Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Buddha."

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
(Created page with " First published Thu Feb 17, 2011; substantive revision Tue Feb 3, 2015 The Buddha (fl. circa 450 BCE) is the individual whose teachings form the basis of the Buddhist tr...")
 
 
Line 6: Line 6:
 
First published Thu Feb 17, 2011; substantive revision Tue Feb 3, 2015
 
First published Thu Feb 17, 2011; substantive revision Tue Feb 3, 2015
  
The Buddha (fl. circa 450 BCE) is the individual whose teachings form the basis of the Buddhist tradition. These teachings, preserved in texts known as the Nikāyas or Āgamas, concern the quest for liberation from suffering. While the ultimate aim of the Buddha's teachings is thus to help individuals attain the good life, his analysis of the source of suffering centrally involves claims concerning the nature of persons, as well as how we acquire knowledge about the world and our place in it. These teachings formed the basis of a philosophical tradition that developed and defended a variety of sophisticated theories in metaphysics and epistemology.
+
The [[Buddha]] (fl. circa 450 BCE) is the {{Wiki|individual}} whose teachings [[form]] the basis of the [[Buddhist tradition]]. These teachings, preserved in texts known as the [[Nikāyas]] or [[Āgamas]], [[concern]] the quest for [[liberation]] from [[suffering]]. While the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] aim of the [[Buddha's teachings]] is thus to help {{Wiki|individuals}} attain the good [[life]], his analysis of the source of [[suffering]] centrally involves claims concerning the [[nature]] of persons, as well as how we acquire [[knowledge]] about the [[world]] and our place in it. These teachings formed the basis of a [[philosophical]] [[tradition]] that developed and defended a variety of sophisticated theories in [[metaphysics]] and epistemology.
  
  
  
  
1. Buddha as Philosopher
+
1. [[Buddha]] as [[Philosopher]]
  
  
  
This entry concerns the historical individual, traditionally called Gautama, who is identified by modern scholars as the founder of Buddhism. According to Buddhist teachings, there have been other Buddhas in the past, and there will be yet more in the future.  
+
This entry concerns the historical {{Wiki|individual}}, [[traditionally]] called [[Gautama]], who is identified by {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]] as the [[founder of Buddhism]]. According to [[Buddhist teachings]], there have been other [[Buddhas]] in the {{Wiki|past}}, and there will be yet more in the {{Wiki|future}}.  
  
  
The title ‘Buddha’, which literally means ‘awakened’, is conferred on an individual who discovers the path to nirvana, the cessation of suffering, and propagates that discovery so that others may also achieve nirvana. If the teaching that there have been other Buddhas is true, then Gautama is not the founder of Buddhism.  
+
The title ‘[[Buddha]]’, which literally means ‘[[awakened]]’, is conferred on an {{Wiki|individual}} who discovers the [[path]] to [[nirvana]], the [[cessation of suffering]], and propagates that discovery so that others may also achieve [[nirvana]]. If the [[teaching]] that there have been other [[Buddhas]] is true, then [[Gautama]] is not the [[founder of Buddhism]].  
  
  
This entry will follow modern scholarship in taking an agnostic stance on the question of whether there have been other Buddhas, and likewise for questions concerning the superhuman status and powers that some Buddhists attribute to Buddhas. The concern of this entry is just those aspects of the thought of the historical individual Gautama that bear on the development of the Buddhist philosophical tradition.
+
This entry will follow {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} in taking an agnostic stance on the question of whether there have been other [[Buddhas]], and likewise for questions concerning the superhuman {{Wiki|status}} and [[powers]] that some [[Buddhists]] attribute to [[Buddhas]]. The [[concern]] of this entry is just those aspects of the [[thought]] of the historical {{Wiki|individual}} [[Gautama]] that bear on the [[development]] of the [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]].
  
  
The Buddha will here be treated as a philosopher. To so treat him is controversial, but before coming to why that should be so, let us first rehearse those basic aspects of the Buddha's life and teachings that are relatively non-controversial. Tradition has it that Gautama lived to age 80. Up until recently his dates were thought to be approximately 560–480 BCE, but many scholars now hold that he must have died around 405 BCE. He was born into a family of some wealth and power, members of the Śākya clan, in the area of the present border between India and Nepal.  
+
The [[Buddha]] will here be treated as a [[philosopher]]. To so treat him is controversial, but before coming to why that should be so, let us first rehearse those basic aspects of the [[Buddha's life]] and teachings that are relatively non-controversial. [[Tradition]] has it that [[Gautama]] lived to age 80. Up until recently his dates were [[thought]] to be approximately 560–480 BCE, but many [[scholars]] now hold that he must have [[died]] around 405 BCE. He was born into a [[family]] of some [[wealth]] and power, members of the [[Śākya]] {{Wiki|clan}}, in the area of the {{Wiki|present}} border between [[India]] and [[Nepal]].  
  
  
The story is that in early adulthood he abandoned his comfortable life as a householder (as well as his wife and young son) in order to seek a solution to the problem of existential suffering. He first took up with a number of different wandering ascetics (śramanas) who claimed to know the path to liberation from suffering. Finding their teachings unsatisfactory, he struck out on his own, and through a combination of insight and meditational practice attained the state of enlightenment (bodhi) which is said to represent the cessation of all further suffering. He then devoted the remaining 45 years of his life to teaching others the insights and techniques that had led him to this achievement.
+
The story is that in early adulthood he abandoned his comfortable [[life]] as a [[householder]] (as well as his wife and young son) in order to seek a {{Wiki|solution}} to the problem of [[existential]] [[suffering]]. He first took up with a number of different wandering [[ascetics]] (śramanas) who claimed to know the [[path to liberation]] from [[suffering]]. Finding their teachings unsatisfactory, he struck out on his [[own]], and through a combination of [[insight]] and [[meditational practice]] [[attained]] the [[state of enlightenment]] ([[bodhi]]) which is said to represent the [[cessation]] of all further [[suffering]]. He then devoted the remaining 45 years of his [[life]] to [[teaching]] others the [[insights]] and [[techniques]] that had led him to this [[achievement]].
  
  
  
Gautama could himself be classified as one of the śramanas. That there existed such a phenomenon as the śramanas tells us that there was some degree of dissatisfaction with the customary religious practices then prevailing in the Gangetic basin of North India. These practices consisted largely in the rituals and sacrifices prescribed in the Vedas. Among the śramanas there were many, including the Buddha, who rejected the authority of the Vedas as definitive pronouncements on the nature of the world and our place in it (and for this reason are called ‘heterodox’). But within the Vedic canon itself there is a stratum of (comparatively late) texts, the Upaniṣads, that likewise displays disaffection with Brahmin ritualism.  
+
[[Gautama]] could himself be classified as one of the śramanas. That there existed such a [[phenomenon]] as the śramanas tells us that there was some [[degree]] of [[dissatisfaction]] with the customary [[religious]] practices then prevailing in the Gangetic basin of [[North India]]. These practices consisted largely in the [[rituals]] and [[sacrifices]] prescribed in the [[Vedas]]. Among the śramanas there were many, [[including]] the [[Buddha]], who rejected the authority of the [[Vedas]] as definitive pronouncements on the [[nature]] of the [[world]] and our place in it (and for this [[reason]] are called ‘[[Wikipedia:Heterodoxy|heterodox]]’). But within the {{Wiki|Vedic}} [[canon]] itself there is a stratum of (comparatively late) texts, the [[Upaniṣads]], that likewise displays disaffection with [[Brahmin]] ritualism.  
  
  
Among the new ideas that figure in these (‘orthodox’) texts, as well as in the teachings of those heterodox śramanas whose doctrines are known to us, are the following: that sentient beings (including humans, non-human animals, gods, and the inhabitants of various hells) undergo rebirth; that rebirth is governed by the causal laws of karma (good actions cause pleasant fruit for the agent, evil actions cause unpleasant fruit, etc.); that continual rebirth is inherently unsatisfactory; that there is an ideal state for sentient beings involving liberation from the cycle of rebirth; and that attaining this state requires overcoming ignorance concerning one's true identity. Various views are offered concerning this ignorance and how to overcome it.  
+
Among the new [[ideas]] that figure in these (‘[[orthodox]]’) texts, as well as in the teachings of those [[Wikipedia:Heterodoxy|heterodox]] śramanas whose [[doctrines]] are known to us, are the following: that [[sentient beings]] ([[including]] [[humans]], {{Wiki|non-human}} [[animals]], [[gods]], and the inhabitants of various [[hells]]) undergo [[rebirth]]; that [[rebirth]] is governed by the causal laws of [[karma]] ([[good actions]] [[cause]] [[pleasant]] fruit for the agent, [[evil actions]] [[cause]] [[unpleasant]] fruit, etc.); that continual [[rebirth]] is inherently unsatisfactory; that there is an {{Wiki|ideal}} [[state]] for [[sentient beings]] involving [[liberation]] from the [[cycle of rebirth]]; and that [[attaining]] this [[state]] requires [[overcoming]] [[ignorance]] concerning one's true [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]. Various [[views]] are [[offered]] concerning this [[ignorance]] and how to overcome it.  
  
The Bhagavad Gītā (classified by some orthodox schools as an Upaniṣad) lists four such methods, and discusses at least two separate views concerning our identity: that there is a plurality of distinct selves, each being the true agent of a person's actions and the bearer of karmic merit and demerit but existing separately from the body and its associated states; and that there is just one self, of the nature of pure consciousness (a ‘witness’) and identical with the essence of the cosmos, Brahman or pure undifferentiated Being.
+
The {{Wiki|Bhagavad Gītā}} (classified by some [[orthodox schools]] as an [[Upaniṣad]]) lists four such [[methods]], and discusses at least two separate [[views]] concerning our [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]: that there is a plurality of {{Wiki|distinct}} selves, each being the true agent of a person's [[actions]] and the bearer of [[karmic merit]] and {{Wiki|demerit}} but [[existing]] separately from the [[body]] and its associated states; and that there is just one [[self]], of the [[nature]] of [[pure consciousness]] (a ‘{{Wiki|witness}}’) and [[identical]] with the [[essence]] of the [[cosmos]], [[Brahman]] or [[pure]] undifferentiated Being.
  
  
  
The Buddha agreed with those of his contemporaries embarked on the same soteriological project that it is ignorance about our identity that is responsible for suffering. What sets his teachings apart (at this level of analysis) lies in what he says that ignorance consists in: the conceit that there is an ‘I’ and a ‘mine’. This is the famous Buddhist teaching of non-self (anātman). And it is with this teaching that the controversy begins concerning whether Gautama may legitimately be represented as a philosopher.  
+
The [[Buddha]] agreed with those of his contemporaries embarked on the same [[soteriological]] project that it is [[ignorance]] about our [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] that is responsible for [[suffering]]. What sets his teachings apart (at this level of analysis) lies in what he says that [[ignorance]] consists in: the [[conceit]] that there is an ‘I’ and a ‘mine’. This is the famous [[Buddhist teaching]] of [[non-self]] ([[anātman]]). And it is with this [[teaching]] that the [[controversy]] begins concerning whether [[Gautama]] may legitimately be represented as a [[philosopher]].  
  
First there are those who (correctly) point out that the Buddha never categorically denies the existence of a self that transcends what is empirically given, namely the five skandhas or psychophysical elements. While the Buddha does deny that any of the psychophysical elements is a self, these interpreters claim that he at least leaves open the possibility that there is a self that is transcendent in the sense of being non-empirical.  
+
First there are those who (correctly) point out that the [[Buddha]] never categorically denies the [[existence]] of a [[self]] that {{Wiki|transcends}} what is [[empirically]] given, namely the [[five skandhas]] or {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]]. While the [[Buddha]] does deny that any of the {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]] is a [[self]], these interpreters claim that he at least leaves open the possibility that there is a [[self]] that is [[transcendent]] in the [[sense]] of being non-empirical.  
  
To this it may be objected that all of classical Indian philosophy—Buddhist and orthodox alike—understood the Buddha to have denied the self tout court. To this it is sometimes replied that the later philosophical tradition simply got the Buddha wrong, at least in part because the Buddha sought to indicate something that cannot be grasped through the exercise of philosophical rationality. On this interpretation, the Buddha should be seen not as a proponent of the philosophical methods of analysis and argumentation, but rather as one who sees those methods as obstacles to final release.
+
To this it may be objected that all of classical [[Indian]] philosophy—Buddhist and [[orthodox]] alike—understood the [[Buddha]] to have denied the [[self]] tout court. To this it is sometimes replied that the later [[philosophical]] [[tradition]] simply got the [[Buddha]] wrong, at least in part because the [[Buddha]] sought to indicate something that cannot be grasped through the exercise of [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}}. On this [[interpretation]], the [[Buddha]] should be seen not as a proponent of the [[philosophical]] [[methods]] of analysis and {{Wiki|argumentation}}, but rather as one who sees those [[methods]] as [[obstacles]] to final [[release]].
  
  
  
Another reason one sometimes encounters for denying that the Buddha is a philosopher is that he rejects the characteristically philosophical activity of theorizing about matters that lack evident practical application. On this interpretation as well, those later Buddhist thinkers who did go in for the construction of theories about the ultimate nature of everything simply failed to heed or properly appreciate the Buddha's advice that we avoid theorizing for its own sake and confine our attention to those matters that are directly relevant to liberation from suffering.  
+
Another [[reason]] one sometimes encounters for denying that the [[Buddha]] is a [[philosopher]] is that he rejects the characteristically [[philosophical]] [[activity]] of theorizing about matters that lack evident {{Wiki|practical}} application. On this [[interpretation]] as well, those later [[Buddhist]] thinkers who did go in for the construction of theories about the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[nature]] of everything simply failed to heed or properly appreciate the [[Buddha's]] advice that we avoid theorizing for its [[own]] [[sake]] and confine our [[attention]] to those matters that are directly relevant to [[liberation]] from [[suffering]].  
  
On this view the teaching of non-self is not a bit of metaphysics, just some practical advice to the effect that we should avoid identifying with things that are transitory and so bound to yield dissatisfaction. What both interpretations share is the assumption that it is possible to arrive at what the Buddha himself thought without relying on the understanding of his teachings developed in the subsequent Buddhist philosophical tradition.
+
On this view the [[teaching]] of [[non-self]] is not a bit of [[metaphysics]], just some [[practical advice]] to the effect that we should avoid identifying with things that are transitory and so [[bound]] to yield [[dissatisfaction]]. What both interpretations share is the assumption that it is possible to arrive at what the [[Buddha]] himself [[thought]] without relying on the [[understanding]] of his teachings developed in the subsequent [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]].
  
  
  
This assumption may be questioned. Our knowledge of the Buddha's teachings comes by way of texts that were not written down until several centuries after his death, are in languages (Pāli, and Chinese translations of Sanskrit) other than the one he is likely to have spoken, and disagree in important respects. The first difficulty may not be as serious as it seems, given that the Buddha's discourses were probably rehearsed shortly after his death and preserved through oral transmission until the time they were committed to writing. And the second need not be insuperable either.  
+
This assumption may be questioned. Our [[knowledge]] of the [[Buddha's teachings]] comes by way of texts that were not written down until several centuries after his [[death]], are in [[languages]] ([[Pāli]], and {{Wiki|Chinese}} translations of [[Sanskrit]]) other than the one he is likely to have spoken, and disagree in important respects. The first difficulty may not be as serious as it seems, given that the [[Buddha's]] [[discourses]] were probably rehearsed shortly after his [[death]] and preserved through [[oral transmission]] until the time they were committed to [[writing]]. And the second need not be insuperable either.  
  
  
But the third is troubling, in that it suggests textual transmission involved processes of insertion and deletion in aid of one side or another in sectarian disputes. Our ancient sources attest to this: one will encounter a dispute among Buddhist thinkers where one side cites some utterance of the Buddha in support of their position, only to have the other side respond that the text from which the quotation is taken is not universally recognized as authoritatively the word of the Buddha. This suggests that our record of the Buddha's teaching may be colored by the philosophical elaboration of those teachings propounded by later thinkers in the Buddhist tradition.
+
But the third is troubling, in that it suggests textual [[transmission]] involved {{Wiki|processes}} of insertion and deletion in aid of one side or another in {{Wiki|sectarian}} [[disputes]]. Our [[ancient]] sources attest to this: one will encounter a dispute among [[Buddhist]] thinkers where one side cites some utterance of the [[Buddha]] in support of their position, only to have the other side respond that the text from which the quotation is taken is not universally [[recognized]] as authoritatively the [[word of the Buddha]]. This suggests that our record of the [[Buddha's teaching]] may be colored by the [[philosophical]] [[elaboration]] of those teachings propounded by later thinkers in the [[Buddhist tradition]].
  
  
  
Some scholars are more sanguine than others about the possibility of overcoming this difficulty, and thereby getting at what the Buddha himself had thought, as opposed to what later Buddhist philosophers thought he had thought. No position will be taken on this dispute here. We will be treating the Buddha's thought as it was understood within the later philosophical tradition that he had inspired.  
+
Some [[scholars]] are more sanguine than others about the possibility of [[overcoming]] this difficulty, and thereby getting at what the [[Buddha]] himself had [[thought]], as opposed to what later [[Buddhist philosophers]] [[thought]] he had [[thought]]. No position will be taken on this dispute here. We will be treating the [[Buddha's]] [[thought]] as it was understood within the later [[philosophical]] [[tradition]] that he had inspired.  
  
  
The resulting interpretation may or may not be faithful to his intentions. It is at least logically possible that he believed there to be a transcendent self that can only be known by mystical intuition, or that the exercise of philosophical rationality leads only to sterile theorizing and away from real emancipation. What we can say with some assurance is that this is not how the Buddhist philosophical tradition understood him. It is their understanding that will be the subject of this essay.
+
The resulting [[interpretation]] may or may not be [[faithful]] to his {{Wiki|intentions}}. It is at least [[logically]] possible that he believed there to be a [[transcendent]] [[self]] that can only be known by [[mystical]] [[intuition]], or that the exercise of [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}} leads only to sterile theorizing and away from real {{Wiki|emancipation}}. What we can say with some assurance is that this is not how the [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]] understood him. It is their [[understanding]] that will be the [[subject]] of this essay.
  
  
Line 72: Line 72:
  
  
The Buddha's basic teachings are usually summarized using the device of the Four Noble Truths:
+
The [[Buddha's]] basic teachings are usually summarized using the device of the [[Four Noble Truths]]:
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
  
     There is suffering.
+
     There is [[suffering]].
     There is the origination of suffering.
+
     There is the origination of [[suffering]].
     There is the cessation of suffering.
+
     There is the [[cessation of suffering]].
     There is a path to the cessation of suffering.
+
     There is a [[path]] to the [[cessation of suffering]].
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
  
The first of these claims might seem obvious, even when ‘suffering’ is understood to mean not mere pain but existential suffering, the sort of frustration, alienation and despair that arise out of our experience of transitoriness. But there are said to be different levels of appreciation of this truth, some quite subtle and difficult to attain; the highest of these is said to involve the realization that everything is of the nature of suffering.  
+
The first of these claims might seem obvious, even when ‘[[suffering]]’ is understood to mean not mere [[pain]] but [[existential]] [[suffering]], the sort of [[frustration]], alienation and {{Wiki|despair}} that arise out of our [[experience]] of transitoriness. But there are said to be different levels of [[appreciation]] of this [[truth]], some quite {{Wiki|subtle}} and difficult to attain; the [[highest]] of these is said to involve the [[realization]] that everything is of the [[nature]] of [[suffering]].  
  
Perhaps it is sufficient for present purposes to point out that while this is not the implausible claim that all of life's states and events are necessarily experienced as unsatisfactory, still the realization that all (oneself included) is impermanent can undermine a precondition for real enjoyment of the events in a life: that such events are meaningful by virtue of their having a place in an open-ended narrative.
+
Perhaps it is sufficient for {{Wiki|present}} purposes to point out that while this is not the implausible claim that all of life's states and events are necessarily [[experienced]] as unsatisfactory, still the [[realization]] that all (oneself included) is [[impermanent]] can undermine a precondition for real [[enjoyment]] of the events in a [[life]]: that such events are meaningful by [[virtue]] of their having a place in an open-ended {{Wiki|narrative}}.
  
  
It is with the development and elaboration of (2) that substantive philosophical controversy begins. (2) is the simple claim that there are causes and conditions for the arising of suffering. (3) then makes the obvious point that if the origination of suffering depends on causes, future suffering can be prevented by bringing about the cessation of those causes. (4) specifies a set of techniques that are said to be effective in such cessation.  
+
It is with the [[development]] and [[elaboration]] of (2) that substantive [[philosophical]] [[controversy]] begins. (2) is the simple claim that there are [[causes and conditions]] for the [[arising]] of [[suffering]]. (3) then makes the obvious point that if the origination of [[suffering]] depends on [[causes]], {{Wiki|future}} [[suffering]] can be prevented by bringing about the [[cessation]] of those [[causes]]. (4) specifies a set of [[techniques]] that are said to be effective in such [[cessation]].  
  
  
Much then hangs on the correct identification of the causes of suffering. The answer is traditionally spelled out in a list consisting of twelve links in a causal chain that begins with ignorance and ends with suffering (represented by the states of old age, disease and death). Modern scholarship has established that this list is a later compilation. For the texts that claim to convey the Buddha's own teachings give two slightly different formulations of this list, and shorter formulations containing only some of the twelve items are also found in the texts.  
+
Much then hangs on the correct identification of the [[causes of suffering]]. The answer is [[traditionally]] spelled out in a list consisting of [[twelve links]] in a [[causal chain]] that begins with [[ignorance]] and ends with [[suffering]] (represented by the states of [[old age]], {{Wiki|disease}} and [[death]]). {{Wiki|Modern}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} has established that this list is a later compilation. For the texts that claim to convey the [[Buddha's]] [[own]] teachings give two slightly different formulations of this list, and shorter formulations containing only some of the twelve items are also found in the texts.  
  
But it seems safe to say that the Buddha taught an analysis of the origins of suffering roughly along the following lines: given the existence of a fully functioning assemblage of psychophysical elements (the parts that make up a sentient being), ignorance concerning the three characteristics of sentient existence—suffering, impermanence and non-self—will lead, in the course of normal interactions with the environment, to appropriation (the identification of certain elements as ‘I’ and ‘mine’). This leads in turn to the formation of attachments, in the form of desire and aversion, and the strengthening of ignorance concerning the true nature of sentient existence. These ensure future rebirth, and thus future instances of old age, disease and death, in a potentially unending cycle.
+
But it seems safe to say that the [[Buddha]] [[taught]] an analysis of the origins of [[suffering]] roughly along the following lines: given the [[existence]] of a fully functioning assemblage of {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]] (the parts that make up a [[sentient being]]), [[ignorance]] concerning [[the three characteristics]] of [[sentient]] existence—suffering, [[impermanence]] and non-self—will lead, in the course of normal interactions with the {{Wiki|environment}}, to appropriation (the identification of certain [[elements]] as ‘I’ and ‘mine’). This leads in turn to the formation of [[attachments]], in the [[form of desire]] and [[aversion]], and the strengthening of [[ignorance]] concerning the [[true nature]] of [[sentient]] [[existence]]. These ensure {{Wiki|future}} [[rebirth]], and thus {{Wiki|future}} instances of [[old age]], {{Wiki|disease}} and [[death]], in a potentially unending cycle.
  
  
  
The key to escape from this cycle is said to lie in realization of the truth about sentient existence—that it is characterized by suffering, impermanence and non-self. But this realization is not easily achieved, since acts of appropriation have already made desire, aversion and ignorance deeply entrenched habits of mind. Thus the measures specified in (4) include various forms of training designed to replace such habits with others that are more conducive to seeing things as they are. Training in meditation is also prescribed, as a way of enhancing one's observational abilities, especially with respect to one's own psychological states. Insight is cultivated through the use of these newly developed observational powers, as informed by knowledge acquired through the exercise of philosophical rationality.  
+
The key to escape from this cycle is said to lie in [[realization]] of the [[truth]] about [[sentient]] existence—that it is characterized by [[suffering]], [[impermanence]] and [[non-self]]. But this [[realization]] is not easily achieved, since acts of appropriation have already made [[desire]], [[aversion]] and [[ignorance]] deeply entrenched [[habits]] of [[mind]]. Thus the measures specified in (4) include various [[forms]] of {{Wiki|training}} designed to replace such [[habits]] with others that are more conducive to [[seeing]] things as they are. Training in [[meditation]] is also prescribed, as a way of enhancing one's observational {{Wiki|abilities}}, especially with [[respect]] to one's [[own]] [[psychological]] states. [[Insight]] is cultivated through the use of these newly developed observational [[powers]], as informed by [[knowledge]] acquired through the exercise of [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}}.  
  
  
There is a debate in the later tradition as to whether final release can be attained through theoretical insight alone, through meditation alone, or only by using both techniques. Ch'an, for instance, is based on the premise that enlightenment can be attained through meditation alone, whereas Theravāda advocates using both but also holds that analysis alone may be sufficient for some. (This disagreement begins with a dispute over how to interpret D I.77–84.) The third option seems the most plausible, but the first is certainly of some interest given its suggestion that one can attain the ideal state for humans just by doing philosophy.
+
There is a [[debate]] in the later [[tradition]] as to whether final [[release]] can be [[attained]] through {{Wiki|theoretical}} [[insight]] alone, through [[meditation]] alone, or only by using both [[techniques]]. [[Ch'an]], for instance, is based on the premise that [[enlightenment]] can be [[attained]] through [[meditation]] alone, whereas [[Theravāda]] advocates using both but also holds that analysis alone may be sufficient for some. (This disagreement begins with a dispute over how to interpret D I.77–84.) The third option seems the most plausible, but the first is certainly of some [[interest]] given its suggestion that one can attain the {{Wiki|ideal}} [[state]] for [[humans]] just by doing [[philosophy]].
  
  
  
The Buddha seems to have held (2) to constitute the core of his discovery. He calls his teachings a ‘middle path’ between two extreme views, and it is this claim concerning the causal origins of suffering that he identifies as the key to avoiding those extremes. The extremes are eternalism, the view that persons are eternal, and annihilationism, the view that persons go utterly out of existence (usually understood to mean at death, though a term still shorter than one lifetime is not ruled out).  
+
The [[Buddha]] seems to have held (2) to constitute the core of his discovery. He calls his teachings a ‘[[middle path]]’ between two extreme [[views]], and it is this claim concerning the causal origins of [[suffering]] that he identifies as the key to avoiding those extremes. The extremes are {{Wiki|eternalism}}, the view that persons are eternal, and {{Wiki|annihilationism}}, the view that persons go utterly out of [[existence]] (usually understood to mean at [[death]], though a term still shorter than one [[lifetime]] is not ruled out).  
  
It will be apparent that eternalism requires the existence of the sort of self that the Buddha denies. What is not immediately evident is why the denial of such a self is not tantamount to the claim that the person is annihilated at death (or even sooner, depending on just how impermanent one takes the psychophysical elements to be).  
+
It will be apparent that {{Wiki|eternalism}} requires the [[existence]] of the sort of [[self]] that the [[Buddha]] denies. What is not immediately evident is why the {{Wiki|denial}} of such a [[self]] is not tantamount to the claim that the [[person]] is {{Wiki|annihilated}} at [[death]] (or even sooner, depending on just how [[impermanent]] one takes the {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]] to be).  
  
The solution to this puzzle lies in the fact that eternalism and annihilationism both share the presupposition that there is an ‘I’ whose existence might either extend beyond death or terminate at death. The idea of the ‘middle path’ is that all of life's continuities can be explained in terms of facts about a causal series of psychophysical elements. There being nothing more than a succession of these impermanent, impersonal events and states, the question of the ultimate fate of this ‘I’, the supposed owner of these elements, simply does not arise.
+
The {{Wiki|solution}} to this puzzle lies in the fact that {{Wiki|eternalism}} and {{Wiki|annihilationism}} both share the presupposition that there is an ‘I’ whose [[existence]] might either extend beyond [[death]] or terminate at [[death]]. The [[idea]] of the ‘[[middle path]]’ is that all of life's continuities can be explained in terms of facts about a causal series of {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]]. There being nothing more than a succession of these [[impermanent]], {{Wiki|impersonal}} events and states, the question of the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[fate]] of this ‘I’, the supposed [[owner]] of these [[elements]], simply does not arise.
  
  
This reductionist view of sentient beings was later articulated in terms of the distinction between two kinds of truth, conventional and ultimate. Each kind of truth has its own domain of objects, the things that are only conventionally real and the things that are ultimately real respectively. Conventionally real entities are those things that are accepted as real by common sense, but that turn out on further analysis to be wholes compounded out of simpler entities and thus not strictly speaking real at all.  
+
This reductionist view of [[sentient beings]] was later articulated in terms of the {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[two kinds of truth]], [[Wikipedia:Convention (norm)|conventional]] and [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]]. Each kind of [[truth]] has its [[own]] domain of [[objects]], the things that are only {{Wiki|conventionally}} real and the things that are [[ultimately real]] respectively. Conventionally real entities are those things that are accepted as real by {{Wiki|common sense}}, but that turn out on further analysis to be wholes [[compounded]] out of simpler entities and thus not strictly {{Wiki|speaking}} real at all.  
  
The stock example of a conventionally real entity is the chariot, which we take to be real only because it is more convenient, given our interests and cognitive limitations, to have a single name for the parts when assembled in the right way. Since our belief that there are chariots is thus due to our having a certain useful concept, the chariot is said to be a mere conceptual fiction.  
+
The stock example of a {{Wiki|conventionally}} real [[entity]] is the [[chariot]], which we take to be real only because it is more convenient, given our interests and [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] limitations, to have a single [[name]] for the parts when assembled in the right way. Since our [[belief]] that there are chariots is thus due to our having a certain useful {{Wiki|concept}}, the [[chariot]] is said to be a mere {{Wiki|conceptual}} {{Wiki|fiction}}.  
  
(This does not, however, mean that all conceptualization is falsification; only concepts that allow of reductive analysis lead to this artificial inflation of our ontology, and thus to a kind of error.) Ultimately real entities are those ultimate parts into which conceptual fictions are analyzable. An ultimately true statement is one that correctly describes how certain ultimately real entities are arranged.  
+
(This does not, however, mean that all [[conceptualization]] is [[falsification]]; only [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] that allow of {{Wiki|reductive}} analysis lead to this artificial inflation of our {{Wiki|ontology}}, and thus to a kind of error.) [[Ultimately real]] entities are those [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] parts into which {{Wiki|conceptual}} fictions are analyzable. An ultimately true statement is one that correctly describes how certain [[ultimately real]] entities are arranged.  
  
A conventionally true statement is one that, given how the ultimately real entities are arranged, would correctly describe certain conceptual fictions if they also existed. The ultimate truth concerning the relevant ultimately real entities helps explain why it should turn out to be useful to accept conventionally true statements (such as ‘King Milinda rode in a chariot’) when the objects described in those statements are mere fictions.
+
A {{Wiki|conventionally}} true statement is one that, given how the [[ultimately real]] entities are arranged, would correctly describe certain {{Wiki|conceptual}} fictions if they also existed. The [[ultimate truth]] concerning the relevant [[ultimately real]] entities helps explain why it should turn out to be useful to accept {{Wiki|conventionally}} true statements (such as ‘[[King Milinda]] rode in a [[chariot]]’) when the [[objects]] described in those statements are mere fictions.
  
  
  
Using this distinction between the two truths, the key insight of the ‘middle path’ may be expressed as follows. The ultimate truth about sentient beings is just that there is a causal series of impermanent, impersonal psychophysical elements. Since these are all impermanent, and lack other properties that would be required of an essence of the person, none of them is a self.  
+
Using this {{Wiki|distinction}} between the [[two truths]], the key [[insight]] of the ‘[[middle path]]’ may be expressed as follows. The [[ultimate truth]] about [[sentient beings]] is just that there is a causal series of [[impermanent]], {{Wiki|impersonal}} {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]]. Since these are all [[impermanent]], and lack other properties that would be required of an [[essence]] of the [[person]], none of them is a [[self]].  
  
But given the right arrangement of such entities in a causal series, it is useful to think of them as making up one thing, a person. It is thus conventionally true that there are persons, things that endure for a lifetime and possibly (if there is rebirth) longer. This is conventionally true because generally speaking there is more overall happiness and less overall pain and suffering when one part of such a series identifies with other parts of the same series.  
+
But given the right arrangement of such entities in a causal series, it is useful to think of them as making up one thing, a [[person]]. It is thus {{Wiki|conventionally}} true that there are persons, things that endure for a [[lifetime]] and possibly (if there is [[rebirth]]) longer. This is {{Wiki|conventionally}} true because generally {{Wiki|speaking}} there is more overall [[happiness]] and less overall [[pain]] and [[suffering]] when one part of such a series identifies with other parts of the same series.  
  
For instance, when the present set of psychophysical elements identifies with future elements, it is less likely to engage in behavior (such as smoking) that results in present pleasure but far greater future pain. The utility of this convention is, however, limited. Past a certain point—namely the point at which we take it too seriously, as more than just a useful fiction—it results in existential suffering. The cessation of suffering is attained by extirpating all sense of an ‘I’ that serves as agent and owner.
+
For instance, when the {{Wiki|present}} set of {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]] identifies with {{Wiki|future}} [[elements]], it is less likely to engage in {{Wiki|behavior}} (such as [[smoking]]) that results in {{Wiki|present}} [[pleasure]] but far greater {{Wiki|future}} [[pain]]. The utility of this convention is, however, limited. Past a certain point—namely the point at which we take it too seriously, as more than just a useful fiction—it results in [[existential]] [[suffering]]. The [[cessation of suffering]] is [[attained]] by extirpating all [[sense]] of an ‘I’ that serves as agent and [[owner]].
  
  
  
3. Non-Self
+
3. [[Non-Self]]
  
  
  
The Buddha's ‘middle path’ strategy can be seen as one of first arguing that there is nothing that the word ‘I’ genuinely denotes, and then explaining that our erroneous sense of an ‘I’ stems from our employment of the useful fiction represented by the concept of the person. While the second part of this strategy only receives its full articulation in the later development of the theory of two truths, the first part can be found in the Buddha's own teachings, in the form of several philosophical arguments for non-self. Best known among these is the argument from impermanence (S III.66–8), which has this basic structure:
+
The [[Buddha's]] ‘[[middle path]]’ strategy can be seen as one of first arguing that there is nothing that the [[word]] ‘I’ genuinely denotes, and then explaining that our erroneous [[sense]] of an ‘I’ stems from our employment of the useful {{Wiki|fiction}} represented by the {{Wiki|concept}} of the [[person]]. While the second part of this strategy only receives its full articulation in the later [[development]] of the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[two truths]], the first part can be found in the [[Buddha's]] [[own]] teachings, in the [[form]] of several [[philosophical]] arguments for [[non-self]]. Best known among these is the argument from [[impermanence]] (S III.66–8), which has this basic {{Wiki|structure}}:
  
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
     If there were a self it would be permanent.
+
     If there were a [[self]] it would be [[permanent]].
     None of the five kinds of psychophysical element is permanent.
+
     None of the five kinds of {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[element]] is [[permanent]].
     ∴ There is no self.
+
     ∴ There is [[no self]].
  
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
It is the fact that this argument does not contain a premise explicitly asserting that the five skandhas (classes of psychophysical element) are exhaustive of the constituents of persons, plus the fact that these are all said to be empirically observable, that leads some to claim that the Buddha did not intend to deny the existence of a self tout court.  
+
It is the fact that this argument does not contain a premise explicitly asserting that the [[five skandhas]] (classes of {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[element]]) are exhaustive of the constituents of persons, plus the fact that these are all said to be [[empirically]] observable, that leads some to claim that the [[Buddha]] did not intend to deny the [[existence]] of a [[self]] tout court.  
  
There is, however, evidence that the Buddha was generally hostile toward attempts to establish the existence of unobservable entities. In the Pohapāda Sutta (D I.178–203), for instance, the Buddha compares someone who posits an unseen seer in order to explain our introspective awareness of cognitions, to a man who has conceived a longing for the most beautiful woman in the world based solely on the thought that such a woman must surely exist.  
+
There is, however, {{Wiki|evidence}} that the [[Buddha]] was generally {{Wiki|hostile}} toward attempts to establish the [[existence]] of unobservable entities. In the Pohapāda [[Sutta]] (D I.178–203), for instance, the [[Buddha]] compares someone who posits an unseen [[seer]] in order to explain our introspective [[awareness]] of [[cognitions]], to a man who has [[conceived]] a longing for the most beautiful woman in the [[world]] based solely on the [[thought]] that such a woman must surely [[exist]].  
  
And in the Tevijja Sutta (D I.235–52), the Buddha rejects the claim of certain Brahmins to know the path to oneness with Brahman, on the grounds that no one has actually observed this Brahman. This makes more plausible the assumption that the argument has as an implicit premise the claim that there is no more to the person than the five skandhas.
+
And in the [[Tevijja Sutta]] (D I.235–52), the [[Buddha]] rejects the claim of certain [[Brahmins]] to know the [[path]] to [[oneness]] with [[Brahman]], on the grounds that no one has actually observed this [[Brahman]]. This makes more plausible the assumption that the argument has as an implicit premise the claim that there is no more to the [[person]] than the [[five skandhas]].
  
Premise (1) appears to be based on the assumption that persons undergo rebirth, together with the thought that one function of a self would be to account for diachronic personal identity. By ‘permanent’ is here meant continued existence over at least several lives. This is shown by the fact that the Buddha rules out the body as a self on the grounds that the body exists for just one lifetime.  
+
Premise (1) appears to be based on the assumption that persons undergo [[rebirth]], together with the [[thought]] that one function of a [[self]] would be to account for diachronic personal [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]]. By ‘[[permanent]]’ is here meant continued [[existence]] over at least several [[lives]]. This is shown by the fact that the [[Buddha]] {{Wiki|rules}} out the [[body]] as a [[self]] on the grounds that the [[body]] [[exists]] for just one [[lifetime]].  
  
(This also demonstrates that the Buddha did not mean by ‘impermanent’ what some later Buddhist philosophers meant, viz., existing for just a moment; the Buddhist doctrine of momentariness represents a later development.) The mental entities that make up the remaining four types of psychophysical element might seem like more promising candidates, but these are ruled out on the grounds that these all originate in dependence on contact between sense faculty and object, and last no longer than a particular sense-object-contact event.  
+
(This also demonstrates that the [[Buddha]] did not mean by ‘[[impermanent]]’ what some later [[Buddhist philosophers]] meant, viz., [[existing]] for just a [[moment]]; the [[Buddhist doctrine]] of [[momentariness]] represents a later [[development]].) The [[mental]] entities that make up the remaining four types of {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[element]] might seem like more [[promising]] candidates, but these are ruled out on the grounds that these all originate in [[dependence]] on [[contact]] between [[sense]] {{Wiki|faculty}} and [[object]], and last no longer than a particular sense-object-contact event.  
  
That he listed five kinds of psychophysical element, and not just one, shows that the Buddha embraced a kind of dualism. But this strategy for demonstrating the impermanence of the psychological elements shows that his dualism was not the sort of mind-body dualism familiar from substance ontologies like those of Descartes and of the Nyāya school of orthodox Indian philosophy. Instead of seeing the mind as the persisting bearer of such transient events as occurrences of cognition, feeling and volition, he treats ‘mind’ as a kind of aggregate term for bundles of transient mental events. These events being impermanent, they too fail to account for diachronic personal identity in the way in which a self might be expected to.
+
That he listed five kinds of {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[element]], and not just one, shows that the [[Buddha]] embraced a kind of [[dualism]]. But this strategy for demonstrating the [[impermanence]] of the [[psychological]] [[elements]] shows that his [[dualism]] was not the sort of mind-body [[dualism]] familiar from [[substance]] ontologies like those of {{Wiki|Descartes}} and of the [[Nyāya school]] of [[orthodox]] [[Indian philosophy]]. Instead of [[seeing]] the [[mind]] as the persisting bearer of such transient events as occurrences of [[cognition]], [[feeling]] and [[Wikipedia:Volition (psychology)|volition]], he treats ‘[[mind]]’ as a kind of [[aggregate]] term for bundles of transient [[mental events]]. These events being [[impermanent]], they too fail to account for diachronic personal [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] in the way in which a [[self]] might be expected to.
  
  
Another argument for non-self, which might be called the argument from control (S III.66–8), has this structure:
+
Another argument for [[non-self]], which might be called the argument from control (S III.66–8), has this {{Wiki|structure}}:
  
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
     If there were a self, one could never desire that it be changed.
+
     If there were a [[self]], one could never [[desire]] that it be changed.
     Each of the five kinds of psychophysical element is such that one can desire that it be changed.
+
     Each of the five kinds of {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[element]] is such that one can [[desire]] that it be changed.
     ∴ There is no self.
+
     ∴ There is [[no self]].
  
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
  
Premise (1) is puzzling. It appears to presuppose that the self should have complete control over itself, so that it would effortlessly adjust its state to its desires. That the self should be thought of as the locus of control is certainly plausible. Those Indian self-theorists who claim that the self is a mere passive witness recognize that the burden of proof is on them to show that the self is not an agent.  But it seems implausibly demanding to require of the self that it have complete control over itself. We do not require that vision see itself if it is to see other things.  
+
Premise (1) is puzzling. It appears to presuppose that the [[self]] should have complete control over itself, so that it would effortlessly adjust its [[state]] to its [[desires]]. That the [[self]] should be [[thought]] of as the locus of control is certainly plausible. Those [[Indian]] self-theorists who claim that the [[self]] is a mere passive {{Wiki|witness}} [[recognize]] that the [[burden]] of [[proof]] is on them to show that the [[self]] is not an agent.  But it seems implausibly demanding to require of the [[self]] that it have complete control over itself. We do not require that [[vision]] see itself if it is to see other things.  
  
The case of vision suggests an alternative interpretation, however. We might hold that vision does not see itself for the reason that this would violate an irreflexivity principle, to the effect that an entity cannot operate on itself. Indian philosophers who accept this principle cite supportive instances such as the knife that cannot cut itself and the finger-tip that cannot touch itself. If this principle is accepted, then if the self were the locus of control it would follow that it could never exercise this function on itself. A self that was the controller could never find itself in the position of seeking to change its state to one that it deemed more desirable. On this interpretation, the first premise seems to be true.  
+
The case of [[vision]] suggests an alternative [[interpretation]], however. We might hold that [[vision]] does not see itself for the [[reason]] that this would violate an irreflexivity [[principle]], to the effect that an [[entity]] cannot operate on itself. [[Indian]] [[philosophers]] who accept this [[principle]] cite supportive instances such as the knife that cannot cut itself and the finger-tip that cannot {{Wiki|touch}} itself. If this [[principle]] is accepted, then if the [[self]] were the locus of control it would follow that it could never exercise this function on itself. A [[self]] that was the controller could never find itself in the position of seeking to change its [[state]] to one that it deemed more desirable. On this [[interpretation]], the first premise seems to be true.  
  
And there is ample evidence that (2) is true:  it is difficult to imagine a bodily or psychological state over which one might not wish to exercise control. Consequently, given the assumption that the person is wholly composed of the psychophysical elements, it appears to follow that a self of this description does not exist.
+
And there is ample {{Wiki|evidence}} that (2) is true:  it is difficult to [[imagine]] a [[bodily]] or [[psychological state]] over which one might not wish to exercise control. Consequently, given the assumption that the [[person]] is wholly composed of the {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]], it appears to follow that a [[self]] of this description does not [[exist]].
  
These two arguments appear, then, to give good reason to deny a self that might ground diachronic personal identity and serve as locus of control, given the assumption that there is no more to the person than the empirically given psychophysical elements. But it now becomes something of a puzzle how one is to explain diachronic personal identity and agency.  
+
These two arguments appear, then, to give good [[reason]] to deny a [[self]] that might ground diachronic personal [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] and serve as locus of control, given the assumption that there is no more to the [[person]] than the [[empirically]] given {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]]. But it now becomes something of a puzzle how one is to explain diachronic personal [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] and agency.  
  
To start with the latter, does the argument from control not suggest that control must be exercised by something other than the psychophysical elements? This was precisely the conclusion of the Sāṃkhya school of orthodox Indian philosophy. One of their arguments for the existence of a self was that it is possible to exercise control over all the empirically given constituents of the person; while they agree with the Buddha that a self is never observed, they take the phenomena of agency to be grounds for positing a self that transcends all possible experience.
+
To start with the [[latter]], does the argument from control not suggest that control must be exercised by something other than the {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]]? This was precisely the conclusion of the [[Sāṃkhya]] school of [[orthodox]] [[Indian philosophy]]. One of their arguments for the [[existence]] of a [[self]] was that it is possible to exercise control over all the [[empirically]] given constituents of the [[person]]; while they agree with the [[Buddha]] that a [[self]] is never observed, they take the [[phenomena]] of agency to be grounds for positing a [[self]] that {{Wiki|transcends}} all possible [[experience]].
  
  
  
This line of objection to the Buddha's teaching of non-self is more commonly formulated in response to the argument from impermanence, however. Perhaps its most dramatic form is aimed at the Buddha's acceptance of the doctrines of karma and rebirth. It is clear that the body ceases to exist at death. And given the Buddha's argument that mental states all originate in dependence on sense-object contact events, it seems no psychological constituent of the person can transmigrate either.  
+
This line of objection to the [[Buddha's teaching]] of [[non-self]] is more commonly formulated in response to the argument from [[impermanence]], however. Perhaps its most dramatic [[form]] is aimed at the [[Buddha's]] [[acceptance]] of the [[doctrines]] of [[karma and rebirth]]. It is clear that the [[body]] ceases to [[exist]] at [[death]]. And given the [[Buddha's]] argument that [[mental states]] all originate in [[dependence]] on [[sense-object]] [[contact]] events, it seems no [[psychological]] constituent of the [[person]] can transmigrate either.  
  
Yet the Buddha claims that persons who have not yet achieved enlightenment will be reborn as sentient beings of some sort after they die. If there is no constituent whatever that moves from one life to the next, how could the being in the next life be the same person as the being in this life? This question becomes all the more pointed when it is added that rebirth is governed by karma, something that functions as a kind of cosmic justice: those born into fortunate circumstances do so as a result of good deeds in prior lives, while unpleasant births result from evil past deeds. Such a system of reward and punishment could be just only if the recipient of pleasant or unpleasant karmic fruit is the same person as the agent of the good or evil action. And the opponent finds it incomprehensible how this could be so in the absence of a persisting self.
+
Yet the [[Buddha]] claims that persons who have not yet achieved [[enlightenment]] will be [[reborn]] as [[sentient beings]] of some sort after they [[die]]. If there is no constituent whatever that moves from one [[life]] to the next, how could the being in the next [[life]] be the same [[person]] as the being in this [[life]]? This question becomes all the more pointed when it is added that [[rebirth]] is governed by [[karma]], something that functions as a kind of [[cosmic]] justice: those born into [[fortunate]] circumstances do so as a result of [[good deeds]] in prior [[lives]], while [[unpleasant]] [[births]] result from [[evil]] {{Wiki|past}} [[deeds]]. Such a system of reward and {{Wiki|punishment}} could be just only if the recipient of [[pleasant]] or [[unpleasant]] [[karmic]] fruit is the same [[person]] as the agent of the good or [[evil action]]. And the opponent finds it incomprehensible how this could be so in the absence of a persisting [[self]].
  
  
  
4. Karma and Rebirth
+
4. [[Karma and Rebirth]]
  
  
  
It is not just classical Indian self-theorists who have found this objection persuasive. Some Buddhists have as well. Among these Buddhists, however, this has led to the rejection not of non-self but of rebirth. (Historically this response was not unknown among East Asian Buddhists, and it is not rare among Western Buddhists today.) The evidence that the Buddha himself accepted rebirth and karma seems quite strong, however. The later tradition would distinguish between two types of discourse in the body of the Buddha's teachings: those intended for an audience of householders seeking instruction from a sage, and those intended for an audience of monastic renunciates already versed in his teachings.  
+
It is not just classical [[Indian]] self-theorists who have found this objection {{Wiki|persuasive}}. Some [[Buddhists]] have as well. Among these [[Buddhists]], however, this has led to the rejection not of [[non-self]] but of [[rebirth]]. (Historically this response was not unknown among {{Wiki|East Asian}} [[Buddhists]], and it is not rare among [[Western Buddhists]] today.) The {{Wiki|evidence}} that the [[Buddha]] himself accepted [[rebirth]] and [[karma]] seems quite strong, however. The later [[tradition]] would distinguish between two types of [[discourse]] in the [[body]] of the [[Buddha's teachings]]: those intended for an audience of householders seeking instruction from a [[Wikipedia:Sage (sophos|sage]], and those intended for an audience of [[monastic]] renunciates already versed in his teachings.  
  
  
And it would be one thing if his use of the concepts of karma and rebirth were limited to the former. For then such appeals could be explained away as another instance of the Buddha's pedagogical skill (commonly referred to as upāya). The idea would be that householders who fail to comply with the most basic demands of morality are not likely (for reasons to be discussed shortly) to make significant progress toward the cessation of suffering, and the teaching of karma and rebirth, even if not strictly speaking true, does give those who accept it a (prudential) reason to be moral. But this sort of ‘noble lie’ justification for the Buddha teaching a doctrine he does not accept fails in the face of the evidence that he also taught it to quite advanced monastics (e.g., A III.33).  
+
And it would be one thing if his use of the [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]] of [[karma and rebirth]] were limited to the former. For then such appeals could be explained away as another instance of the [[Buddha's]] pedagogical skill (commonly referred to as [[upāya]]). The [[idea]] would be that householders who fail to comply with the most basic demands of [[morality]] are not likely (for [[reasons]] to be discussed shortly) to make significant progress toward the [[cessation of suffering]], and the [[teaching]] of [[karma and rebirth]], even if not strictly {{Wiki|speaking}} true, does give those who accept it a (prudential) [[reason]] to be [[moral]]. But this sort of ‘[[noble]] lie’ {{Wiki|justification}} for the [[Buddha teaching]] a [[doctrine]] he does not accept fails in the face of the {{Wiki|evidence}} that he also [[taught]] it to quite advanced [[monastics]] (e.g., A III.33).  
  
And what he taught is not the version of karma popular in certain circles today, according to which, for instance, an act done out of hatred makes the agent somewhat more disposed to perform similar actions out of similar motives in the future, which in turn makes negative experiences more likely for the agent. What the Buddha teaches is instead the far stricter view that each action has its own specific consequence for the agent, the hedonic nature of which is determined in accordance with causal laws and in such a way as to require rebirth as long as action continues. So if there is a conflict between the doctrine of non-self and the teaching of karma and rebirth, it is not to be resolved by weakening the Buddha's commitment to the latter.
+
And what he [[taught]] is not the version of [[karma]] popular in certain circles today, according to which, for instance, an act done out of [[hatred]] makes the agent somewhat more disposed to perform similar [[actions]] out of similar motives in the {{Wiki|future}}, which in turn makes negative [[experiences]] more likely for the agent. What the [[Buddha]] teaches is instead the far stricter view that each [[action]] has its [[own]] specific consequence for the agent, the {{Wiki|hedonic}} [[nature]] of which is determined in accordance with causal laws and in such a way as to require [[rebirth]] as long as [[action]] continues. So if there is a conflict between the [[doctrine of non-self]] and the [[teaching]] of [[karma and rebirth]], it is not to be resolved by weakening the [[Buddha's]] commitment to the [[latter]].
  
  
  
The Sanskrit term karma literally means ‘action’. What is nowadays referred to somewhat loosely as the theory of karma is, speaking more strictly, the view that there is a causal relationship between action (karma) and ‘fruit’ (phala), the latter being an experience of pleasure, pain or indifference for the agent of the action. This is the view that the Buddha appears to have accepted in its most straightforward form. Actions are said to be of three types: bodily, verbal and mental. The Buddha insists, however, that by action is meant not the movement or change involved, but rather the volition or intention that brought about the change.  
+
The [[Sanskrit]] term [[karma]] literally means ‘[[action]]’. What is nowadays referred to somewhat loosely as the [[theory of karma]] is, {{Wiki|speaking}} more strictly, the view that there is a causal relationship between [[action]] ([[karma]]) and ‘fruit’ ([[phala]]), the [[latter]] being an [[experience]] of [[pleasure]], [[pain]] or [[indifference]] for the agent of the [[action]]. This is the view that the [[Buddha]] appears to have accepted in its most straightforward [[form]]. [[Actions]] are said to be of three types: [[bodily]], [[verbal]] and [[mental]]. The [[Buddha]] insists, however, that by [[action]] is meant not the {{Wiki|movement}} or change involved, but rather the [[Wikipedia:Volition (psychology)|volition]] or [[intention]] that brought about the change.  
  
As Gombrich (2009) points out, the Buddha's insistence on this point reflects the transition from an earlier ritualistic view of action to a view that brings action within the purview of ethics. For it is when actions are seen as subject to moral assessment that intention becomes relevant. One does not, for instance, perform the morally blameworthy action of speaking insultingly to an elder just by making sounds that approximate to the pronunciation of profanities in the presence of an elder; parrots and prelinguistic children can do as much. What matters for moral assessment is the mental state (if any) that produced the bodily, verbal or mental change.  
+
As Gombrich (2009) points out, the [[Buddha's]] insistence on this point reflects the transition from an earlier [[ritualistic]] view of [[action]] to a view that brings [[action]] within the purview of [[ethics]]. For it is when [[actions]] are seen as [[subject]] to [[moral]] assessment that [[intention]] becomes relevant. One does not, for instance, perform the {{Wiki|morally}} blameworthy [[action]] of {{Wiki|speaking}} insultingly to an elder just by [[making sounds]] that approximate to the pronunciation of profanities in the presence of an elder; parrots and prelinguistic children can do as much. What matters for [[moral]] assessment is the [[mental state]] (if any) that produced the [[bodily]], [[verbal]] or [[mental]] change.  
  
  
And it is the occurrence of these mental states that is said to cause the subsequent occurrence of hedonically good, bad and neutral experiences. More specifically, it is the occurrence of the three ‘defiled’ mental states that brings about karmic fruit. The three defilements (kleśas) are desire, aversion and ignorance. And we are told quite specifically (A III.33) that actions performed by an agent in whom these three defilements have been destroyed do not have karmic consequences; such an agent is experiencing their last birth.
+
And it is the occurrence of these [[mental states]] that is said to [[cause]] the subsequent occurrence of hedonically good, bad and [[neutral]] [[experiences]]. More specifically, it is the occurrence of the three ‘[[defiled]]’ [[mental states]] that brings about [[karmic]] fruit. The three [[defilements]] ([[kleśas]]) are [[desire]], [[aversion]] and [[ignorance]]. And we are told quite specifically (A III.33) that [[actions]] performed by an agent in whom these three [[defilements]] have been destroyed do not have [[karmic]] {{Wiki|consequences}}; such an agent is experiencing their last [[birth]].
  
  
  
Some caution is required in understanding this claim about the defilements. The Buddha seems to be saying that it is possible to act not only without ignorance, but also in the absence of desire or aversion, yet it is difficult to see how there could be intentional action without some positive or negative motivation. To see one's way around this difficulty, one must realize that by ‘desire’ and ‘aversion’ are meant those positive and negative motives respectively that are colored by ignorance, viz. ignorance concerning suffering, impermanence and non-self. Presumably the enlightened person, while knowing the truth about these matters, can still engage in motivated action.  
+
Some caution is required in [[understanding]] this claim about the [[defilements]]. The [[Buddha]] seems to be saying that it is possible to act not only without [[ignorance]], but also in the absence of [[desire]] or [[aversion]], yet it is difficult to see how there could be [[intentional action]] without some positive or negative [[motivation]]. To see one's way around this difficulty, one must realize that by ‘[[desire]]’ and ‘[[aversion]]’ are meant those positive and negative motives respectively that are colored by [[ignorance]], viz. [[ignorance]] concerning [[suffering]], [[impermanence]] and [[non-self]]. Presumably the [[enlightened person]], while [[knowing]] the [[truth]] about these matters, can still engage in motivated [[action]].  
  
Their actions are not based on the presupposition that there is an ‘I’ for which those actions can have significance. Ignorance concerning these matters perpetuates rebirth, and thus further occasions for existential suffering, by facilitating a motivational structure that reinforces one's ignorance.  
+
Their [[actions]] are not based on the presupposition that there is an ‘I’ for which those [[actions]] can have significance. [[Ignorance]] concerning these matters perpetuates [[rebirth]], and thus further occasions for [[existential]] [[suffering]], by facilitating a motivational {{Wiki|structure}} that reinforces one's [[ignorance]].  
  
We can now see how compliance with common-sense morality could be seen as an initial step on the path to the cessation of suffering. While the presence of ignorance makes all action—even that deemed morally good—karmically potent, those actions commonly considered morally evil are especially powerful reinforcers of ignorance, in that they stem from the assumption that the agent's welfare is of paramount importance. While recognition of the moral value of others may still involve the conceit that there is an ‘I’, it can nonetheless constitute progress toward dissolution of the sense of self.
+
We can now see how compliance with {{Wiki|common-sense}} [[morality]] could be seen as an initial step on the [[path]] to the [[cessation of suffering]]. While the presence of [[ignorance]] makes all action—even that deemed {{Wiki|morally}} good—karmically potent, those [[actions]] commonly considered {{Wiki|morally}} [[evil]] are especially powerful reinforcers of [[ignorance]], in that they stem from the assumption that the agent's {{Wiki|welfare}} is of paramount importance. While {{Wiki|recognition}} of the [[moral]] value of others may still involve the [[conceit]] that there is an ‘I’, it can nonetheless constitute progress toward dissolution of the [[sense]] of [[self]].
  
  
  
This excursus into what the Buddha meant by karma may help us see how his middle path strategy could be used to reply to the objection to non-self from rebirth. That objection was that the reward and punishment generated by karma across lives could never be deserved in the absence of a transmigrating self. The middle path strategy generally involves locating and rejecting an assumption shared by a pair of extreme views.  
+
This excursus into what the [[Buddha]] meant by [[karma]] may help us see how his [[middle path]] strategy could be used to reply to the objection to [[non-self]] from [[rebirth]]. That objection was that the reward and {{Wiki|punishment}} generated by [[karma]] across [[lives]] could never be deserved in the absence of a transmigrating [[self]]. The [[middle path]] strategy generally involves locating and rejecting an assumption shared by a pair of extreme [[views]].  
  
In this case the views will be (1) that the person in the later life deserves the fruit generated by the action in the earlier life, and (2) that this person does not deserve the fruit. One assumption shared by (1) and (2) is that persons deserve reward and punishment depending on the moral character of their actions, and one might deny this assumption. But that would be tantamount to moral nihilism, and a middle path is said to avoid nihilisms (such as annihilationism).  
+
In this case the [[views]] will be (1) that the [[person]] in the later [[life]] deserves the fruit generated by the [[action]] in the earlier [[life]], and (2) that this [[person]] does not deserve the fruit. One assumption shared by (1) and (2) is that persons deserve reward and {{Wiki|punishment}} depending on the [[moral]] [[character]] of their [[actions]], and one might deny this assumption. But that would be tantamount to [[moral]] [[nihilism]], and a [[middle path]] is said to avoid nihilisms (such as {{Wiki|annihilationism}}).  
  
A more promising alternative might be to deny that there are ultimately such things as persons that could bear moral properties like desert. This is what the Buddha seems to mean when he asserts that the earlier and the later person are neither the same nor different (S II.62; S II.76; S II.113). Since any two existing things must be either identical or distinct, to say of the two persons that they are neither is to say that strictly speaking they do not exist.
+
A more [[promising]] alternative might be to deny that there are ultimately such things as persons that could bear [[moral]] properties like desert. This is what the [[Buddha]] seems to mean when he asserts that the earlier and the later [[person]] are neither the same nor different (S II.62; S II.76; S II.113). Since any two [[existing]] things must be either [[identical]] or {{Wiki|distinct}}, to say of the two persons that they are neither is to say that strictly {{Wiki|speaking}} they do not [[exist]].
  
  
  
This alternative is more promising because it avoids moral nihilism. For it allows one to assert that persons and their moral properties are conventionally real. To say this is to say that given our interests and cognitive limitations, we do better at achieving our aim—minimizing overall pain and suffering—by acting as though there are persons with morally significant properties. Ultimately there are just impersonal entities and events in causal sequence: ignorance, the sorts of desires that ignorance facilitates, an intention formed on the basis of such a desire, a bodily, verbal or mental action, a feeling of pleasure, pain or indifference, and an occasion of suffering.  
+
This alternative is more [[promising]] because it avoids [[moral]] [[nihilism]]. For it allows one to assert that persons and their [[moral]] properties are {{Wiki|conventionally}} real. To say this is to say that given our interests and [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] limitations, we do better at achieving our aim—minimizing overall [[pain]] and suffering—by acting as though there are persons with {{Wiki|morally}} significant properties. Ultimately there are just {{Wiki|impersonal}} entities and events in causal sequence: [[ignorance]], the sorts of [[desires]] that [[ignorance]] facilitates, an [[intention]] formed on the basis of such a [[desire]], a [[bodily]], [[verbal]] or [[mental action]], a [[feeling]] of [[pleasure]], [[pain]] or [[indifference]], and an occasion of [[suffering]].  
  
The claim is that this situation is usefully thought of as, for instance, a person who performs an evil deed due to their ignorance of the true nature of things, receives the unpleasant fruit they deserve in the next life, and suffers through their continuing on the wheel of saṃsāra. It is useful to think of the situation in this way because it helps us locate the appropriate places to intervene to prevent future pain (the evil deed) and future suffering (ignorance).
+
The claim is that this situation is usefully [[thought]] of as, for instance, a [[person]] who performs an [[evil deed]] due to their [[ignorance]] of the [[true nature of things]], receives the [[unpleasant]] fruit they deserve in the next [[life]], and [[suffers]] through their continuing on the [[wheel]] of [[saṃsāra]]. It is useful to think of the situation in this way because it helps us locate the appropriate places to intervene to prevent {{Wiki|future}} [[pain]] (the [[evil deed]]) and {{Wiki|future}} [[suffering]] ([[ignorance]]).
  
  
  
It is no doubt quite difficult to believe that karma and rebirth exist in the form that the Buddha claims. It is said that their existence can be confirmed by those who have developed the power of retrocognition through advanced yogic technique. But this is of little help to those not already convinced that meditation is a reliable means of knowledge. What can be said with some assurance is that karma and rebirth are not inconsistent with non-self. Rebirth without transmigration is logically possible.
+
It is no [[doubt]] quite difficult to believe that [[karma and rebirth]] [[exist]] in the [[form]] that the [[Buddha]] claims. It is said that their [[existence]] can be confirmed by those who have developed the power of retrocognition through advanced [[yogic]] technique. But this is of little help to those not already convinced that [[meditation]] is a reliable means of [[knowledge]]. What can be said with some assurance is that [[karma and rebirth]] are not inconsistent with [[non-self]]. [[Rebirth]] without [[transmigration]] is [[logically]] possible.
  
  
  
5. Attitude toward Reason
+
5. [[Attitude]] toward [[Reason]]
  
  
When the Buddha says that a person in one life and the person in another life are neither the same nor different, one's first response might be to take ‘different’ to mean something other than ‘not the same’. But while this is possible in English given the ambiguity of ‘the same’, it is not possible in the Pāli source, where the Buddha is represented as unambiguously denying both numerical identity and numerical distinctness.  
+
When the [[Buddha]] says that a [[person]] in one [[life]] and the [[person]] in another [[life]] are neither the same nor different, one's first response might be to take ‘different’ to mean something other than ‘not the same’. But while this is possible in English given the [[ambiguity]] of ‘the same’, it is not possible in the [[Pāli]] source, where the [[Buddha]] is represented as unambiguously denying both numerical [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]] and numerical distinctness.  
  
This has led some to wonder whether the Buddha does not employ a deviant logic. Such suspicions are strengthened by those cases where the options are not two but four, cases of the so-called tetralemma (catuṣkoṭi). For instance, when the Buddha is questioned about the post-mortem status of the enlightened person or arhat (e.g., at M I.483–8)  the possibilities are listed as: (1) the arhat continues to exist after death, (2) does not exist after death, (3) both exists and does not exist after death, and (4) neither exists nor does not exist after death.
+
This has led some to [[wonder]] whether the [[Buddha]] does not employ a deviant [[logic]]. Such suspicions are strengthened by those cases where the options are not two but four, cases of the so-called [[tetralemma]] ([[catuṣkoṭi]]). For instance, when the [[Buddha]] is questioned about the [[post-mortem]] {{Wiki|status}} of the [[enlightened person]] or [[arhat]] (e.g., at M I.483–8)  the possibilities are listed as: (1) the [[arhat]] continues to [[exist]] after [[death]], (2) does not [[exist]] after [[death]], (3) both [[exists]] and does not [[exist]] after [[death]], and (4) [[neither exists]] [[nor does not exist]] after [[death]].
  
  When the Buddha rejects both (1) and (2) we get a repetition of ‘neither the same nor different’. But when he goes on to entertain, and then reject, (3) and (4) the logical difficulties are compounded. Since each of (3) and (4) appears to be formally contradictory, to entertain either is to entertain the possibility that a contradiction might be true. And their denial seems tantamount to affirmation of excluded middle, which is prima facie incompatible with the denial of both (1) and (2). One might wonder whether we are here in the presence of the mystical.
+
  When the [[Buddha]] rejects both (1) and (2) we get a repetition of ‘neither the same nor different’. But when he goes on to entertain, and then reject, (3) and (4) the [[logical]] difficulties are [[compounded]]. Since each of (3) and (4) appears to be formally [[contradictory]], to entertain either is to entertain the possibility that a {{Wiki|contradiction}} might be true. And their {{Wiki|denial}} seems tantamount to [[affirmation]] of excluded middle, which is [[Wikipedia:Prima facie|prima facie]] incompatible with the {{Wiki|denial}} of both (1) and (2). One might [[wonder]] whether we are here in the presence of the [[mystical]].
  
  
  
There were some Buddhist philosophers who took ‘neither the same nor different’ in this way. These were the Personalists (Pudgalavādins), who were so called because they affirmed the ultimate existence of the person as something named and conceptualized in dependence on the psychophysical elements. They claimed that the person is neither identical with nor distinct from the psychophysical elements.  
+
There were some [[Buddhist philosophers]] who took ‘neither the same nor different’ in this way. These were the Personalists ([[Pudgalavādins]]), who were so called because they [[affirmed]] the [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]] [[existence]] of the [[person]] as something named and [[conceptualized]] in [[dependence]] on the {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]]. They claimed that the [[person]] is neither [[identical]] with nor {{Wiki|distinct}} from the {{Wiki|psychophysical}} [[elements]].  
  
  
They were prepared to accept, as a consequence, that nothing whatever can be said about the relation between person and elements. But their view was rejected by most Buddhist philosophers, in part on the grounds that it quickly leads to an ineffability paradox: one can say neither that the person's relation to the elements is inexpressible, nor that it is not inexpressible.  
+
They were prepared to accept, as a consequence, that nothing whatever can be said about the [[relation]] between [[person]] and [[elements]]. But their view was rejected by most [[Buddhist philosophers]], in part on the grounds that it quickly leads to an ineffability [[paradox]]: one can say neither that the person's [[relation]] to the [[elements]] is inexpressible, nor that it is not inexpressible.  
  
The consensus view was instead that the fact that the person can be said to be neither identical with nor distinct from the elements is grounds for taking the person to be a mere conceptual fiction. Concerning the persons in the two lives, they understood the negations involved in ‘neither the same nor different’ to be of the commitmentless variety, i.e., to function like illocutionary negation.  
+
The consensus view was instead that the fact that the [[person]] can be said to be neither [[identical]] with nor {{Wiki|distinct}} from the [[elements]] is grounds for taking the [[person]] to be a mere {{Wiki|conceptual}} {{Wiki|fiction}}. Concerning the persons in the two [[lives]], they understood the negations involved in ‘neither the same nor different’ to be of the commitmentless variety, i.e., to function like illocutionary {{Wiki|negation}}.  
  
If we agree that the statement ‘7 is green’ is semantically ill-formed, on the grounds that abstract objects such as numbers do not have colors, then we might go on to say, ‘Do not say that 7 is green, and do not say that it is not green either’. There is no contradiction here, since the illocutionary negation operator ‘do not say’ generates no commitment to an alternative characterization.
+
If we agree that the statement ‘7 is [[green]]’ is {{Wiki|semantically}} ill-formed, on the grounds that abstract [[objects]] such as numbers do not have colors, then we might go on to say, ‘Do not say that 7 is [[green]], and do not say that it is not [[green]] either’. There is no {{Wiki|contradiction}} here, since the illocutionary {{Wiki|negation}} operator ‘do not say’ generates no commitment to an alternative characterization.
  
  
  
There is also evidence that claims of type (3) involve parameterization. For instance, the claim about the arhat would be that there is some respect in which they can be said to exist after death, and some other respect in which they can be said to no longer exist after death. Entertaining such a proposition does not require that one believe there might be true contradictions.  
+
There is also {{Wiki|evidence}} that claims of type (3) involve parameterization. For instance, the claim about the [[arhat]] would be that there is some [[respect]] in which they can be said to [[exist]] after [[death]], and some other [[respect]] in which they can be said to no longer [[exist]] after [[death]]. Entertaining such a proposition does not require that one believe there might be true contradictions.  
  
  
And while claims of type (4) would seem to be logically equivalent to those of type (3) (regardless of whether or not they involve parameterization), the tradition treated this type as asserting that the subject is beyond all conceptualization. To reject the type (4) claim about the arhat is to close off one natural response to the rejections of the first three claims: that the status of the arhat after death transcends rational understanding. That the Buddha rejected all four possibilities concerning this and related questions is not evidence that he employed a deviant logic.
+
And while claims of type (4) would seem to be [[logically]] {{Wiki|equivalent}} to those of type (3) (regardless of whether or not they involve parameterization), the [[tradition]] treated this type as asserting that the [[subject]] is beyond all [[conceptualization]]. To reject the type (4) claim about the [[arhat]] is to close off one natural response to the rejections of the first three claims: that the {{Wiki|status}} of the [[arhat]] after [[death]] {{Wiki|transcends}} [[rational]] [[understanding]]. That the [[Buddha]] rejected all four possibilities concerning this and related questions is not {{Wiki|evidence}} that he employed a deviant [[logic]].
  
  
  
The Buddha's response to questions like those concerning the arhat is sometimes cited in defense of a different claim about his attitude toward rationality. This is the claim that the Buddha was essentially a pragmatist, someone who rejects philosophical theorizing for its own sake and employs philosophical rationality only to the extent that doing so can help solve the practical problem of eliminating suffering.  
+
The [[Buddha's]] response to questions like those concerning the [[arhat]] is sometimes cited in defense of a different claim about his [[attitude]] toward {{Wiki|rationality}}. This is the claim that the [[Buddha]] was [[essentially]] a {{Wiki|pragmatist}}, someone who rejects [[philosophical]] theorizing for its [[own]] [[sake]] and employs [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}} only to the extent that doing so can help solve the {{Wiki|practical}} problem of eliminating [[suffering]].  
  
The Buddha does seem to be embracing something like this attitude when he defends his refusal to answer questions like that about the arhat, or whether the series of lives has a beginning, or whether the living principle (jīva) is identical with the body. He calls all the possible views with respect to such questions distractions insofar as answering them would not lead to the cessation of the defilements and thus to the end of suffering.  
+
The [[Buddha]] does seem to be embracing something like this [[attitude]] when he defends his refusal to answer questions like that about the [[arhat]], or whether the series of [[lives]] has a beginning, or whether the living [[principle]] (jīva) is [[identical]] with the [[body]]. He calls all the possible [[views]] with [[respect]] to such questions {{Wiki|distractions}} insofar as answering them would not lead to the [[cessation]] of the [[defilements]] and thus to the end of [[suffering]].  
  
And in a famous simile (M I.429) he compares someone who insists that the Buddha answer these questions to someone who has been wounded by an arrow but will not have the wound treated until they are told who shot the arrow, what sort of wood the arrow is made of, and the like.
+
And in a famous simile (M I.429) he compares someone who insists that the [[Buddha]] answer these questions to someone who has been wounded by an arrow but will not have the wound treated until they are told who shot the arrow, what sort of [[wood]] the arrow is made of, and the like.
  
  
  
Passages such as these surely attest to the great importance the Buddha placed on sharing his insights to help others overcome suffering. But this is consistent with the belief that philosophical rationality may be used to answer questions that lack evident connection with pressing practical concerns. And on at least one occasion the Buddha does just this.  
+
Passages such as these surely attest to the great importance the [[Buddha]] placed on sharing his [[insights]] to help others overcome [[suffering]]. But this is consistent with the [[belief]] that [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}} may be used to answer questions that lack evident [[connection]] with pressing {{Wiki|practical}} concerns. And on at least one occasion the [[Buddha]] does just this.  
  
Pressed to give his answers to the questions about the arhat and the like, the Buddha first rejects all the possibilities of the tetralemma, and defends his refusal on the grounds that such theories are not conducive to liberation from saṃsāra.  
+
Pressed to give his answers to the questions about the [[arhat]] and the like, the [[Buddha]] first rejects all the possibilities of the [[tetralemma]], and defends his refusal on the grounds that such theories are not conducive to [[liberation]] from [[saṃsāra]].  
  
But when his questioner shows signs of thereby losing confidence in the value of the Buddha's teachings about the path to the cessation of suffering, the Buddha responds with the example of a fire that goes out after exhausting its fuel. If one were asked where this fire has gone, the Buddha points out, one could consistently deny that it has gone to the north, to the south, or in any other direction.  
+
But when his questioner shows [[signs]] of thereby losing [[confidence]] in the value of the [[Buddha's teachings]] about the [[path]] to the [[cessation of suffering]], the [[Buddha]] responds with the example of a [[fire]] that goes out after exhausting its fuel. If one were asked where this [[fire]] has gone, the [[Buddha]] points out, one could consistently deny that it has gone to the [[north]], to the [[south]], or in any other [[direction]].  
  
This is so for the simple reason that the questions ‘Has it gone to the north?’, ‘Has it gone to the south?’, etc., all share the false presupposition that the fire continues to exist. Likewise the questions about the arhat and the like all share the false presupposition that there is such a thing as a person who might either continue to exist after death, cease to exist at death, etc. The difficulty with these questions is not that they try to extend philosophical rationality beyond its legitimate domain, as the handmaiden of soteriologically useful practice. It is rather that they rest on a false presupposition—something that is disclosed through the employment of philosophical rationality.
+
This is so for the simple [[reason]] that the questions ‘Has it gone to the [[north]]?’, ‘Has it gone to the [[south]]?’, etc., all share the false presupposition that the [[fire]] continues to [[exist]]. Likewise the questions about the [[arhat]] and the like all share the false presupposition that there is such a thing as a [[person]] who might either continue to [[exist]] after [[death]], cease to [[exist]] at [[death]], etc. The difficulty with these questions is not that they try to extend [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}} beyond its legitimate domain, as the handmaiden of [[soteriologically]] useful practice. It is rather that they rest on a false presupposition—something that is disclosed through the employment of [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}}.
  
  
  
A different sort of challenge to the claim that the Buddha valued philosophical rationality for its own sake comes from the role played by authority in Buddhist soteriology. For instance, in the Buddhist tradition one sometimes encounters the claim that only enlightened persons such as the Buddha can know all the details of karmic causation.  
+
A different sort of challenge to the claim that the [[Buddha]] valued [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}} for its [[own]] [[sake]] comes from the role played by authority in [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|soteriology}}. For instance, in the [[Buddhist tradition]] one sometimes encounters the claim that only [[enlightened]] persons such as the [[Buddha]] can know all the details of [[karmic causation]].  
  
And to the extent that the moral rules are thought to be determined by the details of karmic causation, this might be taken to mean that our knowledge of the moral rules is dependent on the authority of the Buddha. Again, the subsequent development of Buddhist philosophy seems to have been constrained by the need to make theory compatible with certain key claims of the Buddha.  
+
And to the extent that the [[moral rules]] are [[thought]] to be determined by the details of [[karmic causation]], this might be taken to mean that our [[knowledge]] of the [[moral rules]] is dependent on the authority of the [[Buddha]]. Again, the subsequent [[development]] of [[Buddhist philosophy]] seems to have been constrained by the need to make {{Wiki|theory}} compatible with certain key claims of the [[Buddha]].  
  
For instance, one school developed an elaborate form of four-dimensionalism, not because of any deep dissatisfaction with presentism, but because they believed the non-existence of the past and the future to be incompatible with the Buddha's alleged ability to cognize past and future events.  
+
For instance, one school developed an elaborate [[form]] of four-dimensionalism, not because of any deep [[dissatisfaction]] with presentism, but because they believed the [[non-existence]] of the {{Wiki|past}} and the {{Wiki|future}} to be incompatible with the [[Buddha's]] alleged ability to {{Wiki|cognize}} {{Wiki|past}} and {{Wiki|future}} events.  
  
And some modern scholars go so far as to wonder whether non-self functions as anything more than a sort of linguistic taboo against the use of words like ‘I’  and ‘self’ in the Buddhist tradition (Collins 1982: 183). The suggestion is that just as in some other religious traditions the views of the founder or the statements of scripture trump all other considerations, including any views arrived at through the free exercise of rational inquiry, so in Buddhism as well there can be at best only a highly constrained arena for the deployment of philosophical rationality.
+
And some {{Wiki|modern}} [[scholars]] go so far as to [[wonder]] whether [[non-self]] functions as anything more than a sort of {{Wiki|linguistic}} {{Wiki|taboo}} against the use of words like ‘I’  and ‘[[self]]’ in the [[Buddhist tradition]] (Collins 1982: 183). The suggestion is that just as in some other [[religious]] [[traditions]] the [[views]] of the founder or the statements of [[scripture]] trump all other considerations, [[including]] any [[views]] arrived at through the free exercise of [[rational]] inquiry, so in [[Buddhism]] as well there can be at best only a highly constrained arena for the deployment of [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}}.
  
  
  
Now it could be that while this is true of the tradition that developed out of the Buddha's teachings, the Buddha himself held the unfettered use of rationality in quite high esteem. This would seem to conflict with what he is represented as saying in response to the report that he arrived at his conclusions through reasoning and analysis alone: that such a report is libelous, since he possesses a number of superhuman cognitive powers (M I.68).  
+
Now it could be that while this is true of the [[tradition]] that developed out of the [[Buddha's teachings]], the [[Buddha]] himself held the unfettered use of {{Wiki|rationality}} in quite high esteem. This would seem to conflict with what he is represented as saying in response to the report that he arrived at his conclusions through {{Wiki|reasoning}} and analysis alone: that such a report is libelous, since he possesses a number of superhuman [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[powers]] (M I.68).  
  
But at least some scholars take this passage to be not the Buddha's own words but an expression of later devotionalist concerns (Gombrich 2009: 164). Indeed one does find a spirited discussion within the tradition concerning the question whether the Buddha is omniscient, a discussion that may well reflect competition between Buddhism and those Brahmanical schools that posit an omniscient creator.   
+
But at least some [[scholars]] take this passage to be not the [[Buddha's]] [[own]] words but an expression of later devotionalist concerns (Gombrich 2009: 164). Indeed one does find a spirited [[discussion]] within the [[tradition]] concerning the question whether the [[Buddha]] is [[omniscient]], a [[discussion]] that may well reflect competition between [[Buddhism]] and those [[Brahmanical]] schools that posit an [[omniscient]] creator.   
  
And at least for the most part the Buddhist tradition is careful not to attribute to the Buddha the sort of omniscience usually ascribed to an all-perfect being: the actual cognition, at any one time, of all truths. Instead a Buddha is said to be omniscient only in the much weaker sense of always having the ability to cognize any individual fact relevant to the soteriological project, viz. the details of their own past lives, the workings of the karmic causal laws, and whether a given individual's defilements have been extirpated.  
+
And at least for the most part the [[Buddhist tradition]] is careful not to attribute to the [[Buddha]] the sort of [[omniscience]] usually ascribed to an all-perfect being: the actual [[cognition]], at any one time, of all [[truths]]. Instead a [[Buddha]] is said to be [[omniscient]] only in the much weaker [[sense]] of always having the ability to {{Wiki|cognize}} any {{Wiki|individual}} fact relevant to the [[soteriological]] project, viz. the details of their [[own]] [[past lives]], the workings of the [[karmic]] causal laws, and whether a given individual's [[defilements]] have been extirpated.  
  
Moreover, these abilities are said to be ones that a Buddha acquires through a specific course of training, and thus ones that others may reasonably aspire to as well. The attitude of the later tradition seems to be that while one could discover the relevant facts on one's own, it would be more reasonable to take advantage of the fact that the Buddha has already done all the epistemic labor involved. When we arrive in a new town we could always find our final destination through trial and error, but it would make more sense to ask someone who already knows their way about.
+
Moreover, these {{Wiki|abilities}} are said to be ones that a [[Buddha]] acquires through a specific course of {{Wiki|training}}, and thus ones that others may reasonably aspire to as well. The [[attitude]] of the later [[tradition]] seems to be that while one could discover the relevant facts on one's [[own]], it would be more reasonable to take advantage of the fact that the [[Buddha]] has already done all the {{Wiki|epistemic}} labor involved. When we arrive in a new town we could always find our final destination through trial and error, but it would make more [[sense]] to ask someone who already [[knows]] their way about.
  
  
  
The Buddhist philosophical tradition grew out of earlier efforts to systematize the Buddha's teachings. Within a century or two of the death of the Buddha, exegetical differences led to debates concerning the Buddha's true intention on some matter, such as that between the Personalists and others over the status of the person.  
+
The [[Buddhist]] [[philosophical]] [[tradition]] grew out of earlier efforts to systematize the [[Buddha's teachings]]. Within a century or two of the [[death of the Buddha]], {{Wiki|exegetical}} differences led to [[debates]] concerning the [[Buddha's]] true [[intention]] on some {{Wiki|matter}}, such as that between the Personalists and others over the {{Wiki|status}} of the [[person]].  
  
While the parties to these debates use many of the standard tools and techniques of philosophy, they were still circumscribed by the assumption that the Buddha's views on the matter at hand are authoritative. In time, however, the discussion widened to include interlocutors representing various Brahmanical systems. Since the latter did not take the Buddha's word as authoritative, Buddhist thinkers were required to defend their positions in other ways.  
+
While the parties to these [[debates]] use many of the standard tools and [[techniques]] of [[philosophy]], they were still circumscribed by the assumption that the [[Buddha's]] [[views]] on the {{Wiki|matter}} at hand are authoritative. In time, however, the [[discussion]] widened to include interlocutors representing various [[Brahmanical]] systems. Since the [[latter]] did not take the [[Buddha's]] [[word]] as authoritative, [[Buddhist]] thinkers were required to defend their positions in other ways.  
  
The resulting debate (which continued for about nine centuries) touched on most of the topics now considered standard in metaphysics, epistemology and philosophy of language, and was characterized by considerable sophistication in philosophical methodology. What the Buddha would have thought of these developments we cannot say with any certainty. What we can say is that many Buddhists have believed that the unfettered exercise of philosophical rationality is quite consistent with his teachings.
+
The resulting [[debate]] (which continued for about nine centuries) touched on most of the topics now considered standard in [[metaphysics]], epistemology and [[philosophy]] of [[language]], and was characterized by considerable {{Wiki|sophistication}} in [[philosophical]] [[Wikipedia:scientific method|methodology]]. What the [[Buddha]] would have [[thought]] of these developments we cannot say with any {{Wiki|certainty}}. What we can say is that many [[Buddhists]] have believed that the unfettered exercise of [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|rationality}} is quite consistent with his teachings.
  
  
  
Bibliography
+
[[Bibliography]]
  
  
Line 308: Line 308:
  
 
<poem>
 
<poem>
[A] Anguttara Nikāya: The Book of the Gradual Sayings, trans. F. L. Woodward & E. M. Hare, 5 volumes, Bristol: Pali Text Society, 1932–6.
+
[A] [[Anguttara Nikāya]]: The [[Book]] of the [[Gradual Sayings]], trans. F. L. Woodward & E. M. Hare, 5 volumes, [[Bristol]]: [[Pali Text Society]], 1932–6.
[D] Dīgha Nikāya: The Long Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Dīgha Nikāya, trans. Maurice Walshe, Boston: Wisdom Publications, 1987.
+
[D] [[Dīgha Nikāya]]: [[The Long Discourses of the Buddha]]: A Translation of the [[Dīgha Nikāya]], trans. [[Maurice Walshe]], [[Boston]]: [[Wisdom Publications]], 1987.
[M] Majjhima Nikāya:  The Middle Length Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Majjhima Nikaya, trans.  Bhikkhu Nanamoli and Bhikkhu Bodhi, Boston: Wisdom Publications, 1995.
+
[M] [[Majjhima Nikāya]]:  The [[Middle Length Discourses]] of the [[Buddha]]: A Translation of the [[Majjhima Nikaya]], trans.  [[Bhikkhu Nanamoli]] and [[Bhikkhu Bodhi]], [[Boston]]: [[Wisdom Publications]], 1995.
  
[S] Saṃyutta Nikāya: The Connected Discourses of the Buddha, trans. Bhikkhu Bodhi, Boston: Wisdom Publications, 2000.
+
[S] [[Saṃyutta Nikāya]]: The [[Connected Discourses]] of the [[Buddha]], trans. [[Bhikkhu Bodhi]], [[Boston]]: [[Wisdom Publications]], 2000.
 
Secondary Sources
 
Secondary Sources
  
     Albahari, Miri, 2006. Analytical Buddhism, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
+
     Albahari, Miri, 2006. Analytical [[Buddhism]], Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
     Albahari, Miri, 2014. ‘Insight Knowledge of No Self in Buddhism: An Epistemic Analysis,’ Philosophers' Imprint, 14(1): 1–30, available online.
+
     Albahari, Miri, 2014. ‘[[Insight Knowledge]] of [[No Self]] in [[Buddhism]]: An Epistemic Analysis,’ [[Philosophers]]' Imprint, 14(1): 1–30, available online.
     Collins, Stephen, 1982. Selfless Persons, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
+
     Collins, Stephen, 1982. [[Selfless]] Persons, [[Cambridge]]: {{Wiki|Cambridge University Press}}.
     Gethin, Rupert, 1998. The Foundations of Buddhism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
+
     [[Gethin]], Rupert, 1998. The Foundations of [[Buddhism]], [[Oxford]]: [[Oxford University Press]].
     Gombrich, Richard F., 1996. How Buddhism Began, London: Athlone.
+
     Gombrich, Richard F., 1996. [[How Buddhism Began]], [[London]]: Athlone.
     –––, 2009. What the Buddha Thought, London: Equinox.
+
     –––, 2009. What the [[Buddha]] [[Thought]], [[London]]: Equinox.
  
     Gowans, Christopher, 2003. Philosophy of the Buddha, London: Routledge.
+
     Gowans, Christopher, 2003. [[Philosophy of the Buddha]], [[London]]: Routledge.
     Harvey, Peter, 1995. The Selfless Mind, Richmond, UK: Curzon.
+
     Harvey, Peter, 1995. The [[Selfless]] [[Mind]], Richmond, UK: Curzon.
     Jayatilleke, K.N., 1963. Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge, London: George Allen and Unwin.
+
     [[Jayatilleke]], K.N., 1963. Early [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Knowledge]], [[London]]: George Allen and Unwin.
     Rahula, Walpola, 1967. What the Buddha Taught, 2nd ed., London: Unwin.
+
     [[Rahula, Walpola]], 1967. What the [[Buddha]] [[Taught]], 2nd ed., [[London]]: Unwin.
     Ronkin, Noa, 2005. Early Buddhist Metaphysics, London: Routledge.
+
     Ronkin, Noa, 2005. [[Early Buddhist Metaphysics]], [[London]]: Routledge.
     Ruegg, David Seyfort, 1977. ‘The Uses of the Four Positions of the Catuṣkoṭi and the Problem of the Description of Reality in Mahāyāna Buddhism,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy, 5: 1–71.
+
     Ruegg, David Seyfort, 1977. ‘The Uses of the Four Positions of the [[Catuṣkoṭi]] and the Problem of the Description of [[Reality]] in [[Mahāyāna Buddhism]],’ [[Journal of Indian Philosophy]], 5: 1–71.
     Siderits, Mark, 2007. Buddhism As Philosophy, Indianapolis: Hackett.
+
     [[Siderits, Mark]], 2007. [[Buddhism]] As [[Philosophy]], {{Wiki|Indianapolis}}: Hackett.
 
</poem>
 
</poem>
  

Latest revision as of 00:20, 12 February 2020



First published Thu Feb 17, 2011; substantive revision Tue Feb 3, 2015

The Buddha (fl. circa 450 BCE) is the individual whose teachings form the basis of the Buddhist tradition. These teachings, preserved in texts known as the Nikāyas or Āgamas, concern the quest for liberation from suffering. While the ultimate aim of the Buddha's teachings is thus to help individuals attain the good life, his analysis of the source of suffering centrally involves claims concerning the nature of persons, as well as how we acquire knowledge about the world and our place in it. These teachings formed the basis of a philosophical tradition that developed and defended a variety of sophisticated theories in metaphysics and epistemology.



1. Buddha as Philosopher


This entry concerns the historical individual, traditionally called Gautama, who is identified by modern scholars as the founder of Buddhism. According to Buddhist teachings, there have been other Buddhas in the past, and there will be yet more in the future.


The title ‘Buddha’, which literally means ‘awakened’, is conferred on an individual who discovers the path to nirvana, the cessation of suffering, and propagates that discovery so that others may also achieve nirvana. If the teaching that there have been other Buddhas is true, then Gautama is not the founder of Buddhism.


This entry will follow modern scholarship in taking an agnostic stance on the question of whether there have been other Buddhas, and likewise for questions concerning the superhuman status and powers that some Buddhists attribute to Buddhas. The concern of this entry is just those aspects of the thought of the historical individual Gautama that bear on the development of the Buddhist philosophical tradition.


The Buddha will here be treated as a philosopher. To so treat him is controversial, but before coming to why that should be so, let us first rehearse those basic aspects of the Buddha's life and teachings that are relatively non-controversial. Tradition has it that Gautama lived to age 80. Up until recently his dates were thought to be approximately 560–480 BCE, but many scholars now hold that he must have died around 405 BCE. He was born into a family of some wealth and power, members of the Śākya clan, in the area of the present border between India and Nepal.


The story is that in early adulthood he abandoned his comfortable life as a householder (as well as his wife and young son) in order to seek a solution to the problem of existential suffering. He first took up with a number of different wandering ascetics (śramanas) who claimed to know the path to liberation from suffering. Finding their teachings unsatisfactory, he struck out on his own, and through a combination of insight and meditational practice attained the state of enlightenment (bodhi) which is said to represent the cessation of all further suffering. He then devoted the remaining 45 years of his life to teaching others the insights and techniques that had led him to this achievement.


Gautama could himself be classified as one of the śramanas. That there existed such a phenomenon as the śramanas tells us that there was some degree of dissatisfaction with the customary religious practices then prevailing in the Gangetic basin of North India. These practices consisted largely in the rituals and sacrifices prescribed in the Vedas. Among the śramanas there were many, including the Buddha, who rejected the authority of the Vedas as definitive pronouncements on the nature of the world and our place in it (and for this reason are called ‘heterodox’). But within the Vedic canon itself there is a stratum of (comparatively late) texts, the Upaniṣads, that likewise displays disaffection with Brahmin ritualism.


Among the new ideas that figure in these (‘orthodox’) texts, as well as in the teachings of those heterodox śramanas whose doctrines are known to us, are the following: that sentient beings (including humans, non-human animals, gods, and the inhabitants of various hells) undergo rebirth; that rebirth is governed by the causal laws of karma (good actions cause pleasant fruit for the agent, evil actions cause unpleasant fruit, etc.); that continual rebirth is inherently unsatisfactory; that there is an ideal state for sentient beings involving liberation from the cycle of rebirth; and that attaining this state requires overcoming ignorance concerning one's true identity. Various views are offered concerning this ignorance and how to overcome it.

The Bhagavad Gītā (classified by some orthodox schools as an Upaniṣad) lists four such methods, and discusses at least two separate views concerning our identity: that there is a plurality of distinct selves, each being the true agent of a person's actions and the bearer of karmic merit and demerit but existing separately from the body and its associated states; and that there is just one self, of the nature of pure consciousness (a ‘witness’) and identical with the essence of the cosmos, Brahman or pure undifferentiated Being.


The Buddha agreed with those of his contemporaries embarked on the same soteriological project that it is ignorance about our identity that is responsible for suffering. What sets his teachings apart (at this level of analysis) lies in what he says that ignorance consists in: the conceit that there is an ‘I’ and a ‘mine’. This is the famous Buddhist teaching of non-self (anātman). And it is with this teaching that the controversy begins concerning whether Gautama may legitimately be represented as a philosopher.

First there are those who (correctly) point out that the Buddha never categorically denies the existence of a self that transcends what is empirically given, namely the five skandhas or psychophysical elements. While the Buddha does deny that any of the psychophysical elements is a self, these interpreters claim that he at least leaves open the possibility that there is a self that is transcendent in the sense of being non-empirical.

To this it may be objected that all of classical Indian philosophy—Buddhist and orthodox alike—understood the Buddha to have denied the self tout court. To this it is sometimes replied that the later philosophical tradition simply got the Buddha wrong, at least in part because the Buddha sought to indicate something that cannot be grasped through the exercise of philosophical rationality. On this interpretation, the Buddha should be seen not as a proponent of the philosophical methods of analysis and argumentation, but rather as one who sees those methods as obstacles to final release.


Another reason one sometimes encounters for denying that the Buddha is a philosopher is that he rejects the characteristically philosophical activity of theorizing about matters that lack evident practical application. On this interpretation as well, those later Buddhist thinkers who did go in for the construction of theories about the ultimate nature of everything simply failed to heed or properly appreciate the Buddha's advice that we avoid theorizing for its own sake and confine our attention to those matters that are directly relevant to liberation from suffering.

On this view the teaching of non-self is not a bit of metaphysics, just some practical advice to the effect that we should avoid identifying with things that are transitory and so bound to yield dissatisfaction. What both interpretations share is the assumption that it is possible to arrive at what the Buddha himself thought without relying on the understanding of his teachings developed in the subsequent Buddhist philosophical tradition.


This assumption may be questioned. Our knowledge of the Buddha's teachings comes by way of texts that were not written down until several centuries after his death, are in languages (Pāli, and Chinese translations of Sanskrit) other than the one he is likely to have spoken, and disagree in important respects. The first difficulty may not be as serious as it seems, given that the Buddha's discourses were probably rehearsed shortly after his death and preserved through oral transmission until the time they were committed to writing. And the second need not be insuperable either.


But the third is troubling, in that it suggests textual transmission involved processes of insertion and deletion in aid of one side or another in sectarian disputes. Our ancient sources attest to this: one will encounter a dispute among Buddhist thinkers where one side cites some utterance of the Buddha in support of their position, only to have the other side respond that the text from which the quotation is taken is not universally recognized as authoritatively the word of the Buddha. This suggests that our record of the Buddha's teaching may be colored by the philosophical elaboration of those teachings propounded by later thinkers in the Buddhist tradition.


Some scholars are more sanguine than others about the possibility of overcoming this difficulty, and thereby getting at what the Buddha himself had thought, as opposed to what later Buddhist philosophers thought he had thought. No position will be taken on this dispute here. We will be treating the Buddha's thought as it was understood within the later philosophical tradition that he had inspired.


The resulting interpretation may or may not be faithful to his intentions. It is at least logically possible that he believed there to be a transcendent self that can only be known by mystical intuition, or that the exercise of philosophical rationality leads only to sterile theorizing and away from real emancipation. What we can say with some assurance is that this is not how the Buddhist philosophical tradition understood him. It is their understanding that will be the subject of this essay.


2. Core Teachings


The Buddha's basic teachings are usually summarized using the device of the Four Noble Truths:


    There is suffering.
    There is the origination of suffering.
    There is the cessation of suffering.
    There is a path to the cessation of suffering.

The first of these claims might seem obvious, even when ‘suffering’ is understood to mean not mere pain but existential suffering, the sort of frustration, alienation and despair that arise out of our experience of transitoriness. But there are said to be different levels of appreciation of this truth, some quite subtle and difficult to attain; the highest of these is said to involve the realization that everything is of the nature of suffering.

Perhaps it is sufficient for present purposes to point out that while this is not the implausible claim that all of life's states and events are necessarily experienced as unsatisfactory, still the realization that all (oneself included) is impermanent can undermine a precondition for real enjoyment of the events in a life: that such events are meaningful by virtue of their having a place in an open-ended narrative.


It is with the development and elaboration of (2) that substantive philosophical controversy begins. (2) is the simple claim that there are causes and conditions for the arising of suffering. (3) then makes the obvious point that if the origination of suffering depends on causes, future suffering can be prevented by bringing about the cessation of those causes. (4) specifies a set of techniques that are said to be effective in such cessation.


Much then hangs on the correct identification of the causes of suffering. The answer is traditionally spelled out in a list consisting of twelve links in a causal chain that begins with ignorance and ends with suffering (represented by the states of old age, disease and death). Modern scholarship has established that this list is a later compilation. For the texts that claim to convey the Buddha's own teachings give two slightly different formulations of this list, and shorter formulations containing only some of the twelve items are also found in the texts.

But it seems safe to say that the Buddha taught an analysis of the origins of suffering roughly along the following lines: given the existence of a fully functioning assemblage of psychophysical elements (the parts that make up a sentient being), ignorance concerning the three characteristics of sentient existence—suffering, impermanence and non-self—will lead, in the course of normal interactions with the environment, to appropriation (the identification of certain elements as ‘I’ and ‘mine’). This leads in turn to the formation of attachments, in the form of desire and aversion, and the strengthening of ignorance concerning the true nature of sentient existence. These ensure future rebirth, and thus future instances of old age, disease and death, in a potentially unending cycle.


The key to escape from this cycle is said to lie in realization of the truth about sentient existence—that it is characterized by suffering, impermanence and non-self. But this realization is not easily achieved, since acts of appropriation have already made desire, aversion and ignorance deeply entrenched habits of mind. Thus the measures specified in (4) include various forms of training designed to replace such habits with others that are more conducive to seeing things as they are. Training in meditation is also prescribed, as a way of enhancing one's observational abilities, especially with respect to one's own psychological states. Insight is cultivated through the use of these newly developed observational powers, as informed by knowledge acquired through the exercise of philosophical rationality.


There is a debate in the later tradition as to whether final release can be attained through theoretical insight alone, through meditation alone, or only by using both techniques. Ch'an, for instance, is based on the premise that enlightenment can be attained through meditation alone, whereas Theravāda advocates using both but also holds that analysis alone may be sufficient for some. (This disagreement begins with a dispute over how to interpret D I.77–84.) The third option seems the most plausible, but the first is certainly of some interest given its suggestion that one can attain the ideal state for humans just by doing philosophy.


The Buddha seems to have held (2) to constitute the core of his discovery. He calls his teachings a ‘middle path’ between two extreme views, and it is this claim concerning the causal origins of suffering that he identifies as the key to avoiding those extremes. The extremes are eternalism, the view that persons are eternal, and annihilationism, the view that persons go utterly out of existence (usually understood to mean at death, though a term still shorter than one lifetime is not ruled out).

It will be apparent that eternalism requires the existence of the sort of self that the Buddha denies. What is not immediately evident is why the denial of such a self is not tantamount to the claim that the person is annihilated at death (or even sooner, depending on just how impermanent one takes the psychophysical elements to be).

The solution to this puzzle lies in the fact that eternalism and annihilationism both share the presupposition that there is an ‘I’ whose existence might either extend beyond death or terminate at death. The idea of the ‘middle path’ is that all of life's continuities can be explained in terms of facts about a causal series of psychophysical elements. There being nothing more than a succession of these impermanent, impersonal events and states, the question of the ultimate fate of this ‘I’, the supposed owner of these elements, simply does not arise.


This reductionist view of sentient beings was later articulated in terms of the distinction between two kinds of truth, conventional and ultimate. Each kind of truth has its own domain of objects, the things that are only conventionally real and the things that are ultimately real respectively. Conventionally real entities are those things that are accepted as real by common sense, but that turn out on further analysis to be wholes compounded out of simpler entities and thus not strictly speaking real at all.

The stock example of a conventionally real entity is the chariot, which we take to be real only because it is more convenient, given our interests and cognitive limitations, to have a single name for the parts when assembled in the right way. Since our belief that there are chariots is thus due to our having a certain useful concept, the chariot is said to be a mere conceptual fiction.

(This does not, however, mean that all conceptualization is falsification; only concepts that allow of reductive analysis lead to this artificial inflation of our ontology, and thus to a kind of error.) Ultimately real entities are those ultimate parts into which conceptual fictions are analyzable. An ultimately true statement is one that correctly describes how certain ultimately real entities are arranged.

A conventionally true statement is one that, given how the ultimately real entities are arranged, would correctly describe certain conceptual fictions if they also existed. The ultimate truth concerning the relevant ultimately real entities helps explain why it should turn out to be useful to accept conventionally true statements (such as ‘King Milinda rode in a chariot’) when the objects described in those statements are mere fictions.


Using this distinction between the two truths, the key insight of the ‘middle path’ may be expressed as follows. The ultimate truth about sentient beings is just that there is a causal series of impermanent, impersonal psychophysical elements. Since these are all impermanent, and lack other properties that would be required of an essence of the person, none of them is a self.

But given the right arrangement of such entities in a causal series, it is useful to think of them as making up one thing, a person. It is thus conventionally true that there are persons, things that endure for a lifetime and possibly (if there is rebirth) longer. This is conventionally true because generally speaking there is more overall happiness and less overall pain and suffering when one part of such a series identifies with other parts of the same series.

For instance, when the present set of psychophysical elements identifies with future elements, it is less likely to engage in behavior (such as smoking) that results in present pleasure but far greater future pain. The utility of this convention is, however, limited. Past a certain point—namely the point at which we take it too seriously, as more than just a useful fiction—it results in existential suffering. The cessation of suffering is attained by extirpating all sense of an ‘I’ that serves as agent and owner.


3. Non-Self


The Buddha'smiddle path’ strategy can be seen as one of first arguing that there is nothing that the word ‘I’ genuinely denotes, and then explaining that our erroneous sense of an ‘I’ stems from our employment of the useful fiction represented by the concept of the person. While the second part of this strategy only receives its full articulation in the later development of the theory of two truths, the first part can be found in the Buddha's own teachings, in the form of several philosophical arguments for non-self. Best known among these is the argument from impermanence (S III.66–8), which has this basic structure:

    If there were a self it would be permanent.
    None of the five kinds of psychophysical element is permanent.
    ∴ There is no self.

It is the fact that this argument does not contain a premise explicitly asserting that the five skandhas (classes of psychophysical element) are exhaustive of the constituents of persons, plus the fact that these are all said to be empirically observable, that leads some to claim that the Buddha did not intend to deny the existence of a self tout court.

There is, however, evidence that the Buddha was generally hostile toward attempts to establish the existence of unobservable entities. In the Pohapāda Sutta (D I.178–203), for instance, the Buddha compares someone who posits an unseen seer in order to explain our introspective awareness of cognitions, to a man who has conceived a longing for the most beautiful woman in the world based solely on the thought that such a woman must surely exist.

And in the Tevijja Sutta (D I.235–52), the Buddha rejects the claim of certain Brahmins to know the path to oneness with Brahman, on the grounds that no one has actually observed this Brahman. This makes more plausible the assumption that the argument has as an implicit premise the claim that there is no more to the person than the five skandhas.

Premise (1) appears to be based on the assumption that persons undergo rebirth, together with the thought that one function of a self would be to account for diachronic personal identity. By ‘permanent’ is here meant continued existence over at least several lives. This is shown by the fact that the Buddha rules out the body as a self on the grounds that the body exists for just one lifetime.

(This also demonstrates that the Buddha did not mean by ‘impermanent’ what some later Buddhist philosophers meant, viz., existing for just a moment; the Buddhist doctrine of momentariness represents a later development.) The mental entities that make up the remaining four types of psychophysical element might seem like more promising candidates, but these are ruled out on the grounds that these all originate in dependence on contact between sense faculty and object, and last no longer than a particular sense-object-contact event.

That he listed five kinds of psychophysical element, and not just one, shows that the Buddha embraced a kind of dualism. But this strategy for demonstrating the impermanence of the psychological elements shows that his dualism was not the sort of mind-body dualism familiar from substance ontologies like those of Descartes and of the Nyāya school of orthodox Indian philosophy. Instead of seeing the mind as the persisting bearer of such transient events as occurrences of cognition, feeling and volition, he treats ‘mind’ as a kind of aggregate term for bundles of transient mental events. These events being impermanent, they too fail to account for diachronic personal identity in the way in which a self might be expected to.


Another argument for non-self, which might be called the argument from control (S III.66–8), has this structure:

    If there were a self, one could never desire that it be changed.
    Each of the five kinds of psychophysical element is such that one can desire that it be changed.
     ∴ There is no self.

Premise (1) is puzzling. It appears to presuppose that the self should have complete control over itself, so that it would effortlessly adjust its state to its desires. That the self should be thought of as the locus of control is certainly plausible. Those Indian self-theorists who claim that the self is a mere passive witness recognize that the burden of proof is on them to show that the self is not an agent. But it seems implausibly demanding to require of the self that it have complete control over itself. We do not require that vision see itself if it is to see other things.

The case of vision suggests an alternative interpretation, however. We might hold that vision does not see itself for the reason that this would violate an irreflexivity principle, to the effect that an entity cannot operate on itself. Indian philosophers who accept this principle cite supportive instances such as the knife that cannot cut itself and the finger-tip that cannot touch itself. If this principle is accepted, then if the self were the locus of control it would follow that it could never exercise this function on itself. A self that was the controller could never find itself in the position of seeking to change its state to one that it deemed more desirable. On this interpretation, the first premise seems to be true.

And there is ample evidence that (2) is true: it is difficult to imagine a bodily or psychological state over which one might not wish to exercise control. Consequently, given the assumption that the person is wholly composed of the psychophysical elements, it appears to follow that a self of this description does not exist.

These two arguments appear, then, to give good reason to deny a self that might ground diachronic personal identity and serve as locus of control, given the assumption that there is no more to the person than the empirically given psychophysical elements. But it now becomes something of a puzzle how one is to explain diachronic personal identity and agency.

To start with the latter, does the argument from control not suggest that control must be exercised by something other than the psychophysical elements? This was precisely the conclusion of the Sāṃkhya school of orthodox Indian philosophy. One of their arguments for the existence of a self was that it is possible to exercise control over all the empirically given constituents of the person; while they agree with the Buddha that a self is never observed, they take the phenomena of agency to be grounds for positing a self that transcends all possible experience.


This line of objection to the Buddha's teaching of non-self is more commonly formulated in response to the argument from impermanence, however. Perhaps its most dramatic form is aimed at the Buddha's acceptance of the doctrines of karma and rebirth. It is clear that the body ceases to exist at death. And given the Buddha's argument that mental states all originate in dependence on sense-object contact events, it seems no psychological constituent of the person can transmigrate either.

Yet the Buddha claims that persons who have not yet achieved enlightenment will be reborn as sentient beings of some sort after they die. If there is no constituent whatever that moves from one life to the next, how could the being in the next life be the same person as the being in this life? This question becomes all the more pointed when it is added that rebirth is governed by karma, something that functions as a kind of cosmic justice: those born into fortunate circumstances do so as a result of good deeds in prior lives, while unpleasant births result from evil past deeds. Such a system of reward and punishment could be just only if the recipient of pleasant or unpleasant karmic fruit is the same person as the agent of the good or evil action. And the opponent finds it incomprehensible how this could be so in the absence of a persisting self.


4. Karma and Rebirth


It is not just classical Indian self-theorists who have found this objection persuasive. Some Buddhists have as well. Among these Buddhists, however, this has led to the rejection not of non-self but of rebirth. (Historically this response was not unknown among East Asian Buddhists, and it is not rare among Western Buddhists today.) The evidence that the Buddha himself accepted rebirth and karma seems quite strong, however. The later tradition would distinguish between two types of discourse in the body of the Buddha's teachings: those intended for an audience of householders seeking instruction from a sage, and those intended for an audience of monastic renunciates already versed in his teachings.


And it would be one thing if his use of the concepts of karma and rebirth were limited to the former. For then such appeals could be explained away as another instance of the Buddha's pedagogical skill (commonly referred to as upāya). The idea would be that householders who fail to comply with the most basic demands of morality are not likely (for reasons to be discussed shortly) to make significant progress toward the cessation of suffering, and the teaching of karma and rebirth, even if not strictly speaking true, does give those who accept it a (prudential) reason to be moral. But this sort of ‘noble lie’ justification for the Buddha teaching a doctrine he does not accept fails in the face of the evidence that he also taught it to quite advanced monastics (e.g., A III.33).

And what he taught is not the version of karma popular in certain circles today, according to which, for instance, an act done out of hatred makes the agent somewhat more disposed to perform similar actions out of similar motives in the future, which in turn makes negative experiences more likely for the agent. What the Buddha teaches is instead the far stricter view that each action has its own specific consequence for the agent, the hedonic nature of which is determined in accordance with causal laws and in such a way as to require rebirth as long as action continues. So if there is a conflict between the doctrine of non-self and the teaching of karma and rebirth, it is not to be resolved by weakening the Buddha's commitment to the latter.


The Sanskrit term karma literally means ‘action’. What is nowadays referred to somewhat loosely as the theory of karma is, speaking more strictly, the view that there is a causal relationship between action (karma) and ‘fruit’ (phala), the latter being an experience of pleasure, pain or indifference for the agent of the action. This is the view that the Buddha appears to have accepted in its most straightforward form. Actions are said to be of three types: bodily, verbal and mental. The Buddha insists, however, that by action is meant not the movement or change involved, but rather the volition or intention that brought about the change.

As Gombrich (2009) points out, the Buddha's insistence on this point reflects the transition from an earlier ritualistic view of action to a view that brings action within the purview of ethics. For it is when actions are seen as subject to moral assessment that intention becomes relevant. One does not, for instance, perform the morally blameworthy action of speaking insultingly to an elder just by making sounds that approximate to the pronunciation of profanities in the presence of an elder; parrots and prelinguistic children can do as much. What matters for moral assessment is the mental state (if any) that produced the bodily, verbal or mental change.


And it is the occurrence of these mental states that is said to cause the subsequent occurrence of hedonically good, bad and neutral experiences. More specifically, it is the occurrence of the three ‘defiledmental states that brings about karmic fruit. The three defilements (kleśas) are desire, aversion and ignorance. And we are told quite specifically (A III.33) that actions performed by an agent in whom these three defilements have been destroyed do not have karmic consequences; such an agent is experiencing their last birth.


Some caution is required in understanding this claim about the defilements. The Buddha seems to be saying that it is possible to act not only without ignorance, but also in the absence of desire or aversion, yet it is difficult to see how there could be intentional action without some positive or negative motivation. To see one's way around this difficulty, one must realize that by ‘desire’ and ‘aversion’ are meant those positive and negative motives respectively that are colored by ignorance, viz. ignorance concerning suffering, impermanence and non-self. Presumably the enlightened person, while knowing the truth about these matters, can still engage in motivated action.

Their actions are not based on the presupposition that there is an ‘I’ for which those actions can have significance. Ignorance concerning these matters perpetuates rebirth, and thus further occasions for existential suffering, by facilitating a motivational structure that reinforces one's ignorance.

We can now see how compliance with common-sense morality could be seen as an initial step on the path to the cessation of suffering. While the presence of ignorance makes all action—even that deemed morally good—karmically potent, those actions commonly considered morally evil are especially powerful reinforcers of ignorance, in that they stem from the assumption that the agent's welfare is of paramount importance. While recognition of the moral value of others may still involve the conceit that there is an ‘I’, it can nonetheless constitute progress toward dissolution of the sense of self.


This excursus into what the Buddha meant by karma may help us see how his middle path strategy could be used to reply to the objection to non-self from rebirth. That objection was that the reward and punishment generated by karma across lives could never be deserved in the absence of a transmigrating self. The middle path strategy generally involves locating and rejecting an assumption shared by a pair of extreme views.

In this case the views will be (1) that the person in the later life deserves the fruit generated by the action in the earlier life, and (2) that this person does not deserve the fruit. One assumption shared by (1) and (2) is that persons deserve reward and punishment depending on the moral character of their actions, and one might deny this assumption. But that would be tantamount to moral nihilism, and a middle path is said to avoid nihilisms (such as annihilationism).

A more promising alternative might be to deny that there are ultimately such things as persons that could bear moral properties like desert. This is what the Buddha seems to mean when he asserts that the earlier and the later person are neither the same nor different (S II.62; S II.76; S II.113). Since any two existing things must be either identical or distinct, to say of the two persons that they are neither is to say that strictly speaking they do not exist.


This alternative is more promising because it avoids moral nihilism. For it allows one to assert that persons and their moral properties are conventionally real. To say this is to say that given our interests and cognitive limitations, we do better at achieving our aim—minimizing overall pain and suffering—by acting as though there are persons with morally significant properties. Ultimately there are just impersonal entities and events in causal sequence: ignorance, the sorts of desires that ignorance facilitates, an intention formed on the basis of such a desire, a bodily, verbal or mental action, a feeling of pleasure, pain or indifference, and an occasion of suffering.

The claim is that this situation is usefully thought of as, for instance, a person who performs an evil deed due to their ignorance of the true nature of things, receives the unpleasant fruit they deserve in the next life, and suffers through their continuing on the wheel of saṃsāra. It is useful to think of the situation in this way because it helps us locate the appropriate places to intervene to prevent future pain (the evil deed) and future suffering (ignorance).


It is no doubt quite difficult to believe that karma and rebirth exist in the form that the Buddha claims. It is said that their existence can be confirmed by those who have developed the power of retrocognition through advanced yogic technique. But this is of little help to those not already convinced that meditation is a reliable means of knowledge. What can be said with some assurance is that karma and rebirth are not inconsistent with non-self. Rebirth without transmigration is logically possible.


5. Attitude toward Reason


When the Buddha says that a person in one life and the person in another life are neither the same nor different, one's first response might be to take ‘different’ to mean something other than ‘not the same’. But while this is possible in English given the ambiguity of ‘the same’, it is not possible in the Pāli source, where the Buddha is represented as unambiguously denying both numerical identity and numerical distinctness.

This has led some to wonder whether the Buddha does not employ a deviant logic. Such suspicions are strengthened by those cases where the options are not two but four, cases of the so-called tetralemma (catuṣkoṭi). For instance, when the Buddha is questioned about the post-mortem status of the enlightened person or arhat (e.g., at M I.483–8) the possibilities are listed as: (1) the arhat continues to exist after death, (2) does not exist after death, (3) both exists and does not exist after death, and (4) neither exists nor does not exist after death.

When the Buddha rejects both (1) and (2) we get a repetition of ‘neither the same nor different’. But when he goes on to entertain, and then reject, (3) and (4) the logical difficulties are compounded. Since each of (3) and (4) appears to be formally contradictory, to entertain either is to entertain the possibility that a contradiction might be true. And their denial seems tantamount to affirmation of excluded middle, which is prima facie incompatible with the denial of both (1) and (2). One might wonder whether we are here in the presence of the mystical.


There were some Buddhist philosophers who took ‘neither the same nor different’ in this way. These were the Personalists (Pudgalavādins), who were so called because they affirmed the ultimate existence of the person as something named and conceptualized in dependence on the psychophysical elements. They claimed that the person is neither identical with nor distinct from the psychophysical elements.


They were prepared to accept, as a consequence, that nothing whatever can be said about the relation between person and elements. But their view was rejected by most Buddhist philosophers, in part on the grounds that it quickly leads to an ineffability paradox: one can say neither that the person's relation to the elements is inexpressible, nor that it is not inexpressible.

The consensus view was instead that the fact that the person can be said to be neither identical with nor distinct from the elements is grounds for taking the person to be a mere conceptual fiction. Concerning the persons in the two lives, they understood the negations involved in ‘neither the same nor different’ to be of the commitmentless variety, i.e., to function like illocutionary negation.

If we agree that the statement ‘7 is green’ is semantically ill-formed, on the grounds that abstract objects such as numbers do not have colors, then we might go on to say, ‘Do not say that 7 is green, and do not say that it is not green either’. There is no contradiction here, since the illocutionary negation operator ‘do not say’ generates no commitment to an alternative characterization.


There is also evidence that claims of type (3) involve parameterization. For instance, the claim about the arhat would be that there is some respect in which they can be said to exist after death, and some other respect in which they can be said to no longer exist after death. Entertaining such a proposition does not require that one believe there might be true contradictions.


And while claims of type (4) would seem to be logically equivalent to those of type (3) (regardless of whether or not they involve parameterization), the tradition treated this type as asserting that the subject is beyond all conceptualization. To reject the type (4) claim about the arhat is to close off one natural response to the rejections of the first three claims: that the status of the arhat after death transcends rational understanding. That the Buddha rejected all four possibilities concerning this and related questions is not evidence that he employed a deviant logic.


The Buddha's response to questions like those concerning the arhat is sometimes cited in defense of a different claim about his attitude toward rationality. This is the claim that the Buddha was essentially a pragmatist, someone who rejects philosophical theorizing for its own sake and employs philosophical rationality only to the extent that doing so can help solve the practical problem of eliminating suffering.

The Buddha does seem to be embracing something like this attitude when he defends his refusal to answer questions like that about the arhat, or whether the series of lives has a beginning, or whether the living principle (jīva) is identical with the body. He calls all the possible views with respect to such questions distractions insofar as answering them would not lead to the cessation of the defilements and thus to the end of suffering.

And in a famous simile (M I.429) he compares someone who insists that the Buddha answer these questions to someone who has been wounded by an arrow but will not have the wound treated until they are told who shot the arrow, what sort of wood the arrow is made of, and the like.


Passages such as these surely attest to the great importance the Buddha placed on sharing his insights to help others overcome suffering. But this is consistent with the belief that philosophical rationality may be used to answer questions that lack evident connection with pressing practical concerns. And on at least one occasion the Buddha does just this.

Pressed to give his answers to the questions about the arhat and the like, the Buddha first rejects all the possibilities of the tetralemma, and defends his refusal on the grounds that such theories are not conducive to liberation from saṃsāra.

But when his questioner shows signs of thereby losing confidence in the value of the Buddha's teachings about the path to the cessation of suffering, the Buddha responds with the example of a fire that goes out after exhausting its fuel. If one were asked where this fire has gone, the Buddha points out, one could consistently deny that it has gone to the north, to the south, or in any other direction.

This is so for the simple reason that the questions ‘Has it gone to the north?’, ‘Has it gone to the south?’, etc., all share the false presupposition that the fire continues to exist. Likewise the questions about the arhat and the like all share the false presupposition that there is such a thing as a person who might either continue to exist after death, cease to exist at death, etc. The difficulty with these questions is not that they try to extend philosophical rationality beyond its legitimate domain, as the handmaiden of soteriologically useful practice. It is rather that they rest on a false presupposition—something that is disclosed through the employment of philosophical rationality.


A different sort of challenge to the claim that the Buddha valued philosophical rationality for its own sake comes from the role played by authority in Buddhist soteriology. For instance, in the Buddhist tradition one sometimes encounters the claim that only enlightened persons such as the Buddha can know all the details of karmic causation.

And to the extent that the moral rules are thought to be determined by the details of karmic causation, this might be taken to mean that our knowledge of the moral rules is dependent on the authority of the Buddha. Again, the subsequent development of Buddhist philosophy seems to have been constrained by the need to make theory compatible with certain key claims of the Buddha.

For instance, one school developed an elaborate form of four-dimensionalism, not because of any deep dissatisfaction with presentism, but because they believed the non-existence of the past and the future to be incompatible with the Buddha's alleged ability to cognize past and future events.

And some modern scholars go so far as to wonder whether non-self functions as anything more than a sort of linguistic taboo against the use of words like ‘I’ and ‘self’ in the Buddhist tradition (Collins 1982: 183). The suggestion is that just as in some other religious traditions the views of the founder or the statements of scripture trump all other considerations, including any views arrived at through the free exercise of rational inquiry, so in Buddhism as well there can be at best only a highly constrained arena for the deployment of philosophical rationality.


Now it could be that while this is true of the tradition that developed out of the Buddha's teachings, the Buddha himself held the unfettered use of rationality in quite high esteem. This would seem to conflict with what he is represented as saying in response to the report that he arrived at his conclusions through reasoning and analysis alone: that such a report is libelous, since he possesses a number of superhuman cognitive powers (M I.68).

But at least some scholars take this passage to be not the Buddha's own words but an expression of later devotionalist concerns (Gombrich 2009: 164). Indeed one does find a spirited discussion within the tradition concerning the question whether the Buddha is omniscient, a discussion that may well reflect competition between Buddhism and those Brahmanical schools that posit an omniscient creator.

And at least for the most part the Buddhist tradition is careful not to attribute to the Buddha the sort of omniscience usually ascribed to an all-perfect being: the actual cognition, at any one time, of all truths. Instead a Buddha is said to be omniscient only in the much weaker sense of always having the ability to cognize any individual fact relevant to the soteriological project, viz. the details of their own past lives, the workings of the karmic causal laws, and whether a given individual's defilements have been extirpated.

Moreover, these abilities are said to be ones that a Buddha acquires through a specific course of training, and thus ones that others may reasonably aspire to as well. The attitude of the later tradition seems to be that while one could discover the relevant facts on one's own, it would be more reasonable to take advantage of the fact that the Buddha has already done all the epistemic labor involved. When we arrive in a new town we could always find our final destination through trial and error, but it would make more sense to ask someone who already knows their way about.


The Buddhist philosophical tradition grew out of earlier efforts to systematize the Buddha's teachings. Within a century or two of the death of the Buddha, exegetical differences led to debates concerning the Buddha's true intention on some matter, such as that between the Personalists and others over the status of the person.

While the parties to these debates use many of the standard tools and techniques of philosophy, they were still circumscribed by the assumption that the Buddha's views on the matter at hand are authoritative. In time, however, the discussion widened to include interlocutors representing various Brahmanical systems. Since the latter did not take the Buddha's word as authoritative, Buddhist thinkers were required to defend their positions in other ways.

The resulting debate (which continued for about nine centuries) touched on most of the topics now considered standard in metaphysics, epistemology and philosophy of language, and was characterized by considerable sophistication in philosophical methodology. What the Buddha would have thought of these developments we cannot say with any certainty. What we can say is that many Buddhists have believed that the unfettered exercise of philosophical rationality is quite consistent with his teachings.


Bibliography


Primary Sources

[A] Anguttara Nikāya: The Book of the Gradual Sayings, trans. F. L. Woodward & E. M. Hare, 5 volumes, Bristol: Pali Text Society, 1932–6.
[D] Dīgha Nikāya: The Long Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Dīgha Nikāya, trans. Maurice Walshe, Boston: Wisdom Publications, 1987.
[M] Majjhima Nikāya: The Middle Length Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Majjhima Nikaya, trans. Bhikkhu Nanamoli and Bhikkhu Bodhi, Boston: Wisdom Publications, 1995.

[S] Saṃyutta Nikāya: The Connected Discourses of the Buddha, trans. Bhikkhu Bodhi, Boston: Wisdom Publications, 2000.
Secondary Sources

    Albahari, Miri, 2006. Analytical Buddhism, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
    Albahari, Miri, 2014. ‘Insight Knowledge of No Self in Buddhism: An Epistemic Analysis,’ Philosophers' Imprint, 14(1): 1–30, available online.
    Collins, Stephen, 1982. Selfless Persons, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Gethin, Rupert, 1998. The Foundations of Buddhism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Gombrich, Richard F., 1996. How Buddhism Began, London: Athlone.
    –––, 2009. What the Buddha Thought, London: Equinox.

    Gowans, Christopher, 2003. Philosophy of the Buddha, London: Routledge.
    Harvey, Peter, 1995. The Selfless Mind, Richmond, UK: Curzon.
    Jayatilleke, K.N., 1963. Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge, London: George Allen and Unwin.
    Rahula, Walpola, 1967. What the Buddha Taught, 2nd ed., London: Unwin.
    Ronkin, Noa, 2005. Early Buddhist Metaphysics, London: Routledge.
    Ruegg, David Seyfort, 1977. ‘The Uses of the Four Positions of the Catuṣkoṭi and the Problem of the Description of Reality in Mahāyāna Buddhism,’ Journal of Indian Philosophy, 5: 1–71.
    Siderits, Mark, 2007. Buddhism As Philosophy, Indianapolis: Hackett.


Source

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/buddha/