argument is that it is no longer a disagreement over the [[nature]] of the [[nondual]] [[experience]]. Since [[Brahman]] is qualityless and imperceptible, there is no {{Wiki|phenomenological}} [[difference]] between a [[Mādhyamika]] [[interpretation]] of Huang-po's blow and an [[Advaitic]] one. In both cases, the arm-movement is [[experienced]] nondually, with no [[bifurcation]] between a self-conscious [[subject]] and "his" [[action]]. In both cases that [[action]] is mysterious [[māyā]], inexplicable in terms of efficient [[causality]] and having no [[svabhāva]] [[reality]] of its [[own]] (nor, of course, does [[Huang-po]], or anything else). The importance of this agreement is great. The only [[difference]] is that [[Mādhyamika]] stops here, while [[Advaita]] assumes that there must be an [[unchanging]] ground as the source of all the changing [[phenomena]]. But since this source is by [[definition]] imperceptible, the [[difference]] is reduced to a far more abstract, although not [[trivial]], one of {{Wiki|emphasis}}: concluding that [[phenomena]] are [[illusory]] [[māyā]] seems to devalue them somewhat more than if [[phenomena]] are merely śunya without any [[Brahman]] "behind" them. In other words, the [[difference]] becomes one of [[attitude]] towards the [[nondual]] [[experience]] rather than anything in the [[experience]] itself: the Advaitin, with his [[dualistic]] {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[Brahman]] and [[māyā]] will be more eager to negate the [[phenomenal]] [[world]] than the [[Buddhist]] [[bodhisattva]], for whom there are only [[empty]] [[forms]]. [21]
  
[20] This is reflected in the {{Wiki|etymology}} of both words. Most [[scholars]] agree that [[Brahman]] comes from the [[root]] brḥ, "to burst forth, grow." "To us, it is clear. [[Brahman]] means [[reality]], which grows, breathes or swells." Radhakrishnan, [[Indian Philosophy]] ({{Wiki|London}}: Alien and Unwin, 1962J, I, 164 n. [[Śunyatā]] is from the [[root]] śu, which means "to swell" in two [[senses]]: not only "hollow or [[empty]]," but also "to be swollen" in the [[sense]] of full, like the [[womb]] of a pregnant woman. It has been unfortunate for [[Buddhist studies]] that the English translation "[[emptiness]]" captures only the first [[sense]].
+
[20] This is reflected in the {{Wiki|etymology}} of both words. Most [[scholars]] agree that [[Brahman]] comes from the [[root]] brḥ, "to burst forth, grow." "To us, it is clear. [[Brahman]] means [[reality]], which grows, breathes or swells." [[Radhakrishnan]], [[Indian Philosophy]] ({{Wiki|London}}: Alien and Unwin, 1962J, I, 164 n. [[Śunyatā]] is from the [[root]] śu, which means "to swell" in two [[senses]]: not only "hollow or [[empty]]," but also "to be swollen" in the [[sense]] of full, like the [[womb]] of a {{Wiki|pregnant}} woman. It has been unfortunate for [[Buddhist studies]] that the English translation "[[emptiness]]" captures only the first [[sense]].
  
[21] I am grateful to the "{{Wiki|Singapore}} [[Mādhyamika]] Study Group", especially Peter Della Santina, for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper. For further [[discussion]] of [[Mādhyamika]], see "How Not to Criticize [[Nāgārjuna]]," [[Philosophy]] East and West, 34 (Oct. 1984).
+
[21] I am grateful to the "{{Wiki|Singapore}} [[Mādhyamika]] Study Group", especially [[Peter Della Santina]], for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper. For further [[discussion]] of [[Mādhyamika]], see "How Not to Criticize [[Nāgārjuna]]," [[Philosophy]] [[East]] and [[West]], 34 (Oct. 1984).
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
 
{{R}}
 
{{R}}
 
[http://ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-MISC/misc33378.htm ccbs.ntu.edu.tw]
 
[http://ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-MISC/misc33378.htm ccbs.ntu.edu.tw]
 
[[Category:Madhyamaka]]
 
[[Category:Madhyamaka]]

Latest revision as of 22:14, 24 March 2015

Ess.jpg

THE PROBLEM of causality is central to all schools of Buddhism, and this is especially true of Mādhyamika. But at first glance there seems to be a contradiction in the Mādhyamika analysis. On the one hand, causal interdependence is clearly a crucial concept, so important that Nāgārjuna identifies it with the most important concept, śunyatā: "We interpret the dependent arising of all things (pratītyasamutpāda) as the absence of being in them (śunyatā)." [1] This emphasis on interdependence develops to completion the early Buddhist doctrine of impermanence: there are no unconditioned elements of existence (dharmas), for all things arise and pass away according to conditions. The undeniable relativity of everything is the means by which self-existence (svabhāva) is refuted.

   At the same time, Nāgārjuna redefines pratītyasamutpāda in such a way as to negate causality altogether. This is apparent even in the prefatory dedication of the Mūlamādhyamikakārikās, in the eight negations which Nāgārjuna attributes to the Buddha:

Neither perishing nor arising in time,

         neither terminable nor eternal,

Neither self-identical nor variant in form,

         neither coming nor going;

Such pratītyasamutpāda.. . .[2]

Consistent with this, the first and most important chapter of the Kārikās concludes that the causal relation is inexplicable, and later chapters go further to claim that causation is like māyā. "Origination, existence, and destruction are of the nature of māyā, dreams, or a fairy castle." [3] The last chapters seize on this issue as one way to crystallize the difference between saṁsāra and nirvāna. The nirvāna chapter distinguishes between them by attributing causal relations only to saṁsāra: "That which, taken as causal or dependent, is the process of being born and passing on, is, taken non-causally and beyond all dependence, declared to be nirvāna." [4] In his commentary on the previous chapter, Candrakirti defines saṁvṛti and duḥkha in the same way: ". . .to be reciprocally dependent in existence, that is, for things to be based on

F1qz6.jpg


[1] Mūlamādhyamikakārikās (hereafter "MMK') XXIV 18, in Lucid Exposition of the Middle Way: The Essential Chapters from [he Prasannapada of andrakirti, trans. Mervyn Sprung (Boulder: Prajña Press, 1979), p. 238. This identification must be kept in mind to avoid Śaṅkara's error of misinterpreting sunyaia as non-being and making Mādhyamika into a nihilism.

[2] I bid., pp. 32-33, 35. For pratītyasamutpāda Sprung gives "the true way of things."

[3] MMK VII 34, as quoted in T. R. V. Murti, The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (London: Allen and Unwin, 1960), p. 177.

[4] MMK XXV 9, in Sprung, p. 255. In my opinion this is the most important verse in the Kārikās.

 p64

each other in utter reciprocity, is saṁvṛti." ". . it is precisely what arises in dependence that constitutes duḥkha, not what does not arise in dependence." [5]

How are we to understand this obvious contradiction? That is, how do we get from interpreting pratītyasamutpāda as "dependent origination" to "non-dependent non-origination," and, what is more, reconcile the two? Explanations which differentiate between two different types of sutras (exoteric neyārtha and esoteric nītārtha), or which refer to the two-truths theory, just raise the same question in a different form, for we need to know how such contradictory truths can both be true, i.e., how these two are related to each other.

     This paper will offer one way (perhaps not the only way) of resolving this problem, which may more properly be said to be a paradox. I shall argue that complete conditionality is phenomenologically equivalent to a denial of all causal conditions. That is, a view which is so radical as to analyze things away into "their" conditions is offering an interpretation of experience which becomes indistinguishable from a view that negates causality altogether. If this is true, we have another instance where it becomes very difficult to distinguish the Mādhyamika nonduality from that of Śaṅkara's Advaita Vedānta. [6] The argument will be made in two steps. We shall see that there is a dialectic inherent in the Mādhyamika analysis. The first stage (discussed in Part I) is apparent: looking at the common-sense distinction between things and their cause-and-effect relationships, Nāgārjuna uses the latter to "dissolve" the former and deny that there are things. Less obvious is the second stage (Part II), which reverses the analysis: as we shall see, the lack of "thingness" in things implies a way of experiencing in which there is no awareness of cause and effect. Things and their causal relations stand and fall together, because our notion of cause-and-effect is dependent on that of things, which cause and are affected. If one collapses, so does the other. The basic problem is that any dualism between them is untenable. It is the delusive bifurcation between them that Nāgārjuna is concerned to negate, and the two ways to do this are to use each pole to "deconstruct" the other. Consistent with the general Mādhyamika project, this is criticism without affirming any philosophical position: having conflated the duality, Nāgārjuna does not offer any view about causality, because nothing remains to be related to anything else. Part III compares this conclusion with the Advaitic position regarding causality.

I

Gns.jpg

   In order to understand the Mādhyamika critique, we must begin with a clear sense of what it is that is being criticized. This is our common-sense understanding of the world, which sees it as a collection of discrete entities (including myself) interacting causally "in" space and time. Just as space and time, if they are to function as "containers," require something understood as nonspatial and nontemporal to "contain," so the causal relation is normally used to explain the interaction between things which

[5] Sprung,pp. 230, 236.

[6] I have argued for this equivalence in two other papers. "Enlightenment in Buddhism and Advaita Vedanta: Are Nirvāna and Moksha the Same?" International Philosophical Quarterly, 22 (1982), 65-74, claims that the no-self modal-view of Buddhism is indistinguishable from the all-Self substance-view of Advaita. See my paper "The Mahayana Deconstruction of Time" (unpublished) which maintains that the nonduality between things and time amounts to making the same claim regarding temporality: if there is only time, this is phenemenologically equivalent to a nunc stans ("eternal now").



p65

are distinct from each other. Nāgārjuna attacks more than the philosophical fancies of Indian metaphysicians, for there is a metaphysics inherent in our common-sense view. This common-sense understanding (one or the other aspect of which is absolutized in systematic metaphysics) is what makes the everyday world saṁsara for us, and it is this saṁsara that Nāgārjuna is concerned to "deconstruct." This is why one must beware of making Mādhyamika into an "ordinary language" philosophy by interpreting śunyatā merely as a "meta-system" term denying a correspondence theory of truth. By no means does the end of philosophical language-games "leave everything as it is" for Nāgārjuna, except in the sense that saṁsara has always really been nirvāṇa.

Gold.jpg

     Why do we experience the world as saṁsara, if that is delusive? Why don't we experience it as it is? The traditional Buddhist answer points to craving and ignorance, but Nāgārjuna focuses on a particular type of mental attachment, that which makes all other attachment possible: prapañca. The nirvāṇa chapter of the Kārikās concludes by characterizing nirvāṇa, negatively, as "the coming to rest of all ways of taking things, the repose of named things (prapañcopaśama)The precise meaning of prapañca is, unfortunately, unclear. Sprung defines it as "the world of named things; the visible manifold." [8] It refers to some indeterminate "interface" between our concepts and our perceptions: that our categories of thinking are somehow responsible for our perceiving "the visible world" as "manifold." The consequence of prapañca is that I now perceive the room I am writing in, not as it really is, nondually, but as a collection of books and chair and pens and paper. . .and me, each of which is in some naive fashion taken to (1) be distinct from the others and (2) persist unchanged unless affected by something else.[9]

This point about prapañca is important because without it one might conclude that Nāgārjuna's critique of self-existence (svabhāva) is a refutation of something that no one believes in anyway. But one does not escape his critique by defining entities in a more common-sense fashion as coming-into and passing-out-of existence. There is no tenable middle ground between self-existence independent of all conditions—an empty set, for there are no such entities—and the complete conditionality of śunyatā. The implication of Nāgārjuna's arguments against self-existence (e.g., MMK chapters I, XV) is to point out the inconsistency in our everyday way of "taking" the world: we accept that things change, and at the same time we assume that somehow they also remain the same—which is necessary if there are to be "things" at all. Other philosophers, recognizing this inconsistency, have tried to solve it by absolutizing one of these at the expense of the other; so the satkāryavāda substance-view of Samkhya emphasizes permanence at the price of not being able to account for change, and the asatkāryavāda modal-view of early Buddhism has the opposite problem of not being able to account for continuity. Nāgārjuna arranges these and the other solutions that have been proposed into a "tetralemma" which exhausts the possible philosophical alternatives; then he proceeds to refute them all. The basic difficulty is that any understanding of cause and effect which tries to relate two separate things together can be reduced to the contradiction of both asserting and denying identity. Nor can one respond to this simply by denying causality, for that is likewise contradicted by our experience. So Nāgārjuna concludes that the "relationship" between cause and effect is incomprehensible.

Goldenbuddha.jpg

[7]MMKXXV 24, in Sprung p. 264.

[8]"Ibid., p. 273.

[9] The role of prapañca in our experience cannot be fully understood without relating it to our intentions. The relations among craving, conceptualizing, and causality have been discussed in "The Difference between saṁsara and Nirvāṇa," Philosophy East and West, 33 (1983), 355-365.

p66

     But the problem is not resolved simply by criticizing such positions, for the difficulty is fundamentally not abstract and philosophical but very personal: it is our lives, not just our theories, which are inconsistent in "taking" the world as a collection of discrete "self-existing" things which yet change. Although during, a philosophy seminar I may accept the complete conditionality and contingency of all experience, as soon as the seminar ends I unconsciously assume that the colleague I join for lunch is the same person whom I spoke with before the seminar—although ever-so-slightly different, due to a relatively extraneous change of mood, etc. This constitutes saṁsara because it is by reifying such "thingness" out of the flux of experience that we become attached to things. (Of course, other hypostatizations of self-existence— my wife, my car and, most of all, myself—tend to be more problematic loci for attachment, but the problem is the same in each case: we cling to things which dissolve as we try to grasp them.)

     It does not suffice to answer this Humean critique of identity [10] with an "ordinary language" rejoinder that we should become more sensitive to the ways we use our permanence-and-change vocabulary, for the Mādhyamika position is that our usual everyday experience is deluded and this ordinary use of language is deluding. As the first prong of his attack, Nāgārjuna refutes our common-sense distinction between things and their causal relations simply by sharpening the distinction to absurdity: if things are to be "self-existent" then they must be separable from their conditions, but their existence is clearly contingent upon the conditions that bring them into being and eventually (when those conditions no longer operate) cause them to disappear. If it is objected that one cannot live without reifying such fictitious entities, at least to some extent, then the Mādhyamika response is to agree. The "lower truth", saṁvṛti, is not negated altogether—it is a truth—but it must not be taken as "the higher truth," as a correct understanding of the way things really are.

GoldenChild JadeOne.jpg

     So the first stage of the Mādhyamika critique uses the complete interdependence of all things to refute their "thingness." The distinction between things and their causal relations is negated by adopting the latter as a means to "deconstruct" the former. This completes the early Buddhist attack on substance. But this absolutizing of conditions is only the first step. Now the critique dialectically reverses to use the perspective of the deconstructed thing in order to deny the reality of causal conditions. In the delusive bifurcation between things and their causal relations, the category of causality turns out to be just as dependent on things as things are on their causal conditions. Our concept of causality presupposes a set of discrete entities, whose interrelation we explain as causation. Cause-and-effect requires something to cause and something to be effected. If this is so, then a complete conditionality which is so radical that it "dissolves" all things must also dissolve itself.

      In order to make this point, it is helpful to transpose the argument from the too-general category of causal conditions to the more specific one of motion-and-rest. Nāgārjuna analyzes motion and rest in chapter two of the Kārikās, immediately after his initial treatment of conditions, and it is clear that the second chapter is meant to apply the general conclusions of chapter one to a particular case. The additional advantage of shifting to motion-and-rest is that we illuminate what is otherwise a very puzzling chapter. The basic problem is that it is not clear what Nāgārjuna is actually doing in chapter two. Like Zeno, he denies the reality of motion, but this is not done

[10] See Hume's Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Section IV, Parts I and II.

p67

to assert an unchanging Parmenidean "block-universe," for Vedantic permanence (i.e., "rest") is also denied. As a result, Nāgārjuna has been criticized for an arid play on words which "resembles the shell game" in being a logical sleight-of-hand" [11]— that is, for basing his argument on a subtle distinction between words which are meaningless because they have no empirical referent—and for committing the fallacy of composition in arguing that what is true for the parts (in this case, traversed, traversing, and to-be-traversed) must be true for the whole. [12] But I think such criticisms miss the point of Nāgārjuna's arguments. Their import is that our usual way of understanding motion, which distinguishes the "mover" from "the act of moving," simply does not make sense, because the interdependence of "mover" and "motion" shows that the hypostatization of either is delusive. (Here "mover" means, not "that which causes motion", but "that thing which moves"; and "motion" is "the movement that happens to the thing") Nāgārjuna's logic in stanzas two through eleven demonstrates that once we have reified a distinction between them, it becomes impossible to relate them back together again—a quandary familiar to students of the Western mind-body problem, which is the result of another reified bifurcation. The difficulty is shown by isolating this hypostatized mover and inquiring into its status. Nāgārjuna asks: In itself, is it a mover, or not? That is, is the predicate "moves" intrinsic to this mover, or contingent? The dilemma is that neither way of understanding the situation is satisfactory. If the "mover" in and of itself already moves, then there is no need to add an "act of motion" later; the predication of such a "second motion" would be redundant. But the other alternative—that the "mover" by itself is a non-mover—does not work either because we cannot thereafter add the predicate: it is a contradiction for a non-mover to move. In neither way can we make sense out of the relation between them. It follows that the "mover" cannot have an existence of its own apart from the "moving," which means that our usual dualistic way of understanding motion is untenable. To summarize this in contemporary terms, Nāgārjuna is pointing out a flaw in the everyday language we use to describe (and hence our ways of thinking about) motion: our ascription of motion predicates to substantive objects is unintelligible.

Graph2.jpg

     At first encounter the above argument may be unconvincing. The options seem so extreme that we suspect there must be some middle ground between them. Of course we can't accept a double movement, but is it really a contradiction for a non-mover to move? What else could move? But, again, no such appeal to our everyday intuitions, or to the ordinary language which shapes and embodies them, is successful against the Mādhyamika critique of those intuitions, which seizes on the inconsistency that is ignored (and to some extent must be ignored) in daily life. We can elaborate upon this by applying the logic that was used earlier to deconstruct the difference between things and their causal relations. Just as (general rule) complete interdependence dissolves the thing into its rational conditions, with no residue of substance remaining, so (specific case) the completeness of movement—the fact that no part of "me" stays unmoved in the chair when "I" go to lunch—means that no self-existing and hence unchanging "thing" remains to move. As with time and with space, we think of the relation between mover and moving with the metaphor of container and contained, and in all three instances the bifurcation is delusive. In order to expose the absurdity of this, Nāgārjuna needs only to sharpen the dichotomy. Despite our intuitions, which

[11] "Richard Robinson, "Did Nāgārjuna Really Refute All Philosophical Views?" Philosophy East and West, 22 (1972), 325.

[12] Hsueh-li Cheng, "Motion and Rest in the Middle Treatise," J. of Chinese Philosophy, 1 (1980) 235 ff.



p68

inconsistently want to postulate some "unchanging core" in order to save the mover, there is no middle ground between a self-existent and hence unmoving thing, and the complete dissolution of the thing that does the moving. Understood in this way, it becomes obvious why his arguments also work just as well against the intelligibility of rest: the bifurcation between the thing and its being at rest is just as delusive, and for precisely the same reason.

Great Departure.JPG

II

So far, we have effected only the first stage of the dialectic, both in the general analysis of causal conditions and this more specific case of motion-and-rest. We have dissolved the thing which moves / is caused and are left with a changing world of causal conditions. The second stage of the dialectic is easy to state but harder to understand: granted, if there is only movement, then there is no mover; but if there is nothing to move, then likewise there can be no movement. Implicit in our concept of change is the notion that a thing is becoming other than it was, so unless one reifies something self-existent (cf. atemporal) in order to provide continuity between these different conditioned (temporal) states, there is nothing outside the changing conditions to be changed. The concept of change (here a general term to include both conditionality and movement) needs something to "bite" on, but the first stage of the dialectic leaves nothing unconditioned to chew. If the colleague I join for lunch is not in any sense the same person I spoke with earlier, because there is no substratum of permanence to "him," then it makes no sense to say that "he" has changed. Without a contained, there can be no container; as the bifurcation dissolves, the poles conflate into a whole which, as Nāgārjuna knew, cannot be represented but remains philosophically indeterminate, since language, in order to describe at all, must dualize between subject and predicate, mover and moved, cause and effect.

      But nonetheless, unless we can get a sense of what such a way of experiencing would be like, the above argument will be at best philosophically persuasive yet will seem irrelevant to daily life. What consequences does all this have for the way we actually experience the world? In particular, it is still unclear how, except by some "logical sleight of hand," all-conditionality can be phenomenologically identified with no-conditionality, as we claimed at the beginning of this paper.

     Let me try to satisfy these questions with the help of a well-known Ch'an (Zen) story.[13] The following example discusses the causal relations of a physical action, but what is said may be applied just as well to sense-perception (e.g., to the nondual sound of a pebble striking bamboo, which awakened Hsiang-yen, or to the nondual pain when Yün-mên broke his ankle) and to thought (Hui Neng: "If we allow our thoughts, past, present and future, to link up in a series, we put ourselves under re­straint. On the other hand, if we never let our mind attach to anything, we shall gain liberation.").

Guides.jpg

     Lin-chi was a monk in the monastery of Huang-po. Three times Lin-chi asked the Master: "What is the real meaning of Bodhidharma coming from the West?" and each time Huang-po immediately struck him. Thereupon, discouraged, he decided to leave

[13]The direct relevance of Ch'an experience to this issue cannot be questioned. While it is true that Ch'an is not. and does not have, any philosophy, yet it is also the case that Mādhyamika, as a philosophical exposition of the Prajñāparamīta, may be said to be the philosophy that most made Ch'an possible.

p69

and was advised to go to Master Ta-yü. Arriving at his monastery, Lin-chi told Ta-yü of his encounters with Huang-po, adding that he didn't know where he was at fault.

      Master Ta-yü exclaimed; "Your master treated you entirely with grandmotherly kindness, and yet you say you don't know your fault." Hearing this, Lin-chi was suddenly awakened and said; "After all, there isn't much in Huang-po's Buddhism!" [14]

      What did Lin-chi realize that awakened him? If (rushing in where Ch'an masters will not tread) we distort his experience into an idea in order to gloss this story, we may say that Lin-chi must have realized that Huang-po had been answering his question. The blows he received were not punishment but a demonstration of why Bodhidharma came from the West. On the common-sense level, the answer to Lin-chi's question is obvious: Bodhidharma was bringing Buddhism to China. But this is a relative, "lower truth" explanation. As a standard Ch'an question designed to initiate a dialogue, it goes without saying that what is sought is the "higher truth," and on this level there is no "why." For the enlightened person, each experience is complete in itself, the only thing in the whole universe; for each action is tathata. Nothing changes because without prapañca-reification everything is perceived afresh, for the first time. As Bodhidharma walked from India there was no thought of "why" in his head; "he" was each step. In the same way, there was no "why" to Huang-po's blows; "he" was that spontaneous, unselfconscious action. Lin-chi's sudden realization of this overflowed into his exclamation: "So, there isn't much to Buddhism after all!" (Only "just 'this'!") Upon returning to Huang-po, he revealed the depth of his understanding—more than just an intellectual insight—by not hesitating to give Huang-po a dose of his own medicine.

H1qh.jpg

      The paradox which makes the above story relevant to this paper is the fact that, at the same time, Bodhidharma's and Huang-po's actions are intentional. Huang-po's blow may be immediate and spontaneous, but there is also a "reason" for it; it is not a random or irrelevant gesture, but a very appropriate response to that particular question, drawn forth by that situation. If we translate this point about intention back into our more general category of causality, here we have a case of an act which is both completely caused (perfect upāya: glove fitting hand tightly, to use the Ch'an analogy) and yet is also uncaused. This paradox is a contradiction only according to our usual understanding of causality, which uses that category-of-thought to relate together the supposedly discrete objects into which prapañca carves the world. The first and most important of these hypostatized "things" is me, the subject who craves some of these objects and thus needs an understanding of cause-and-effect relationships in order to manipulate circumstances and obtain them. (It has been argued that the desire for such manipulation is the very root of our concept of causality. [15] ) This would apply to the story in question if Huang-po, prapañca-deluded, were to perceive Lin-chi dualistically: Lin-chi is sitting there, a person-object that needs to be enlightened, and I,

[14] This version of the story, from the Transmission of the Lamp, is given in Chang Chung-yuan, Original Teachings of Ch'an Buddhism (New York; Vintage, 1971), pp. 116-17.

[15] The idea of cause has its roots in purposive activity and is employed in the first instance when we are concerned to produce or to prevent something. To discover the cause of something is to discover what has to be attested by our activity in order to produce or to prevent that thing; but once the word 'cause' comes to be applied to natural events, the notion of altering the course of events lends to be dropped. 'Cause' is then used in a nonpractical, purely diagnostic way in cases where we have no interest in altering events or power to alter them." (P. H. Nowell-Smith, "Causality or Causation." I have a cyclostyled copy of this article but have not been able to trace its source.)

p70

Huang-po sitting here, am the person who will try to enlighten him. Then "my" blow is reified into a deliberated effect which I hope will cause Lin-chi's awakening.

Ha1r.jpg

      But if, as all schools of Buddhism agree, there is no self to do this causal-relating-between-things, then the above understanding of the situation must be delusive. So Huang-po must have experienced it differently, and causality too must be under­stood differently. It is not denied: on the contrary, without the sense of self and other prapañca- reified objects as a counterfoil, it expands to include everything, as Nagar-juna has already shown. (So the doctrine of karma can be understood simply by applying something like Newton's third law of physical motion to the mental realm as well.) From the perspective of Mādhyamika's "all-conditionality" which deconstructs all things, Huang-po's blow is part of a seamless web of conditions which can be extended, as Hwa Yen does, to encompass the entire universe. As one jewel in the infinite web of lndra, the blow reflects everything everywhere, at all times. But if every event that happens is interdependent with everything else in the whole universe, what a different way of experiencing this involves! It suggests a Spinozistic acceptance of whatever happens, as a product of the whole, but more than this it implies the irrelevance of causality as usually understood. "All-conditionality," in its complete negation of anything to be attached to, offers no practical utility, because there is no longer any object to be obtained or any self that craves it; whereas a self that wants to obtain some thing will need to isolate some discrete object or action as the cause which leads to obtaining it.

      What does all this imply about the way Huang-po experienced his own action? Because he did not perceive the situation dualistically, the action was not "his." That the blow was appropriate to the situation was not due to any prior deliberation, however quick. On the contrary, the action was so appropriate precisely because it was not deliberated, just as the best responses in "dharma-combat" are unmediated by any self-conscious "hindrance in the mind." Then why did Huang-po strike, rather than shout "ho!" as Ma-tsu often did, or utter a few soft words, as Chao-chou probably would have done? This is the crucial point: He does not know and cannot know. ("Not-knowing is very profound" said Master Lo-han, precipitating Wên-i's awakening.) His spontaneous actions are traceless, "like the tracks of a bird in the sky." [16] They respond to a situation like a glove fits on a hand because whatever "decisions are made" (if this phrase can be used here) are not made by him. If one nondualistically is the cause (or effect, or both), rather than being a hypostatized self that dualistically uses it, then there is not the awareness that it is a cause (or effect, or both); it is experienced as whole, complete, and "traceless." In this way there turn out to be only two alternatives: either cause-and-effect relationships between discrete prapañca-objects, manipulated by the prapañca-subject, or nondual "all-conditionality" which amounts to an experience of complete unconditioned freedom. Without the interference that the self creates, Indra's all-encompassing web of causal conditions is indeed seamless. In psychological terms, the barrier between consciousness ("ego") and subconsciousness dissolves ("the bottom falls out of the bucket") and thereafter thoughts and actions are experienced as welling-up nondually from a source

Hell re.jpg

[16] Tung-shan told his students to walk "in the bird's track," which is of course trackless, having no deliberative traces before ("Should I do this or that?") and leaving none after ("Should I have done that?"). For further discussion of the relations among action, intention, and nonduality, see "Wei-wu-wei: Nondual Action," Philosophy East and West, 35 (Jan. 1985).

p71

unfathomably deep—or (what amounts to the same thing) from nowhere. In this sense Mahayana is not wrong to identify śunyatā with the Absolute. [17]

III

     At first glance, the Advaitic account of causality is very different from the Mādhyamika conclusions and Ch'an experience which have been discussed above. Śaṅkara's position regarding causality constitutes part of his more general māyā doctrine, according to which all phenomena are the indescribable and indefinable ajñana which is superimposed (adhyāsa) upon Brahman. But if we delve beneath the surface of terminology and ask what experience this describes, it becomes difficult to find any phenomenological basis for the distinction between the Mādhyamika and Advaitic accounts.

     Perhaps this similarity should not be surprising, since Śaṅkara's dialectic was clearly influenced by Nāgārjuna's. In this regard, it is relevant to compare Śaṅkara's careful critique of Vijñānavāda with his cursory dismissal of Śunyavāda as nihilistic and unworthy of repudiation. [18] Śaṅkara's main treatment of causality, in Brahma-Sūtra-Bhāsya II.i.14-20, is indebted to the Mādhyamika dialectic and reaches a similar conclusion, that we cannot derive the real nature of causal relations from the series of discrete cause-and-effect phenomena. As a Vedantin, Śaṅkara then leaps to the conclusion that the true cause of all effects must be Brahman, which provides the permanent substratum that persists unchanged through all experience. All effect-phenomena are merely illusory name-and-form superimpositions upon Brahman, the substance-ground. Since Brahman is the only real (svabhāva), and phenomena existing as distinct from it are illusory, this is a version of satkāryavāda: the effect pre-exists in the cause. But to distinguish this view from that of Sāṁkhya, which identifies cause and effect by granting the reality of prakṛti, Śaṅkara's theory of causality is more precisely labelled vivartavāda, since the effect (māyā) has a different kind of being from the cause (Brahman). [19]

Hism1.jpeg

     Expressed in this way, the views of Nāgārjuna and Śaṅkara seem diametrically op-

[17] This view of Mādhyamika is important for understanding the trisvabhāva doctrine of Yogācāra Buddhism. The prapañca world of discrete forms corresponds to parikalpita-svabhāva, the "imagined nature." "All-conditionality" corresponds to parinispanna-svabhāva, the "other-dependent nature." "No-conditionality" corresponds to parinispanna-svabhāva, the absolutely-accomplished nondual nature. Read in this way, Vasubandhu's Trisvabhāvanirdeśa, for example, is completely consistent with the Mādhyamika analysis of experience. For both Mādhyamika and Yogācāra, an understanding of "all-conditionality," with its negation of the self-existence of discrete things, is the crucial "hinge" by which we turn from avidyā to prajña.

       I think that the Mādhyamika view of causality—a dialectic which equates complete conditionality with no-conditionality—also implies a critique of Derrida's deconstruction. Derrida's use of the open-endedness (différance) of texts to deconstruct the self-as-writer employs only the First movement of the dialectic; the second and reverse movement (which Derrida does not make) uses the lack of a self to deconstruct the dissemination of meaning. One ends up with something more like the presence of the late Heidegger, where language is realized to be "the house of Being." The same point can be made by comparing the Mādhyamika critique of temporal relations with Derrida's critique of "logocentrism."

[18] It is not unlikely that Śankara discovered his own non-dual philosophy in the system of Nāgārjuna and left it unexplained. His debt to Śunyata doctrine was so great that he quietly passed over it." Lal Mani Joshi, Studies in the Buddhistic Culture of India (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1977), p. 234.

[19] Compare William Blake: "And every Natural Effect has a Spiritual Cause, and Not a Natural; for a Natural Cause only seems: it is a delusion. .. ." (Milton, plate 28, 44-45)

p72

posed. They draw opposite conclusions from the illogicality and unintelligibility of the causal relationship: Nāgārjuna, as a Buddhist, denies any substratum-ground to phenomena, and leaves them empty (śunya) of any Being; Śaṅkara, as a Vedantin, postulates Brahman as an imperceptible but necessary substratum. Phenomenologically, however, these positions turn out to be equivalent. For Advaita, Brahman is the real cause of all phenomena, but, in denying the reality of all changing attributes, Śaṅkara is reduced to defining the substratum so narrowly that it ceases to have any referent. Absolutely nothing can be predicated of Nirguna Brahman, and it can be approached only through the via negatives of neti, neti. Although Śaṅkara would deny it, Brahman ends up as a completely empty ground, unchanging only because it is a Nothing from which all phenomena arise as an ever-changing and hence deceptive appearance. From the perspective of Buddhism, Vedanta reifies śunyatā into an attributeless substance, which, since it has no characteristics of its own, cannot really be said to be at all. From the perspective of Vedanta, however. Buddhism ignores the fact that such a ground is necessary, for as Parmenides pointed out nothing can arise from nothing and it is meaningless to deny all substance: something must be real. Despite this family quarrel, the descriptions converge; what is perhaps more important than the difference is that for both the emptiness of this "ground" (however otherwise understood) is also fullness and limitless richness, for it is lack of any fixed characteristics which makes possible the infinite diversity of the phenomena which arise from "it" [20]

HL.jpg

      What is most significant about their argument is that it is no longer a disagreement over the nature of the nondual experience. Since Brahman is qualityless and imperceptible, there is no phenomenological difference between a Mādhyamika interpretation of Huang-po's blow and an Advaitic one. In both cases, the arm-movement is experienced nondually, with no bifurcation between a self-conscious subject and "his" action. In both cases that action is mysterious māyā, inexplicable in terms of efficient causality and having no svabhāva reality of its own (nor, of course, does Huang-po, or anything else). The importance of this agreement is great. The only difference is that Mādhyamika stops here, while Advaita assumes that there must be an unchanging ground as the source of all the changing phenomena. But since this source is by definition imperceptible, the difference is reduced to a far more abstract, although not trivial, one of emphasis: concluding that phenomena are illusory māyā seems to devalue them somewhat more than if phenomena are merely śunya without any Brahman "behind" them. In other words, the difference becomes one of attitude towards the nondual experience rather than anything in the experience itself: the Advaitin, with his dualistic distinction between Brahman and māyā will be more eager to negate the phenomenal world than the Buddhist bodhisattva, for whom there are only empty forms. [21]

[20] This is reflected in the etymology of both words. Most scholars agree that Brahman comes from the root brḥ, "to burst forth, grow." "To us, it is clear. Brahman means reality, which grows, breathes or swells." Radhakrishnan, Indian Philosophy (London: Alien and Unwin, 1962J, I, 164 n. Śunyatā is from the root śu, which means "to swell" in two senses: not only "hollow or empty," but also "to be swollen" in the sense of full, like the womb of a pregnant woman. It has been unfortunate for Buddhist studies that the English translation "emptiness" captures only the first sense.

[21] I am grateful to the "Singapore Mādhyamika Study Group", especially Peter Della Santina, for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper. For further discussion of Mādhyamika, see "How Not to Criticize Nāgārjuna," Philosophy East and West, 34 (Oct. 1984).

Source

ccbs.ntu.edu.tw