Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "Buddhism and Science: Breaking New Ground B. Alan Wallace"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
{{GenerateImages|10}}
 
{{GenerateImages|10}}
 +
 +
 +
 +
 +
 +
 +
 +
 
{{Centre|'''Buddhism and Science: Breaking New Ground<br/>
 
{{Centre|'''Buddhism and Science: Breaking New Ground<br/>
 
B. Alan Wallace (editor), Columbia University Press, New York, 2003.<br/>
 
B. Alan Wallace (editor), Columbia University Press, New York, 2003.<br/>
 
Dharmacari Ratnaprabha (Robin Cooper)}}
 
Dharmacari Ratnaprabha (Robin Cooper)}}
The great Marxist {{Wiki|sinologist}} Joseph Needham blamed [[Buddhism]] for stifling [[science]] and technology in [[China]] while they flourished in {{Wiki|Europe}}. In claiming that everything is an [[illusion]], [[Buddhism]] ‘played a part in strangling the development of {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[science]]’. [[Zen Buddhism]], in ‘rejecting all [[philosophy]]’ was also unfavourable to a [[scientific]] [[view]].  
+
The great [[Marxist]] {{Wiki|sinologist}} [[Joseph Needham]] blamed [[Buddhism]] for stifling [[science]] and technology in [[China]] while they flourished in {{Wiki|Europe}}. In claiming that everything is an [[illusion]], [[Buddhism]] ‘played a part in strangling the [[development]] of {{Wiki|Chinese}} [[science]]’. [[Zen Buddhism]], in ‘rejecting all [[philosophy]]’ was also unfavourable to a [[scientific]] [[view]].  
  
 
Since the [[Buddha]] refused to speculate, [[Buddhism]] discouraged [[scientific]] research. Above all, its main [[object]] is to escape from this [[world]], not to try to understand it. A ‘despairing’ and ‘perverse’ [[philosophy]], he concludes.[1] Needham's analysis stands in marked contrast to all the sixteen contributors to this [[book]], and indeed to the prevailing [[view]] today that of all the [[religions]] [[Buddhism]] is the most compatible with [[science]]. It is certainly a fact of history that a great surge in systematic [[scientific]] research, followed by technologies with overwhelming effects, took place in {{Wiki|Europe}} from the eighteenth century onwards.  
 
Since the [[Buddha]] refused to speculate, [[Buddhism]] discouraged [[scientific]] research. Above all, its main [[object]] is to escape from this [[world]], not to try to understand it. A ‘despairing’ and ‘perverse’ [[philosophy]], he concludes.[1] Needham's analysis stands in marked contrast to all the sixteen contributors to this [[book]], and indeed to the prevailing [[view]] today that of all the [[religions]] [[Buddhism]] is the most compatible with [[science]]. It is certainly a fact of history that a great surge in systematic [[scientific]] research, followed by technologies with overwhelming effects, took place in {{Wiki|Europe}} from the eighteenth century onwards.  
  
Despite its sophisticated civilisations, [[science]] in {{Wiki|Asia}} had to await influence from {{Wiki|Europe}} before it was able to make comparable advances. A common [[view]] has been that there was a [[religious]] factor in this difference, that something in {{Wiki|Protestant}} [[Christianity]] favoured [[science]]. However, an {{Wiki|excellent}} essay in this volume by Jose Ignacio Cabezon indicates that the {{Wiki|conditioning}} factors were far more complex, and that when {{Wiki|Western}} [[science]] did arrive in {{Wiki|Asia}}, it was treated by [[Buddhists]] in an open and welcoming way, in contrast to the responses to [[science]] of many {{Wiki|European}} churchmen. When [[science]] did arrive, some [[Wikipedia:South Asia|South Asian]] [[Buddhist]] [[monks]] were tempted either to detect prefigurings of [[scientific]] discoveries in [[Buddhist texts]], or to laud [[Buddhism]] as the most [[scientific]] of [[religions]], and the [[Buddha]] as the first [[scientist]].  
+
Despite its sophisticated civilisations, [[science]] in {{Wiki|Asia}} had to await influence from {{Wiki|Europe}} before it was able to make comparable advances. A common [[view]] has been that there was a [[religious]] factor in this difference, that something in {{Wiki|Protestant}} [[Christianity]] favoured [[science]]. However, an {{Wiki|excellent}} essay in this volume by Jose Ignacio [[Cabezon]] indicates that the {{Wiki|conditioning}} factors were far more complex, and that when {{Wiki|Western}} [[science]] did arrive in {{Wiki|Asia}}, it was treated by [[Buddhists]] in an open and welcoming way, in contrast to the responses to [[science]] of many {{Wiki|European}} churchmen. When [[science]] did arrive, some [[Wikipedia:South Asia|South Asian]] [[Buddhist]] [[monks]] were tempted either to detect prefigurings of [[scientific]] discoveries in [[Buddhist texts]], or to laud [[Buddhism]] as the most [[scientific]] of [[religions]], and the [[Buddha]] as the first [[scientist]].  
  
They were supported, from Victorian times onwards, by westerners' responses to [[Buddhism]]. Cabezon points out that [[human beings]] have at first a tendency to treat what is culturally very different in terms of the culturally familiar, so a host of compatibilities between [[Buddhism]] and [[science]] were discerned. [[Buddhism]] was seen as undogmatic, giving authority to the {{Wiki|individual}}, critical in [[spirit]], with a [[universal]] impersonal causal law (like [[science]]), and with a [[scientific]] [[ethics]]. Colonel Olcott, a {{Wiki|Theosophist}} instrumental in the revival of [[Buddhism]] in [[Sri Lanka]], pointed out around 1889 that [[Buddhism]] shared an evolutionary [[vision]] with [[science]], both [[teaching]] ‘that man is the result of the law of development, from an imperfect lower, to a higher and perfect [[condition]]’ (p. 44).  
+
They were supported, from Victorian times onwards, by westerners' responses to [[Buddhism]]. [[Cabezon]] points out that [[human beings]] have at first a tendency to treat what is culturally very different in terms of the culturally familiar, so a host of compatibilities between [[Buddhism]] and [[science]] were discerned. [[Buddhism]] was seen as undogmatic, giving authority to the {{Wiki|individual}}, critical in [[spirit]], with a [[universal]] {{Wiki|impersonal}} causal law (like [[science]]), and with a [[scientific]] [[ethics]]. [[Colonel Olcott]], a {{Wiki|Theosophist}} instrumental in the revival of [[Buddhism]] in [[Sri Lanka]], pointed out around 1889 that [[Buddhism]] shared an evolutionary [[vision]] with [[science]], both [[teaching]] ‘that man is the result of the law of [[development]], from an imperfect lower, to a higher and {{Wiki|perfect}} [[condition]]’ (p. 44).  
  
(I have explored this connection elsewhere.)[2] Cabezon argues that the unsophisticated [[view]] of compatibility, or even [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]], between [[Buddhism]] and [[science]] is now being replaced by one of complementarity. Each has something to offer the other. The contributors to this volume point out a number of such cross-fertilisations, {{Wiki|concentrating}} on two areas in which [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] may be able to advance [[scientific]] [[understanding]]: [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[science]] and {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|physics}}. There is one man in particular who should be credited both with stimulating {{Wiki|Western}} [[scientists]] to investigate [[Buddhism]], and with reassuring [[Buddhists]] that they have [[nothing]] to {{Wiki|fear}} from [[science]] – the [[Dalai Lama.]]  
+
(I have explored this [[connection]] elsewhere.)[2] [[Cabezon]] argues that the unsophisticated [[view]] of compatibility, or even [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]], between [[Buddhism]] and [[science]] is now being replaced by one of complementarity. Each has something to offer the other. The contributors to this volume point out a number of such cross-fertilisations, {{Wiki|concentrating}} on two areas in which [[Buddhist]] [[thought]] may be able to advance [[scientific]] [[understanding]]: [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[science]] and {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|physics}}. There is one man in particular who should be credited both with stimulating {{Wiki|Western}} [[scientists]] to investigate [[Buddhism]], and with reassuring [[Buddhists]] that they have [[nothing]] to {{Wiki|fear}} from [[science]] – the [[Dalai Lama.]]  
  
 
As an inquisitive boy-lama roaming around in the vast [[Potala Palace]], he loved to investigate exotic {{Wiki|Western}} mechanical devices, as well as quizzing his tutors on [[science]]. Somewhere he relates how, as he turned a {{Wiki|globe}} in his hands, it gradually dawned on him that this was a [[representation]] of our spherical [[world]], and the flat [[cosmology]] of the {{Wiki|ancient Indian}} texts had now been superseded. He has never lost his eager fascination for [[science]], and he instigated a continuing series of biennial meetings with groups of {{Wiki|Western}} [[scientists]] in which a number of topics have been freely explored. (The meetings are organised by the Mind-Life Institute, and an appendix in the [[book]] lists those which have been published so far.)  
 
As an inquisitive boy-lama roaming around in the vast [[Potala Palace]], he loved to investigate exotic {{Wiki|Western}} mechanical devices, as well as quizzing his tutors on [[science]]. Somewhere he relates how, as he turned a {{Wiki|globe}} in his hands, it gradually dawned on him that this was a [[representation]] of our spherical [[world]], and the flat [[cosmology]] of the {{Wiki|ancient Indian}} texts had now been superseded. He has never lost his eager fascination for [[science]], and he instigated a continuing series of biennial meetings with groups of {{Wiki|Western}} [[scientists]] in which a number of topics have been freely explored. (The meetings are organised by the Mind-Life Institute, and an appendix in the [[book]] lists those which have been published so far.)  
  
Thus many of the contributors have been involved in the Mind-Life conferences, and have to varying extents practised or studied within the [[Dalai Lama's]] [[Gelug school]] of [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|Alan Wallace}}, the editor, is one of his [[translators]] as well as a writer on [[Buddhism]] and [[science]]; the [[Dalai Lama's]] chief [[translator]], Thupten Jinpa,is probably the only [[Tibetan]] [[monk]] to have studied {{Wiki|Western philosophy}} to a doctoral level, and offers an [[interesting]] essay on [[Tibetan]] responses to [[science]]. [[Geshe]] Jinpa informs us that the [[Dalai Lama]] does more than encourage a dialogue between [[Buddhism]] and [[science]]. He is prepared to let [[science]] change [[Buddhism]], so that if a fact emerges that is incompatible with [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}}, he says, ‘there is no [[doubt]] that we must accept the result of the [[scientific]] research’ (p. 77).
+
Thus many of the contributors have been involved in the Mind-Life conferences, and have to varying extents practised or studied within the [[Dalai Lama's]] [[Gelug school]] of [[Tibetan Buddhism]]. {{Wiki|Alan Wallace}}, the editor, is one of his [[translators]] as well as a writer on [[Buddhism]] and [[science]]; the [[Dalai Lama's]] chief [[translator]], Thupten Jinpa,is probably the only [[Tibetan]] [[monk]] to have studied {{Wiki|Western philosophy}} to a doctoral level, and offers an [[interesting]] essay on [[Tibetan]] responses to [[science]]. [[Geshe]] [[Jinpa]] informs us that the [[Dalai Lama]] does more than encourage a {{Wiki|dialogue}} between [[Buddhism]] and [[science]]. He is prepared to let [[science]] change [[Buddhism]], so that if a fact emerges that is incompatible with [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}}, he says, ‘there is no [[doubt]] that we must accept the result of the [[scientific]] research’ (p. 77).
  
He ‘believes that the dynamic encounter with [[scientific]] [[thought]] could help revitalise [[Buddhist]] analysis of the [[nature]] of [[objective]] [[reality]] and the [[mind]]’ (p. 78). After all, as the [[Dalai Lama]] writes in a short piece for this [[book]] explaining the [[nature of mind]] in [[Tibetan Buddhism]] for the [[benefit]] of [[scientists]], ‘the [[mind]] is [[transformed]] when one ascertains and thoroughly acquaints oneself with fresh [[insights]] into the [[nature]] of [[reality]] that invalidate one's previous misconceptions or false assumptions’ (p. 96).  
+
He ‘believes that the dynamic encounter with [[scientific]] [[thought]] could help revitalise [[Buddhist]] analysis of the [[nature]] of [[objective]] [[reality]] and the [[mind]]’ (p. 78). After all, as the [[Dalai Lama]] writes in a short piece for this [[book]] explaining the [[nature of mind]] in [[Tibetan Buddhism]] for the [[benefit]] of [[scientists]], ‘the [[mind]] is [[transformed]] when one ascertains and thoroughly acquaints oneself with fresh [[insights]] into the [[nature]] of [[reality]] that invalidate one's previous misconceptions or false {{Wiki|assumptions}}’ (p. 96).  
  
 
A [[Buddhist]] is [[interested]] in the way things are, not in [[clinging]] to any specific description, even descriptions [[hallowed]] by centuries of [[transmission]] in a [[Buddhist tradition]]. The section on [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[science]] includes a very stimulating paper by the neuropsychologist David Galin. He engages thoroughly with [[Buddhist]] [[ideas]] on [[self]], being cheerfully prepared to challenge them without being dismissive.  
 
A [[Buddhist]] is [[interested]] in the way things are, not in [[clinging]] to any specific description, even descriptions [[hallowed]] by centuries of [[transmission]] in a [[Buddhist tradition]]. The section on [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[science]] includes a very stimulating paper by the neuropsychologist David Galin. He engages thoroughly with [[Buddhist]] [[ideas]] on [[self]], being cheerfully prepared to challenge them without being dismissive.  
  
It is well worth breasting the current of his sociological jargon for the sake of several gem-like [[insights]] on the [[human]] [[mind]]. How do we deal with the complexity of [[experience]]? Well, we ‘seek and find, or project, a simplifying pattern to approximate every complex field ... by lumping (ignoring some distinctions as negligible) and by splitting (ignoring some relations as negligible). Both ... create discreet entities useful for manipulating, predicting and controlling ... [but] may impose ad hoc boundaries on what are actually densely interconnected systems and then grant autonomous [[existence]] to the segments’ (p. [[108]]).  
+
It is well worth breasting the current of his {{Wiki|sociological}} jargon for the [[sake]] of several gem-like [[insights]] on the [[human]] [[mind]]. How do we deal with the complexity of [[experience]]? Well, we ‘seek and find, or project, a simplifying pattern to approximate every complex field ... by lumping (ignoring some {{Wiki|distinctions}} as negligible) and by splitting (ignoring some relations as negligible). Both ... create discreet entities useful for manipulating, predicting and controlling ... [but] may impose ad hoc [[boundaries]] on what are actually densely interconnected systems and then grant autonomous [[existence]] to the segments’ (p. [[108]]).  
  
Even the contents of our own [[consciousness]] have to be dealt with in this way, resulting in our array of fragmented self-concepts, and we just put up with the anomalies that arise. [[Buddhism]], he explains, agrees that discovering entities is conventionally indispensable, but [[attachment]] and [[aggression]] arise through reifying them, which violates the [[principle]] that all things are [[interdependent]], and all entities are conditional approximations. Galin is [[unhappy]] with [[Buddhism's]] [[moral]] disapproval for these self-errors, since they are ‘an [[essential]] evolutionary [[adaptation]]’ (p. 132). He applauds ‘the [[Buddhist]] solution to the {{Wiki|modern}} [[suffering]] of alienation and anomie ... to completely contextualise [[self]], not to simply erase it.’ (p. 137) He doesn't, I think, have [[confidence]] in the possibility of an unmediated immersion in [[experience]], making all selfviews obsolete. However, he recognises the importance of [[meditation]]. We evolve to act in cumulatively more sophisticated ways on the environment, and have become able to model the states resulting from alternative courses of [[action]] (i.e. [[karma]]). Sitting [[meditation]] eliminates [[physical]] [[action]], and progressively limits [[mental]] [[action]] by interrupting the loop that connects action-observationaction. Thus peripheral [[awareness]] has the [[space]] to grow, and to notice more and more facets of interrelatedness, allowing a more integrated [[mental]] structure to coalesce.  
+
Even the contents of our [[own]] [[consciousness]] have to be dealt with in this way, resulting in our array of fragmented self-concepts, and we just put up with the anomalies that arise. [[Buddhism]], he explains, agrees that discovering entities is {{Wiki|conventionally}} indispensable, but [[attachment]] and [[aggression]] arise through reifying them, which violates the [[principle]] that all things are [[interdependent]], and all entities are [[conditional]] {{Wiki|approximations}}. Galin is [[unhappy]] with [[Buddhism's]] [[moral]] disapproval for these self-errors, since they are ‘an [[essential]] evolutionary [[adaptation]]’ (p. 132). He applauds ‘the [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|solution}} to the {{Wiki|modern}} [[suffering]] of alienation and anomie ... to completely contextualise [[self]], not to simply erase it.’ (p. 137) He doesn't, I think, have [[confidence]] in the possibility of an unmediated immersion in [[experience]], making all selfviews obsolete. However, he recognises the importance of [[meditation]]. We evolve to act in cumulatively more sophisticated ways on the {{Wiki|environment}}, and have become able to model the states resulting from alternative courses of [[action]] (i.e. [[karma]]). Sitting [[meditation]] eliminates [[physical]] [[action]], and progressively limits [[mental]] [[action]] by interrupting the loop that connects action-observationaction. Thus peripheral [[awareness]] has the [[space]] to grow, and to notice more and more facets of interrelatedness, allowing a more integrated [[mental]] {{Wiki|structure}} to coalesce.  
  
Historically, the schools of {{Wiki|psychology}} in the [[West]] have sought to arrive at a final analysis of what the [[self]] actually is, and thus represent the operation of the first [[fetter]] that, according to the [[Buddha]], prevents irreversible [[Insight]]: fixed [[self]] [[view]] (satkā ya-ḍṛṣṭi). However, the present contributors do not represent this trend, which may have run its course.  
+
Historically, the schools of {{Wiki|psychology}} in the [[West]] have sought to arrive at a final analysis of what the [[self]] actually is, and thus represent the operation of the first [[fetter]] that, according to the [[Buddha]], prevents irreversible [[Insight]]: fixed [[self]] [[view]] (satkā ya-ḍṛṣṭi). However, the {{Wiki|present}} contributors do not represent this trend, which may have run its course.  
  
They recognise the fragmentary and contingent [[nature]] of the [[empirical]] [[self]]. William Waldron connects the accounts of {{Wiki|evolutionary psychology}} and [[Buddhism]] concerning the deeply rooted defensive predispositions erected around the [[sense]] of an independent ‘I’ . [[Human]] [[evil]] and [[suffering]] are [[caused]] by attempts to secure [[constructed]] selves, often at the expense of others. Waldron connects [[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|evolutionary psychology}}, claiming that both show that negative behavioural patterns ('[[evil]]') have a big influence over long periods of [[time]] in [[evolution]], being present in ourselves as inherited capacities, active all the [[time]] as predispositions.  
+
They recognise the fragmentary and contingent [[nature]] of the [[empirical]] [[self]]. [[William Waldron]] connects the accounts of {{Wiki|evolutionary psychology}} and [[Buddhism]] concerning the deeply rooted defensive predispositions erected around the [[sense]] of an {{Wiki|independent}} ‘I’ . [[Human]] [[evil]] and [[suffering]] are [[caused]] by attempts to secure [[constructed]] selves, often at the expense of others. Waldron connects [[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|evolutionary psychology}}, claiming that both show that negative behavioural patterns ('[[evil]]') have a big influence over long periods of [[time]] in [[evolution]], being {{Wiki|present}} in ourselves as inherited capacities, active all the [[time]] as predispositions.  
  
We can break such vicious, self-centred patterns by firstly [[understanding]] the [[human]] [[condition]], and then working to overcome their influence. Here, Waldron misses an opportunity to discuss the systematic teachings of [[Buddhist]] [[ethics]], an astonishing omission from the whole [[book]]. The simplest [[Buddhist]] formulation of the way to emancipating [[enlightenment]] outlines three trainings: the training in [[morality]], in [[meditation]], and in [[wisdom]]. [[Buddhism]] and [[Science]] makes an {{Wiki|excellent}} contribution to discussing the second and third in the [[light]] of {{Wiki|modern}} [[scientific]] approaches, but hardly mentions the first – [[morality]].  
+
We can break such vicious, self-centred patterns by firstly [[understanding]] the [[human]] [[condition]], and then working to overcome their influence. Here, Waldron misses an opportunity to discuss the systematic teachings of [[Buddhist]] [[ethics]], an astonishing omission from the whole [[book]]. The simplest [[Buddhist]] formulation of the way to emancipating [[enlightenment]] outlines [[three trainings]]: the {{Wiki|training}} in [[morality]], in [[meditation]], and in [[wisdom]]. [[Buddhism]] and [[Science]] makes an {{Wiki|excellent}} contribution to discussing the second and third in the [[light]] of {{Wiki|modern}} [[scientific]] approaches, but hardly mentions the first – [[morality]].  
  
Yet the connection between [[morality]] and [[scientific]] enterprises is a [[live]] topic in current discussions of [[science]], with very good [[reason]]. New [[scientific]] developments almost always have implications for [[human]] well-being [[beyond]] the [[satisfaction]] of the curiosity of the researchers, and [[beyond]] the promise of technologies for entertainment or labour-saving. For example, transport, agricultural (e.g. genetic modification) and power generation technologies can have major {{Wiki|environmental}} impacts. And {{Wiki|medical}} technologies can involve potentially harming some [[beings]] (including experimental [[animals]]) to fulfil the wishes of others. The [[book]] is rich in [[philosophical]] and [[psychological]] topics, but hardly mentions [[ethics]].[3]  
+
Yet the [[connection]] between [[morality]] and [[scientific]] enterprises is a [[live]] topic in current discussions of [[science]], with very good [[reason]]. New [[scientific]] developments almost always have implications for [[human]] well-being [[beyond]] the [[satisfaction]] of the {{Wiki|curiosity}} of the researchers, and [[beyond]] the promise of technologies for {{Wiki|entertainment}} or labour-saving. For example, transport, agricultural (e.g. {{Wiki|genetic}} modification) and power generation technologies can have major {{Wiki|environmental}} impacts. And {{Wiki|medical}} technologies can involve potentially harming some [[beings]] ([[including]] experimental [[animals]]) to fulfil the wishes of others. The [[book]] is rich in [[philosophical]] and [[psychological]] topics, but hardly mentions [[ethics]].[3]  
  
Another highly technical paper, again worth the [[effort]], is by Francisco Varela and Natalie Depraz. A Chilean {{Wiki|neuroscientist}} who tragically [[died]] in 2001, Varela has for some years been making very fruitful connections between [[Buddhist]] [[non-dual]] understandings of the [[mind]] (informed by his groundbreaking work on {{Wiki|brain}} states), and the work of the {{Wiki|French}} phenomenologists. Having established that actual [[experience]] and the states of the {{Wiki|brain}} act reciprocally upon one another, so that it is [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]] to say that {{Wiki|brain}} states simply [[cause]] {{Wiki|mental events}}, he and Depraz show how [[perception]] can be regarded as subsidiary to the [[mental]] [[function]] of [[imagination]]. [[Perception]] refers to what is present, [[imagination]] to what is not present, and the two mix so that in every moment they are [[emerging]] into [[awareness]] from an [[unconscious]] background, as a living present. It is still the case that the dominant [[view]] among neuroscientists is, in effect, that {{Wiki|processes}} in the [[body]] [[cause]] the [[mind]].  
+
Another highly technical paper, again worth the [[effort]], is by Francisco Varela and Natalie Depraz. A Chilean {{Wiki|neuroscientist}} who tragically [[died]] in 2001, Varela has for some years been making very fruitful connections between [[Buddhist]] [[non-dual]] understandings of the [[mind]] (informed by his groundbreaking work on {{Wiki|brain}} states), and the work of the {{Wiki|French}} [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenologists]]. Having established that actual [[experience]] and the states of the {{Wiki|brain}} act reciprocally upon one another, so that it is [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]] to say that {{Wiki|brain}} states simply [[cause]] {{Wiki|mental events}}, he and Depraz show how [[perception]] can be regarded as subsidiary to the [[mental]] [[function]] of [[imagination]]. [[Perception]] refers to what is {{Wiki|present}}, [[imagination]] to what is not {{Wiki|present}}, and the two mix so that in every [[moment]] they are [[emerging]] into [[awareness]] from an [[unconscious]] background, as a living {{Wiki|present}}. It is still the case that the dominant [[view]] among [[neuroscientists]] is, in effect, that {{Wiki|processes}} in the [[body]] [[cause]] the [[mind]].  
  
But Varela and Depraz have shown that one’s [[state of mind]] can access local neural {{Wiki|processes}}, so that neither can be reduced to the other. The [[mental state]] corresponds to a particular neural state, and actively incorporates or discards any contemporary neural [[activity]] in the relevant {{Wiki|brain}} region, evaluating many potential neural states ‘until a single one is transiently stabilised and expressed behaviourally’ (p. 213). [[Mental states]] require both a {{Wiki|phenomenological}} and a {{Wiki|biological}} account. The neural [[elements]] and the global [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[subject]] are co-determined; the [[subject]] is emergent, not just from the neural base, but also from preceding [[mental states]].  
+
But Varela and Depraz have shown that one’s [[state of mind]] can access local neural {{Wiki|processes}}, so that neither can be reduced to the other. The [[mental state]] corresponds to a particular neural [[state]], and actively incorporates or discards any contemporary neural [[activity]] in the relevant {{Wiki|brain}} region, evaluating many potential neural states ‘until a single one is transiently stabilised and expressed behaviourally’ (p. 213). [[Mental states]] require both a {{Wiki|phenomenological}} and a {{Wiki|biological}} account. The neural [[elements]] and the global [[Wikipedia:cognition|cognitive]] [[subject]] are co-determined; the [[subject]] is emergent, not just from the neural base, but also from preceding [[mental states]].  
  
[[Buddhism]] extends this account by [[offering]] its {{Wiki|pragmatic}} consequences, showing how the living present, with [[imagination]] active, is a means for [[human]] [[transformation]]. The authors then describe empathy-enhancing [[Tibetan]] [[visualisation]] techniques that effect this process. We can be dazzled by the power and scope of [[science]] into accepting the [[philosophical]] assumptions that many [[scientists]] [[live]] by. But the {{Wiki|materialist}} assumption, which includes the [[belief]] that the [[mind]] is only an epiphenomenon of the {{Wiki|brain}}, is shown by analyses such as that of Varela and Depraz to be a very odd one. After all, we know that we make free decisions to use our [[bodies]] in various ways: the [[mental]] is operating upon the [[physical]], as well as being constrained by the limitations of the [[physical]].  
+
[[Buddhism]] extends this account by [[offering]] its {{Wiki|pragmatic}} {{Wiki|consequences}}, showing how the living {{Wiki|present}}, with [[imagination]] active, is a means for [[human]] [[transformation]]. The authors then describe empathy-enhancing [[Tibetan]] [[visualisation]] [[techniques]] that effect this process. We can be dazzled by the power and scope of [[science]] into accepting the [[philosophical]] {{Wiki|assumptions}} that many [[scientists]] [[live]] by. But the {{Wiki|materialist}} assumption, which includes the [[belief]] that the [[mind]] is only an epiphenomenon of the {{Wiki|brain}}, is shown by analyses such as that of Varela and Depraz to be a very odd one. After all, we know that we make free decisions to use our [[bodies]] in various ways: the [[mental]] is operating upon the [[physical]], as well as being constrained by the limitations of the [[physical]].  
  
 
To suppress our [[knowledge]] of freedom of choice seems needless. The difficulty is that notions of reciprocal and interweaving causal {{Wiki|processes}} are comparatively new in the [[West]], so a [[scientist]] would be afraid that granting causal efficacy to the [[mind]] would be to grant that the whole [[material universe]] came into being merely by the force of [[ideas]]. A crucial contribution that [[Buddhism]] can make to [[science]] is to clarify the notion of [[dependent co-arising]] (pratītya samutpā da).  
 
To suppress our [[knowledge]] of freedom of choice seems needless. The difficulty is that notions of reciprocal and interweaving causal {{Wiki|processes}} are comparatively new in the [[West]], so a [[scientist]] would be afraid that granting causal efficacy to the [[mind]] would be to grant that the whole [[material universe]] came into being merely by the force of [[ideas]]. A crucial contribution that [[Buddhism]] can make to [[science]] is to clarify the notion of [[dependent co-arising]] (pratītya samutpā da).  
  
When we observe a [[phenomenon]], inner or outer, we can be confident that it arises and ceases through the coming together of innumerable cooperative [[conditions]], and that it [[forms]] an [[element]] in the complex of [[conditions]] out of which new [[phenomena]] are [[arising]]. Consequently, no [[phenomenon]] [[exists]] independently, nor can it persist, since its [[conditions]] are inevitably changing.  
+
When we observe a [[phenomenon]], inner or outer, we can be confident that it arises and ceases through the coming together of {{Wiki|innumerable}} cooperative [[conditions]], and that it [[forms]] an [[element]] in the complex of [[conditions]] out of which new [[phenomena]] are [[arising]]. Consequently, no [[phenomenon]] [[exists]] {{Wiki|independently}}, nor can it persist, since its [[conditions]] are inevitably changing.  
  
The [[name]] that we give it does not refer to any {{Wiki|real}} {{Wiki|entity}}, but is rather a sort of focused torchbeam selecting for our [[attention]] a little patch on the shifting cloudscape of [[experience]]. Varela and Depraz are refusing to see {{Wiki|brain}} and [[experience]] as isolated entities: ‘there is no gap to bridge, only traces to follow’ (p. 226). By allowing that [[human]] [[experience]] possesses a genuine causal agency, they are taking the subjective pole of [[reality]] seriously, something that is [[essential]] if we are to understand more fully the ways in which [[body]] and [[mind]] interact. Continuing research need not exclude [[consideration]] of those [[mental states]] which are comparatively less closely jointed to a {{Wiki|brain}}.  
+
The [[name]] that we give it does not refer to any {{Wiki|real}} {{Wiki|entity}}, but is rather a sort of focused torchbeam selecting for our [[attention]] a little patch on the shifting cloudscape of [[experience]]. Varela and Depraz are refusing to see {{Wiki|brain}} and [[experience]] as isolated entities: ‘there is no gap to bridge, only traces to follow’ (p. 226). By allowing that [[human]] [[experience]] possesses a genuine causal agency, they are taking the [[subjective]] pole of [[reality]] seriously, something that is [[essential]] if we are to understand more fully the ways in which [[body]] and [[mind]] interact. Continuing research need not exclude [[consideration]] of those [[mental states]] which are comparatively less closely jointed to a {{Wiki|brain}}.  
  
[[Buddhism]] at present diverges from [[science]] in incorporating in its worldview various apparently outof- [[body]] [[experiences]], including the possibility of [[consciousness]] unlinking from a dying [[body]] and [[relinking]] with a growing [[embryo]] – i.e. [[rebirth]]. It is disappointing that this volume is almost completely [[silent]] on [[rebirth]], despite the formidable investigations of Ian Stevenson.[4] [[Matthieu Ricard]] is a French-born [[Tibetan Buddhist]] [[monk]] with a background in [[science]], whose published conversations with his [[philosopher]] father became a bestseller.[5]  
+
[[Buddhism]] at {{Wiki|present}} diverges from [[science]] in incorporating in its worldview various apparently outof- [[body]] [[experiences]], [[including]] the possibility of [[consciousness]] unlinking from a dying [[body]] and [[relinking]] with a growing [[embryo]] – i.e. [[rebirth]]. It is disappointing that this volume is almost completely [[silent]] on [[rebirth]], despite the formidable investigations of {{Wiki|Ian Stevenson}}.[4] [[Matthieu Ricard]] is a French-born [[Tibetan Buddhist]] [[monk]] with a background in [[science]], whose published conversations with his [[philosopher]] father became a bestseller.[5]  
  
His article is on ‘Contemplative [[Science]]’, a vogue designation for [[Buddhism]] that is perhaps trying to appropriate some of the prestige of [[science]]. However, the term does highlight the fact that [[meditation]] and other [[mental]] [[disciplines]] should be seen as valid methods for investigating the [[mind]], complementing the [[objective]] techniques of {{Wiki|brain}} scans and psychiatrists' questionnaires.  
+
His article is on ‘Contemplative [[Science]]’, a vogue designation for [[Buddhism]] that is perhaps trying to appropriate some of the prestige of [[science]]. However, the term does highlight the fact that [[meditation]] and other [[mental]] [[disciplines]] should be seen as valid [[methods]] for investigating the [[mind]], complementing the [[objective]] [[techniques]] of {{Wiki|brain}} scans and psychiatrists' questionnaires.  
  
Many centuries ago, the dialecticians of the Mā dhyamaka school of [[Buddhism]] (starting with Nagā rjuna) tackled [[Indian]] [[philosophical]] positions that in some ways resemble the standpoints of {{Wiki|modern}} [[scientists]]. But it seems to me that Ricard shares with some of the other contributors to this [[book]], notably Wallace, an unreflective overconfidence in the potency of these arguments against [[views]] that after all arise from a very different, and often very {{Wiki|subtle}}, [[philosophical]] background.  
+
Many centuries ago, the [[Wikipedia:Dialectician|dialecticians]] of the Mā dhyamaka school of [[Buddhism]] (starting with Nagā rjuna) tackled [[Indian]] [[philosophical]] positions that in some ways resemble the standpoints of {{Wiki|modern}} [[scientists]]. But it seems to me that Ricard shares with some of the other contributors to this [[book]], notably Wallace, an unreflective overconfidence in the [[potency]] of these arguments against [[views]] that after all arise from a very different, and often very {{Wiki|subtle}}, [[philosophical]] background.  
  
{{Wiki|Western}} [[thought]] already provides well-developed approaches to [[understanding]] [[reality]], which have spotted the weaknesses of [[dualistic]], mechanistic, essentialist and idealist [[views]]; in this volume we have {{Wiki|excellent}} presentations on {{Wiki|Kant}} (Bitbol), and on phenomenology (Varela and Depraz). One might add Spinoza, who so inspired {{Wiki|Einstein}}, and is the [[subject]] of a recent [[book]] by {{Wiki|neuroscientist}} {{Wiki|Antonio Damasio}},[6] as well as {{Wiki|William James}}, Karl Popper and others. Much hard work will be involved in integrating these thinkers with [[Buddhism]] (as the astrophysicist Piet Hut points out in the concluding paper in this volume), but it will be very productive, and surely they cannot be ignored.  
+
{{Wiki|Western}} [[thought]] already provides well-developed approaches to [[understanding]] [[reality]], which have spotted the weaknesses of [[dualistic]], mechanistic, essentialist and {{Wiki|idealist}} [[views]]; in this volume we have {{Wiki|excellent}} presentations on {{Wiki|Kant}} (Bitbol), and on [[Wikipedia:Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] (Varela and Depraz). One might add {{Wiki|Spinoza}}, who so inspired {{Wiki|Einstein}}, and is the [[subject]] of a recent [[book]] by {{Wiki|neuroscientist}} {{Wiki|Antonio Damasio}},[6] as well as {{Wiki|William James}}, [[Karl Popper]] and others. Much hard work will be involved in integrating these thinkers with [[Buddhism]] (as the astrophysicist Piet Hut points out in the concluding paper in this volume), but it will be very {{Wiki|productive}}, and surely they cannot be ignored.  
  
 
Eventually, though, we will need a new [[Tsongkhapa]]: a fine [[scholar]] with a brilliant [[mind]], highly realised through [[meditation]] practice. Meanwhile, the more unreflective {{Wiki|western}} Mā dhyamikans, as well as putting old arguments into new bottles, also tend to conflate [[Buddhism]] as a whole with Mā dhyamaka [[thought]], presenting rival [[Buddhist]] [[doctrines]] as if they had been been conclusively refuted by Nagā rjuna and his successors in the [[Tibetan]] [[Gelug school]].  
 
Eventually, though, we will need a new [[Tsongkhapa]]: a fine [[scholar]] with a brilliant [[mind]], highly realised through [[meditation]] practice. Meanwhile, the more unreflective {{Wiki|western}} Mā dhyamikans, as well as putting old arguments into new bottles, also tend to conflate [[Buddhism]] as a whole with Mā dhyamaka [[thought]], presenting rival [[Buddhist]] [[doctrines]] as if they had been been conclusively refuted by Nagā rjuna and his successors in the [[Tibetan]] [[Gelug school]].  
  
There are [[scholars]] [[writing]] on [[science]] under the influence of other branches of [[Buddhism]], and it is a great [[shame]] that the editor did not bring in their perspectives. For example, several writers on [[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Ecology}} (a topic unfortunately absent from this [[book]]) have practised in Theravā da and [[Zen]], including Joanna Macy, Kenneth Kraft, Leslie Sponsel, [[Bhikkhu Bodhi]], and others. (There is also a bit of a national bias, more than half of the contributors being {{Wiki|Americans}}.) The {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|physics}} section of [[Buddhism]] and [[Science]] explores the surprising departures from downto- [[earth]] realism that have been [[emerging]] mainly in {{Wiki|quantum mechanics}} during the past century.  
+
There are [[scholars]] [[writing]] on [[science]] under the influence of other branches of [[Buddhism]], and it is a great [[shame]] that the editor did not bring in their perspectives. For example, several writers on [[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Ecology}} (a topic unfortunately absent from this [[book]]) have practised in Theravā da and [[Zen]], [[including]] [[Joanna Macy]], Kenneth Kraft, Leslie Sponsel, [[Bhikkhu Bodhi]], and others. (There is also a bit of a national bias, more than half of the contributors being {{Wiki|Americans}}.) The {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|physics}} section of [[Buddhism]] and [[Science]] explores the surprising departures from downto- [[earth]] [[realism]] that have been [[emerging]] mainly in {{Wiki|quantum mechanics}} during the {{Wiki|past}} century.  
  
Fitjof Capra popularised some of the parallels with [[Buddhism]], in a general and rather unconvincing way, in his very influential The {{Wiki|Tao}} of {{Wiki|Physics}}, published nearly 30 years ago. Despite my protestations above, I must admit that a rigorous application of Mā dhyamaka {{Wiki|epistemology}} to {{Wiki|physics}}, as we see in several of the contributions here, promises to be far more genuinely [[illuminating]] than the vague (often [[verbal]]) parallels of Capra. But the most impressive paper is by the {{Wiki|French}} [[philosopher]] of [[science]] Michel Bitbol. (He characterises Capra and others as [[offering]]: ‘mere analogy at an ill-defined level of the two discourses, with obvious apologetic purposes’ (p. 327).)  
+
Fitjof Capra popularised some of the parallels with [[Buddhism]], in a general and rather unconvincing way, in his very influential The {{Wiki|Tao}} of {{Wiki|Physics}}, published nearly 30 years ago. Despite my protestations above, I must admit that a rigorous application of Mā dhyamaka {{Wiki|epistemology}} to {{Wiki|physics}}, as we see in several of the contributions here, promises to be far more genuinely [[illuminating]] than the vague (often [[verbal]]) parallels of Capra. But the most impressive paper is by the {{Wiki|French}} [[philosopher]] of [[science]] Michel Bitbol. (He characterises Capra and others as [[offering]]: ‘mere analogy at an ill-defined level of the two [[discourses]], with obvious apologetic purposes’ (p. 327).)  
  
His 'Cure for [[Metaphysical]] [[Illusions]]' is an extremely thorough, and difficult, elucidation of neo-Kantian [[philosophy]] of [[science]], explaining how Mā dhyamaka approaches can build on it, and extend it radically. Like Nagā rjuna, {{Wiki|Kant}} was aware of the limitations of [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. They are only for the formal ordering of the [[empirical]] contents, a process that will never end, though [[reason]] provides an inaccessible goal of complete [[rational]] [[understanding]] to regulate the process. Unaware of this as we generally are, it is easy to take the [[form]] that our {{Wiki|intellect}} gives to [[phenomena]] as being the [[form]] of the things in themselves, ‘projecting the a priori structure of the [[knowing]] [[subject]] onto the [[world]], thus mistaking it for a pregiven [[worldly]] structure’ (p. 328).  
+
His 'Cure for [[Metaphysical]] [[Illusions]]' is an extremely thorough, and difficult, elucidation of neo-Kantian [[philosophy]] of [[science]], explaining how Mā dhyamaka approaches can build on it, and extend it radically. Like Nagā rjuna, {{Wiki|Kant}} was {{Wiki|aware}} of the limitations of [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. They are only for the formal ordering of the [[empirical]] contents, a process that will never end, though [[reason]] provides an inaccessible goal of complete [[rational]] [[understanding]] to regulate the process. Unaware of this as we generally are, it is easy to take the [[form]] that our {{Wiki|intellect}} gives to [[phenomena]] as being the [[form]] of the things in themselves, ‘projecting the {{Wiki|a priori}} {{Wiki|structure}} of the [[knowing]] [[subject]] onto the [[world]], thus mistaking it for a pregiven [[worldly]] {{Wiki|structure}}’ (p. 328).  
  
 
This is the all-pervasive ‘[[transcendental]] [[illusion]]’, which is very hard to recognise, let alone to compensate for. Bitbol calls on the neo-Kantian [[philosophers]] of [[science]] to help us with recognising it, but needs to bring in [[Buddhism]] to show us how to overcome the [[illusion]]. ‘Nagā rjuna's exclusive [[mission]] was to free everyone from the spell of reified [[conventional truth]]’ (p. 332). (Bitbol helpfully points out in a note that [[saṃvṛti-satya]], usually translated '[[conventional truth]]', is more literally a surface [[truth]] covering over [[ultimate truth]].)  
 
This is the all-pervasive ‘[[transcendental]] [[illusion]]’, which is very hard to recognise, let alone to compensate for. Bitbol calls on the neo-Kantian [[philosophers]] of [[science]] to help us with recognising it, but needs to bring in [[Buddhism]] to show us how to overcome the [[illusion]]. ‘Nagā rjuna's exclusive [[mission]] was to free everyone from the spell of reified [[conventional truth]]’ (p. 332). (Bitbol helpfully points out in a note that [[saṃvṛti-satya]], usually translated '[[conventional truth]]', is more literally a surface [[truth]] covering over [[ultimate truth]].)  
  
Thus, ‘to be in nirvā na means [[seeing]] the very same things that appear to the deluded [[consciousness]] of sa.msā ra, but [[seeing]] them as they are – as merely [[empty]], dependent, [[impermanent]], and [[non-substantial]]' (p.333). Efforts towards a compromise between [[science]] and [[religion]] in the 19th century [[West]] failed, leading to a schizophrenic [[attitude]] in which a system of [[beliefs]] and values were seen as indispensable, but the available system ([[monotheism]]) was [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]] in the [[light]] of [[science]]. Bitbol wishes to initiate the construction of a single higher-order tool, combining [[science]], [[philosophy]], and the ‘nondogmatic {{Wiki|soteriology}}’ [[offered]] by the Mā dhyamaka.  
+
Thus, ‘to be in nirvā na means [[seeing]] the very same things that appear to the deluded [[consciousness]] of sa.msā ra, but [[seeing]] them as they are – as merely [[empty]], dependent, [[impermanent]], and [[non-substantial]]' (p.333). Efforts towards a compromise between [[science]] and [[religion]] in the 19th century [[West]] failed, leading to a schizophrenic [[attitude]] in which a system of [[beliefs]] and values were seen as indispensable, but the available system ([[monotheism]]) was [[Wikipedia:Coherentism|incoherent]] in the [[light]] of [[science]]. Bitbol wishes to [[initiate]] the construction of a single higher-order tool, [[combining]] [[science]], [[philosophy]], and the ‘nondogmatic {{Wiki|soteriology}}’ [[offered]] by the Mā dhyamaka.  
  
 
The new tool needs to rely on the ‘dynamic potentialities’ of [[doctrines]], not their [[Wikipedia:canonical|canonical]] texts, [[seeing]] them as operational rather than {{Wiki|dogmatic}}. [[Scientific]] theories are not {{Wiki|representations}} of the [[world]], but are for structuring our [[actions]] and anticipating their outcomes, with [[philosophy]] helping adjust us between all the possibilities of [[action]] within a value system; then [[Buddhism]] opens [[life]] out in self-transformation.  
 
The new tool needs to rely on the ‘dynamic potentialities’ of [[doctrines]], not their [[Wikipedia:canonical|canonical]] texts, [[seeing]] them as operational rather than {{Wiki|dogmatic}}. [[Scientific]] theories are not {{Wiki|representations}} of the [[world]], but are for structuring our [[actions]] and anticipating their outcomes, with [[philosophy]] helping adjust us between all the possibilities of [[action]] within a value system; then [[Buddhism]] opens [[life]] out in self-transformation.  
  
[[Science]] does not reveal a pre-existent underlying [[absolute reality]] (realism), yet it is more than a set of useful techniques (instrumentalism), being ‘the stabilised byproduct of the dynamic reciprocal [[relation]] between [[reality]] as a whole and a special fraction of it’ – the [[subject]] (p. 337). The structure of [[scientific]] theories is highly significant; they are not arbitrary, but it is possible nevertheless to remain metaphysically agnostic. In fact, Bitbol convincingly argues that this kind of [[philosophy]] of [[science]] is far more compatible with {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|physics}}, especially {{Wiki|quantum mechanics}}, than the [[belief]] in a mechanistic [[world]] and a [[dualistic]] {{Wiki|epistemology}}. [[Scientists]] resist relationalist and [[nondual]] [[philosophies]] through {{Wiki|fear}} of having no ground to stand on.  
+
[[Science]] does not reveal a pre-existent underlying [[absolute reality]] ([[realism]]), yet it is more than a set of useful [[techniques]] (instrumentalism), being ‘the stabilised byproduct of the dynamic reciprocal [[relation]] between [[reality]] as a whole and a special fraction of it’ – the [[subject]] (p. 337). The {{Wiki|structure}} of [[scientific]] theories is highly significant; they are not arbitrary, but it is possible nevertheless to remain [[Wikipedia:Metaphysics|metaphysically]] agnostic. In fact, Bitbol convincingly argues that this kind of [[philosophy]] of [[science]] is far more compatible with {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|physics}}, especially {{Wiki|quantum mechanics}}, than the [[belief]] in a mechanistic [[world]] and a [[dualistic]] {{Wiki|epistemology}}. [[Scientists]] resist relationalist and [[nondual]] [[philosophies]] through {{Wiki|fear}} of having no ground to stand on.  
  
 
They can take [[heart]], says Bitbol. Mā dhyamaka dialectically deconstructs substantialist and [[dualistic]] [[views]], but it also introduces ‘a [[form]] of [[life]] in which losing ground is not a tragedy (it can even promote [[enlightenment]]...) and in which an alternative (say, {{Wiki|pragmatic}}, integrated, and {{Wiki|altruistic}}) strong [[motivation]] can be given to [[science]]’ (p. 339). There is not [[space]] here to detail Bitbol’s compelling [[philosophical]] framework for {{Wiki|quantum mechanics}}, but I will mention his response to the problem of {{Wiki|indeterminism}} – the unpredictability of {{Wiki|quantum}} events. Is it that chance is [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]], and any deterministic laws that we find come from the law of large numbers?  
 
They can take [[heart]], says Bitbol. Mā dhyamaka dialectically deconstructs substantialist and [[dualistic]] [[views]], but it also introduces ‘a [[form]] of [[life]] in which losing ground is not a tragedy (it can even promote [[enlightenment]]...) and in which an alternative (say, {{Wiki|pragmatic}}, integrated, and {{Wiki|altruistic}}) strong [[motivation]] can be given to [[science]]’ (p. 339). There is not [[space]] here to detail Bitbol’s compelling [[philosophical]] framework for {{Wiki|quantum mechanics}}, but I will mention his response to the problem of {{Wiki|indeterminism}} – the unpredictability of {{Wiki|quantum}} events. Is it that chance is [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]], and any deterministic laws that we find come from the law of large numbers?  
Line 73: Line 81:
 
Or is it that [[determinism]] is [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]], and apparent randomness comes from the complexity of huge numbers of interacting events, as studied in {{Wiki|chaos}} {{Wiki|theory}}? If we take a dependent co-arising-type approach, we will see that the [[causes]] of any event are not defined in the [[absolute]], but are ‘[[relative]] to the very circumstances of the production of the [[phenomena]]’ (p. 349).  
 
Or is it that [[determinism]] is [[Wikipedia:Absolute (philosophy)|ultimate]], and apparent randomness comes from the complexity of huge numbers of interacting events, as studied in {{Wiki|chaos}} {{Wiki|theory}}? If we take a dependent co-arising-type approach, we will see that the [[causes]] of any event are not defined in the [[absolute]], but are ‘[[relative]] to the very circumstances of the production of the [[phenomena]]’ (p. 349).  
  
Since [[phenomena]] arise in {{Wiki|dependence}} upon an enormously complex context, a context which includes the [[person]] or instrumentation detecting the [[phenomena]], they are immune to any certain [[determination]]. Relations between things should be seen as being prior to the things that are relating; however, ‘neither connection, nor connected nor connector [[exist]]’, says Nagā rjuna. [[Buddhism’s]] radical analysis is needed to cap [[philosophy]] of [[science]], since it comes from ‘direct stabilised [[experience]] of a disabused outlook’ – i.e., [[non-conceptual]] [[Insight]] into [[reality]] – while the [[insights]] of {{Wiki|Western philosophy}}, impressive though they are, are the products of the free play of [[ideas]]. [[Buddhism]] and [[Science]] succeeds so well because all its contributors take both [[Buddhism]] and [[science]] seriously, [[seeing]] that both represent ways of [[understanding]] [[human]] [[experience]], and both present opportunities for enhancing its quality.  
+
Since [[phenomena]] arise in {{Wiki|dependence}} upon an enormously complex context, a context which includes the [[person]] or instrumentation detecting the [[phenomena]], they are immune to any certain [[determination]]. Relations between things should be seen as being prior to the things that are relating; however, ‘neither [[connection]], nor connected nor connector [[exist]]’, says Nagā rjuna. [[Buddhism’s]] radical analysis is needed to cap [[philosophy]] of [[science]], since it comes from ‘direct stabilised [[experience]] of a disabused outlook’ – i.e., [[non-conceptual]] [[Insight]] into [[reality]] – while the [[insights]] of {{Wiki|Western philosophy}}, impressive though they are, are the products of the free play of [[ideas]]. [[Buddhism]] and [[Science]] succeeds so well because all its contributors take both [[Buddhism]] and [[science]] seriously, [[seeing]] that both represent ways of [[understanding]] [[human]] [[experience]], and both {{Wiki|present}} opportunities for enhancing its [[quality]].  
  
Although Joseph Needham was able to write so dismissively of [[Buddhism]] only a few decades ago, we now know that he was mistaken. We know because [[scientists]] are engaging personally with the practice of [[Buddhism]]. They are finding in it a congenial [[spirituality]] which does not nag at their work so long as that work does no harm. They are also finding that it offers remarkable new vistas into the methods and models of [[science]] itself. But will [[Buddhism]] ever actually influence [[scientific]] practice – where to look in one's research, how to explain and interpret one’s findings?  
+
Although [[Joseph Needham]] was able to write so dismissively of [[Buddhism]] only a few decades ago, we now know that he was mistaken. We know because [[scientists]] are engaging personally with the practice of [[Buddhism]]. They are finding in it a congenial [[spirituality]] which does not nag at their work so long as that work does no harm. They are also finding that it offers remarkable new vistas into the [[methods]] and models of [[science]] itself. But will [[Buddhism]] ever actually influence [[scientific]] practice – where to look in one's research, how to explain and interpret one’s findings?  
  
This [[book]] will convince the reader that mind-science has already been changed by [[Buddhism]], but the jury is still out on {{Wiki|physics}}. Francisco Varela has no [[doubt]]. His assessment, [[thinking]] particularly of [[Buddhism]] impacting [[science]], is that ‘the rediscovery of {{Wiki|Asian}} [[philosophy]], particularly of the [[Buddhist tradition]], is a second {{Wiki|Renaissance}} in the {{Wiki|cultural}} history of the [[West]], with the potential to be equally important as the rediscovery of {{Wiki|Greek}} [[thought]] in the {{Wiki|European}} {{Wiki|Renaissance}}.’[7] The dialogue has only just begun; we [[live]] in exciting times.  
+
This [[book]] will convince the reader that mind-science has already been changed by [[Buddhism]], but the jury is still out on {{Wiki|physics}}. Francisco Varela has no [[doubt]]. His assessment, [[thinking]] particularly of [[Buddhism]] impacting [[science]], is that ‘the rediscovery of {{Wiki|Asian}} [[philosophy]], particularly of the [[Buddhist tradition]], is a second {{Wiki|Renaissance}} in the {{Wiki|cultural}} history of the [[West]], with the potential to be equally important as the rediscovery of {{Wiki|Greek}} [[thought]] in the {{Wiki|European}} {{Wiki|Renaissance}}.’[7] The {{Wiki|dialogue}} has only just begun; we [[live]] in exciting times.  
 
==Notes==
 
==Notes==
  
:[1]. Joseph Needham, The Shorter Science and Civilisation in China, Volume I (Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 264, 265, 272.  
+
:[1]. [[Joseph Needham]], The Shorter [[Science]] and {{Wiki|Civilisation}} in [[China]], Volume I ({{Wiki|Cambridge University Press}}, 1978), pp. 264, 265, 272.  
:[2]. Robin Cooper, The Evolving Mind: Buddhism, Biology and Consciousness (Windhorse Publications, Birmingham, 1996).
+
:[2]. Robin Cooper, The Evolving [[Mind]]: [[Buddhism]], {{Wiki|Biology}} and [[Consciousness]] ([[Windhorse Publications]], {{Wiki|Birmingham}}, 1996).
:[3]. For a good survey, see Damien Keown, Buddhism and Bioethics (Macmillan, London, 1995).  
+
:[3]. For a good survey, see [[Damien Keown]], [[Buddhism]] and {{Wiki|Bioethics}} (Macmillan, [[London]], 1995).  
:[4]. e.g. Ian Stevenson, Twenty Cases Suggestive of Reincarnation (University Press of Virginia, 1974).
+
:[4]. e.g. {{Wiki|Ian Stevenson}}, Twenty Cases Suggestive of [[Reincarnation]] ({{Wiki|University}} Press of Virginia, 1974).
:[5]. Jean-Francois Revel and Matthieu Ricard, The Monk and the Philosopher (Thorsons, London, 1998).
+
:[5]. {{Wiki|Jean-Francois Revel}} and [[Matthieu Ricard]], The [[Monk]] and the [[Philosopher]] (Thorsons, [[London]], 1998).
:[6]. Antonio Damasio, Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow and the Feeling Brain (Heinemann, 2003).  
+
:[6]. {{Wiki|Antonio Damasio}}, Looking for {{Wiki|Spinoza}}: [[Joy]], [[Sorrow]] and the [[Feeling]] {{Wiki|Brain}} (Heinemann, 2003).  
:[7]. Varela, Thomson, and Rosch, The Embodied Mind (MIT press, 1993), p.22.
+
:[7]. Varela, Thomson, and Rosch, The [[Embodied]] [[Mind]] (MIT press, 1993), p.22.
  
  

Latest revision as of 17:30, 30 November 2023


LoB12.jpg
Mb4.JPG
Braindsa.jpg
Kuh0064.JPG
24a4x.jpg
Preaching.JPG
159.jpg
554f (10).jpg
Mara Daughters.JPG
Padma a2.jpg





Buddhism and Science: Breaking New Ground
B. Alan Wallace (editor), Columbia University Press, New York, 2003.
Dharmacari Ratnaprabha (Robin Cooper)

The great Marxist sinologist Joseph Needham blamed Buddhism for stifling science and technology in China while they flourished in Europe. In claiming that everything is an illusion, Buddhism ‘played a part in strangling the development of Chinese science’. Zen Buddhism, in ‘rejecting all philosophy’ was also unfavourable to a scientific view.

Since the Buddha refused to speculate, Buddhism discouraged scientific research. Above all, its main object is to escape from this world, not to try to understand it. A ‘despairing’ and ‘perverse’ philosophy, he concludes.[1] Needham's analysis stands in marked contrast to all the sixteen contributors to this book, and indeed to the prevailing view today that of all the religions Buddhism is the most compatible with science. It is certainly a fact of history that a great surge in systematic scientific research, followed by technologies with overwhelming effects, took place in Europe from the eighteenth century onwards.

Despite its sophisticated civilisations, science in Asia had to await influence from Europe before it was able to make comparable advances. A common view has been that there was a religious factor in this difference, that something in Protestant Christianity favoured science. However, an excellent essay in this volume by Jose Ignacio Cabezon indicates that the conditioning factors were far more complex, and that when Western science did arrive in Asia, it was treated by Buddhists in an open and welcoming way, in contrast to the responses to science of many European churchmen. When science did arrive, some South Asian Buddhist monks were tempted either to detect prefigurings of scientific discoveries in Buddhist texts, or to laud Buddhism as the most scientific of religions, and the Buddha as the first scientist.

They were supported, from Victorian times onwards, by westerners' responses to Buddhism. Cabezon points out that human beings have at first a tendency to treat what is culturally very different in terms of the culturally familiar, so a host of compatibilities between Buddhism and science were discerned. Buddhism was seen as undogmatic, giving authority to the individual, critical in spirit, with a universal impersonal causal law (like science), and with a scientific ethics. Colonel Olcott, a Theosophist instrumental in the revival of Buddhism in Sri Lanka, pointed out around 1889 that Buddhism shared an evolutionary vision with science, both teaching ‘that man is the result of the law of development, from an imperfect lower, to a higher and perfect condition’ (p. 44).

(I have explored this connection elsewhere.)[2] Cabezon argues that the unsophisticated view of compatibility, or even identity, between Buddhism and science is now being replaced by one of complementarity. Each has something to offer the other. The contributors to this volume point out a number of such cross-fertilisations, concentrating on two areas in which Buddhist thought may be able to advance scientific understanding: cognitive science and modern physics. There is one man in particular who should be credited both with stimulating Western scientists to investigate Buddhism, and with reassuring Buddhists that they have nothing to fear from science – the Dalai Lama.

As an inquisitive boy-lama roaming around in the vast Potala Palace, he loved to investigate exotic Western mechanical devices, as well as quizzing his tutors on science. Somewhere he relates how, as he turned a globe in his hands, it gradually dawned on him that this was a representation of our spherical world, and the flat cosmology of the ancient Indian texts had now been superseded. He has never lost his eager fascination for science, and he instigated a continuing series of biennial meetings with groups of Western scientists in which a number of topics have been freely explored. (The meetings are organised by the Mind-Life Institute, and an appendix in the book lists those which have been published so far.)

Thus many of the contributors have been involved in the Mind-Life conferences, and have to varying extents practised or studied within the Dalai Lama's Gelug school of Tibetan Buddhism. Alan Wallace, the editor, is one of his translators as well as a writer on Buddhism and science; the Dalai Lama's chief translator, Thupten Jinpa,is probably the only Tibetan monk to have studied Western philosophy to a doctoral level, and offers an interesting essay on Tibetan responses to science. Geshe Jinpa informs us that the Dalai Lama does more than encourage a dialogue between Buddhism and science. He is prepared to let science change Buddhism, so that if a fact emerges that is incompatible with Buddhist theory, he says, ‘there is no doubt that we must accept the result of the scientific research’ (p. 77).

He ‘believes that the dynamic encounter with scientific thought could help revitalise Buddhist analysis of the nature of objective reality and the mind’ (p. 78). After all, as the Dalai Lama writes in a short piece for this book explaining the nature of mind in Tibetan Buddhism for the benefit of scientists, ‘the mind is transformed when one ascertains and thoroughly acquaints oneself with fresh insights into the nature of reality that invalidate one's previous misconceptions or false assumptions’ (p. 96).

A Buddhist is interested in the way things are, not in clinging to any specific description, even descriptions hallowed by centuries of transmission in a Buddhist tradition. The section on cognitive science includes a very stimulating paper by the neuropsychologist David Galin. He engages thoroughly with Buddhist ideas on self, being cheerfully prepared to challenge them without being dismissive.

It is well worth breasting the current of his sociological jargon for the sake of several gem-like insights on the human mind. How do we deal with the complexity of experience? Well, we ‘seek and find, or project, a simplifying pattern to approximate every complex field ... by lumping (ignoring some distinctions as negligible) and by splitting (ignoring some relations as negligible). Both ... create discreet entities useful for manipulating, predicting and controlling ... [but] may impose ad hoc boundaries on what are actually densely interconnected systems and then grant autonomous existence to the segments’ (p. 108).

Even the contents of our own consciousness have to be dealt with in this way, resulting in our array of fragmented self-concepts, and we just put up with the anomalies that arise. Buddhism, he explains, agrees that discovering entities is conventionally indispensable, but attachment and aggression arise through reifying them, which violates the principle that all things are interdependent, and all entities are conditional approximations. Galin is unhappy with Buddhism's moral disapproval for these self-errors, since they are ‘an essential evolutionary adaptation’ (p. 132). He applauds ‘the Buddhist solution to the modern suffering of alienation and anomie ... to completely contextualise self, not to simply erase it.’ (p. 137) He doesn't, I think, have confidence in the possibility of an unmediated immersion in experience, making all selfviews obsolete. However, he recognises the importance of meditation. We evolve to act in cumulatively more sophisticated ways on the environment, and have become able to model the states resulting from alternative courses of action (i.e. karma). Sitting meditation eliminates physical action, and progressively limits mental action by interrupting the loop that connects action-observationaction. Thus peripheral awareness has the space to grow, and to notice more and more facets of interrelatedness, allowing a more integrated mental structure to coalesce.

Historically, the schools of psychology in the West have sought to arrive at a final analysis of what the self actually is, and thus represent the operation of the first fetter that, according to the Buddha, prevents irreversible Insight: fixed self view (satkā ya-ḍṛṣṭi). However, the present contributors do not represent this trend, which may have run its course.

They recognise the fragmentary and contingent nature of the empirical self. William Waldron connects the accounts of evolutionary psychology and Buddhism concerning the deeply rooted defensive predispositions erected around the sense of an independent ‘I’ . Human evil and suffering are caused by attempts to secure constructed selves, often at the expense of others. Waldron connects Buddhism and evolutionary psychology, claiming that both show that negative behavioural patterns ('evil') have a big influence over long periods of time in evolution, being present in ourselves as inherited capacities, active all the time as predispositions.

We can break such vicious, self-centred patterns by firstly understanding the human condition, and then working to overcome their influence. Here, Waldron misses an opportunity to discuss the systematic teachings of Buddhist ethics, an astonishing omission from the whole book. The simplest Buddhist formulation of the way to emancipating enlightenment outlines three trainings: the training in morality, in meditation, and in wisdom. Buddhism and Science makes an excellent contribution to discussing the second and third in the light of modern scientific approaches, but hardly mentions the first – morality.

Yet the connection between morality and scientific enterprises is a live topic in current discussions of science, with very good reason. New scientific developments almost always have implications for human well-being beyond the satisfaction of the curiosity of the researchers, and beyond the promise of technologies for entertainment or labour-saving. For example, transport, agricultural (e.g. genetic modification) and power generation technologies can have major environmental impacts. And medical technologies can involve potentially harming some beings (including experimental animals) to fulfil the wishes of others. The book is rich in philosophical and psychological topics, but hardly mentions ethics.[3]

Another highly technical paper, again worth the effort, is by Francisco Varela and Natalie Depraz. A Chilean neuroscientist who tragically died in 2001, Varela has for some years been making very fruitful connections between Buddhist non-dual understandings of the mind (informed by his groundbreaking work on brain states), and the work of the French phenomenologists. Having established that actual experience and the states of the brain act reciprocally upon one another, so that it is incoherent to say that brain states simply cause mental events, he and Depraz show how perception can be regarded as subsidiary to the mental function of imagination. Perception refers to what is present, imagination to what is not present, and the two mix so that in every moment they are emerging into awareness from an unconscious background, as a living present. It is still the case that the dominant view among neuroscientists is, in effect, that processes in the body cause the mind.

But Varela and Depraz have shown that one’s state of mind can access local neural processes, so that neither can be reduced to the other. The mental state corresponds to a particular neural state, and actively incorporates or discards any contemporary neural activity in the relevant brain region, evaluating many potential neural states ‘until a single one is transiently stabilised and expressed behaviourally’ (p. 213). Mental states require both a phenomenological and a biological account. The neural elements and the global cognitive subject are co-determined; the subject is emergent, not just from the neural base, but also from preceding mental states.

Buddhism extends this account by offering its pragmatic consequences, showing how the living present, with imagination active, is a means for human transformation. The authors then describe empathy-enhancing Tibetan visualisation techniques that effect this process. We can be dazzled by the power and scope of science into accepting the philosophical assumptions that many scientists live by. But the materialist assumption, which includes the belief that the mind is only an epiphenomenon of the brain, is shown by analyses such as that of Varela and Depraz to be a very odd one. After all, we know that we make free decisions to use our bodies in various ways: the mental is operating upon the physical, as well as being constrained by the limitations of the physical.

To suppress our knowledge of freedom of choice seems needless. The difficulty is that notions of reciprocal and interweaving causal processes are comparatively new in the West, so a scientist would be afraid that granting causal efficacy to the mind would be to grant that the whole material universe came into being merely by the force of ideas. A crucial contribution that Buddhism can make to science is to clarify the notion of dependent co-arising (pratītya samutpā da).

When we observe a phenomenon, inner or outer, we can be confident that it arises and ceases through the coming together of innumerable cooperative conditions, and that it forms an element in the complex of conditions out of which new phenomena are arising. Consequently, no phenomenon exists independently, nor can it persist, since its conditions are inevitably changing.

The name that we give it does not refer to any real entity, but is rather a sort of focused torchbeam selecting for our attention a little patch on the shifting cloudscape of experience. Varela and Depraz are refusing to see brain and experience as isolated entities: ‘there is no gap to bridge, only traces to follow’ (p. 226). By allowing that human experience possesses a genuine causal agency, they are taking the subjective pole of reality seriously, something that is essential if we are to understand more fully the ways in which body and mind interact. Continuing research need not exclude consideration of those mental states which are comparatively less closely jointed to a brain.

Buddhism at present diverges from science in incorporating in its worldview various apparently outof- body experiences, including the possibility of consciousness unlinking from a dying body and relinking with a growing embryo – i.e. rebirth. It is disappointing that this volume is almost completely silent on rebirth, despite the formidable investigations of Ian Stevenson.[4] Matthieu Ricard is a French-born Tibetan Buddhist monk with a background in science, whose published conversations with his philosopher father became a bestseller.[5]

His article is on ‘Contemplative Science’, a vogue designation for Buddhism that is perhaps trying to appropriate some of the prestige of science. However, the term does highlight the fact that meditation and other mental disciplines should be seen as valid methods for investigating the mind, complementing the objective techniques of brain scans and psychiatrists' questionnaires.

Many centuries ago, the dialecticians of the Mā dhyamaka school of Buddhism (starting with Nagā rjuna) tackled Indian philosophical positions that in some ways resemble the standpoints of modern scientists. But it seems to me that Ricard shares with some of the other contributors to this book, notably Wallace, an unreflective overconfidence in the potency of these arguments against views that after all arise from a very different, and often very subtle, philosophical background.

Western thought already provides well-developed approaches to understanding reality, which have spotted the weaknesses of dualistic, mechanistic, essentialist and idealist views; in this volume we have excellent presentations on Kant (Bitbol), and on phenomenology (Varela and Depraz). One might add Spinoza, who so inspired Einstein, and is the subject of a recent book by neuroscientist Antonio Damasio,[6] as well as William James, Karl Popper and others. Much hard work will be involved in integrating these thinkers with Buddhism (as the astrophysicist Piet Hut points out in the concluding paper in this volume), but it will be very productive, and surely they cannot be ignored.

Eventually, though, we will need a new Tsongkhapa: a fine scholar with a brilliant mind, highly realised through meditation practice. Meanwhile, the more unreflective western Mā dhyamikans, as well as putting old arguments into new bottles, also tend to conflate Buddhism as a whole with Mā dhyamaka thought, presenting rival Buddhist doctrines as if they had been been conclusively refuted by Nagā rjuna and his successors in the Tibetan Gelug school.

There are scholars writing on science under the influence of other branches of Buddhism, and it is a great shame that the editor did not bring in their perspectives. For example, several writers on Buddhism and Ecology (a topic unfortunately absent from this book) have practised in Theravā da and Zen, including Joanna Macy, Kenneth Kraft, Leslie Sponsel, Bhikkhu Bodhi, and others. (There is also a bit of a national bias, more than half of the contributors being Americans.) The modern physics section of Buddhism and Science explores the surprising departures from downto- earth realism that have been emerging mainly in quantum mechanics during the past century.

Fitjof Capra popularised some of the parallels with Buddhism, in a general and rather unconvincing way, in his very influential The Tao of Physics, published nearly 30 years ago. Despite my protestations above, I must admit that a rigorous application of Mā dhyamaka epistemology to physics, as we see in several of the contributions here, promises to be far more genuinely illuminating than the vague (often verbal) parallels of Capra. But the most impressive paper is by the French philosopher of science Michel Bitbol. (He characterises Capra and others as offering: ‘mere analogy at an ill-defined level of the two discourses, with obvious apologetic purposes’ (p. 327).)

His 'Cure for Metaphysical Illusions' is an extremely thorough, and difficult, elucidation of neo-Kantian philosophy of science, explaining how Mā dhyamaka approaches can build on it, and extend it radically. Like Nagā rjuna, Kant was aware of the limitations of concepts. They are only for the formal ordering of the empirical contents, a process that will never end, though reason provides an inaccessible goal of complete rational understanding to regulate the process. Unaware of this as we generally are, it is easy to take the form that our intellect gives to phenomena as being the form of the things in themselves, ‘projecting the a priori structure of the knowing subject onto the world, thus mistaking it for a pregiven worldly structure’ (p. 328).

This is the all-pervasive ‘transcendental illusion’, which is very hard to recognise, let alone to compensate for. Bitbol calls on the neo-Kantian philosophers of science to help us with recognising it, but needs to bring in Buddhism to show us how to overcome the illusion. ‘Nagā rjuna's exclusive mission was to free everyone from the spell of reified conventional truth’ (p. 332). (Bitbol helpfully points out in a note that saṃvṛti-satya, usually translated 'conventional truth', is more literally a surface truth covering over ultimate truth.)

Thus, ‘to be in nirvā na means seeing the very same things that appear to the deluded consciousness of sa.msā ra, but seeing them as they are – as merely empty, dependent, impermanent, and non-substantial' (p.333). Efforts towards a compromise between science and religion in the 19th century West failed, leading to a schizophrenic attitude in which a system of beliefs and values were seen as indispensable, but the available system (monotheism) was incoherent in the light of science. Bitbol wishes to initiate the construction of a single higher-order tool, combining science, philosophy, and the ‘nondogmatic soteriologyoffered by the Mā dhyamaka.

The new tool needs to rely on the ‘dynamic potentialities’ of doctrines, not their canonical texts, seeing them as operational rather than dogmatic. Scientific theories are not representations of the world, but are for structuring our actions and anticipating their outcomes, with philosophy helping adjust us between all the possibilities of action within a value system; then Buddhism opens life out in self-transformation.

Science does not reveal a pre-existent underlying absolute reality (realism), yet it is more than a set of useful techniques (instrumentalism), being ‘the stabilised byproduct of the dynamic reciprocal relation between reality as a whole and a special fraction of it’ – the subject (p. 337). The structure of scientific theories is highly significant; they are not arbitrary, but it is possible nevertheless to remain metaphysically agnostic. In fact, Bitbol convincingly argues that this kind of philosophy of science is far more compatible with modern physics, especially quantum mechanics, than the belief in a mechanistic world and a dualistic epistemology. Scientists resist relationalist and nondual philosophies through fear of having no ground to stand on.

They can take heart, says Bitbol. Mā dhyamaka dialectically deconstructs substantialist and dualistic views, but it also introduces ‘a form of life in which losing ground is not a tragedy (it can even promote enlightenment...) and in which an alternative (say, pragmatic, integrated, and altruistic) strong motivation can be given to science’ (p. 339). There is not space here to detail Bitbol’s compelling philosophical framework for quantum mechanics, but I will mention his response to the problem of indeterminism – the unpredictability of quantum events. Is it that chance is ultimate, and any deterministic laws that we find come from the law of large numbers?

Or is it that determinism is ultimate, and apparent randomness comes from the complexity of huge numbers of interacting events, as studied in chaos theory? If we take a dependent co-arising-type approach, we will see that the causes of any event are not defined in the absolute, but are ‘relative to the very circumstances of the production of the phenomena’ (p. 349).

Since phenomena arise in dependence upon an enormously complex context, a context which includes the person or instrumentation detecting the phenomena, they are immune to any certain determination. Relations between things should be seen as being prior to the things that are relating; however, ‘neither connection, nor connected nor connector exist’, says Nagā rjuna. Buddhism’s radical analysis is needed to cap philosophy of science, since it comes from ‘direct stabilised experience of a disabused outlook’ – i.e., non-conceptual Insight into reality – while the insights of Western philosophy, impressive though they are, are the products of the free play of ideas. Buddhism and Science succeeds so well because all its contributors take both Buddhism and science seriously, seeing that both represent ways of understanding human experience, and both present opportunities for enhancing its quality.

Although Joseph Needham was able to write so dismissively of Buddhism only a few decades ago, we now know that he was mistaken. We know because scientists are engaging personally with the practice of Buddhism. They are finding in it a congenial spirituality which does not nag at their work so long as that work does no harm. They are also finding that it offers remarkable new vistas into the methods and models of science itself. But will Buddhism ever actually influence scientific practice – where to look in one's research, how to explain and interpret one’s findings?

This book will convince the reader that mind-science has already been changed by Buddhism, but the jury is still out on physics. Francisco Varela has no doubt. His assessment, thinking particularly of Buddhism impacting science, is that ‘the rediscovery of Asian philosophy, particularly of the Buddhist tradition, is a second Renaissance in the cultural history of the West, with the potential to be equally important as the rediscovery of Greek thought in the European Renaissance.’[7] The dialogue has only just begun; we live in exciting times.

Notes

[1]. Joseph Needham, The Shorter Science and Civilisation in China, Volume I (Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 264, 265, 272.
[2]. Robin Cooper, The Evolving Mind: Buddhism, Biology and Consciousness (Windhorse Publications, Birmingham, 1996).
[3]. For a good survey, see Damien Keown, Buddhism and Bioethics (Macmillan, London, 1995).
[4]. e.g. Ian Stevenson, Twenty Cases Suggestive of Reincarnation (University Press of Virginia, 1974).
[5]. Jean-Francois Revel and Matthieu Ricard, The Monk and the Philosopher (Thorsons, London, 1998).
[6]. Antonio Damasio, Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow and the Feeling Brain (Heinemann, 2003).
[7]. Varela, Thomson, and Rosch, The Embodied Mind (MIT press, 1993), p.22.


Source

www.westernbuddhistreview.com