Articles by alphabetic order
A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z
 Ā Ī Ñ Ś Ū Ö Ō
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0


Difference between revisions of "A Science of Consciousness: Buddhism"

From Tibetan Buddhist Encyclopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
m (1 revision: Robo 2.48 15 septmeber replacetext)
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
[[File:Shell.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Shell.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
“A [[Science]] of [[Consciousness]]: [[Buddhism]] (1), the Modern West (0)”
+
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
 
 +
“A [[Science]] of [[Consciousness]]: [[Buddhism]] (1), the {{Wiki|Modern}} [[West]] (0)”
  
 
B. {{Wiki|Alan Wallace}} Published in
 
B. {{Wiki|Alan Wallace}} Published in
Line 10: Line 18:
 
===Introduction===
 
===Introduction===
  
In his classic work [[Science]] and Civilization in [[China]] Joseph Needham explored the historical [[reasons]] why [[China]], for all its long civilization, never developed [[science]] as we understand it in the modern West, namely a quantitative, technologically driven [[science]] of the outer, [[physical]] [[world]]. In this paper I shall first outline some of the [[reasons]] why {{Wiki|Western civilization}} has never developed a [[science]] of [[Consciousness]]. I shall then argue that [[Buddhism]] has made major strides in developing such a [[science]], and that the contemplative refinement of [[attention]], and the subsequent utilization of such [[attention]] in exploring the [[mind]] firsthand plays a crucial role in such an endeavor. Such training of the [[mind]] is [[vital]] for investigating the nature of [[Consciousness]], and it is also an important prerequisite to [[transforming]] [[Consciousness]] in the pursuit of [[mental]] health and genuine well-being. While [[Buddhism]] has a rich contemplative [[tradition]] for the first-[[person]] exploration of states of [[Consciousness]], it never developed the sciences of the {{Wiki|brain}} and {{Wiki|behavior}} that we have in the modern West. So the integration of the first-[[person]] methodologies of [[Buddhism]] with the third-[[person]] methodologies of the [[cognitive]] sciences may lead to a richer understanding of [[Consciousness]] than either [[Buddhist]] or {{Wiki|Western civilization}} has discovered on its own.  
+
In his classic work [[Science]] and {{Wiki|Civilization}} in [[China]] [[Joseph Needham]] explored the historical [[reasons]] why [[China]], for all its long {{Wiki|civilization}}, never developed [[science]] as we understand it in the {{Wiki|modern}} [[West]], namely a quantitative, technologically driven [[science]] of the outer, [[physical]] [[world]]. In this paper I shall first outline some of the [[reasons]] why {{Wiki|Western civilization}} has never developed a [[science]] of [[Consciousness]]. I shall then argue that [[Buddhism]] has made major strides in developing such a [[science]], and that the {{Wiki|contemplative}} refinement of [[attention]], and the subsequent utilization of such [[attention]] in exploring the [[mind]] firsthand plays a crucial role in such an endeavor. Such {{Wiki|training}} of the [[mind]] is [[vital]] for investigating the [[nature]] of [[Consciousness]], and it is also an important prerequisite to [[transforming]] [[Consciousness]] in the pursuit of [[mental]] [[health]] and genuine well-being. While [[Buddhism]] has a rich {{Wiki|contemplative}} [[tradition]] for the first-[[person]] exploration of states of [[Consciousness]], it never developed the [[sciences]] of the {{Wiki|brain}} and {{Wiki|behavior}} that we have in the {{Wiki|modern}} [[West]]. So the {{Wiki|integration}} of the first-[[person]] methodologies of [[Buddhism]] with the third-[[person]] methodologies of the [[cognitive]] [[sciences]] may lead to a richer [[understanding]] of [[Consciousness]] than either [[Buddhist]] or {{Wiki|Western civilization}} has discovered on its [[own]].  
  
===Historical Impediments to the [[Emergence]] of a [[Science]] of [[Consciousness]] in the West===
+
===Historical Impediments to the [[Emergence]] of a [[Science]] of [[Consciousness]] in the [[West]]===
 
[[File:SerindianGroup.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:SerindianGroup.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
When asking why the West has yet to develop a [[science]] of [[Consciousness]], I turn first to the twin [[roots]] of {{Wiki|Western civilization}}: the {{Wiki|Greco-Roman}} and the {{Wiki|Judeo-Christian}} [[traditions]]. In general, a pivotal [[element]] in the [[emergence]] of a new [[science]] is the development and refinement of instruments to precisely observe and possibly experiment with the [[phenomena]] under investigation. Galileo’s use of the {{Wiki|telescope}} to examine the {{Wiki|sun}}, {{Wiki|moon}}, and {{Wiki|planets}} signaled the [[emergence]] of the [[science]] of {{Wiki|astronomy}}, much as Van Leeuwenhoek’s use of the microscope in observing minute [[life]] forms was instrumental to the [[emergence]] of modern {{Wiki|biology}}. It is therefore reasonable to assume that if there is to be, or ever has been, a [[science]] of [[Consciousness]], it will be heralded by the development and refinement of an instrument with which states of [[Consciousness]] can be observed with rigor and precision. The only instrument [[humanity]] has ever had for directly observing the [[mind]] is the [[mind]] itself, so that must be the instrument to be refined. The untrained [[attention]] is habitually prone to alternating bouts of [[agitation]] and dullness, so if the [[mind]] is to be used as a reliable tool for exploring and experimenting with [[Consciousness]], these dysfunctional traits need to be replaced with attentional stability and vividness.
+
When asking why the [[West]] has yet to develop a [[science]] of [[Consciousness]], I turn first to the twin [[roots]] of {{Wiki|Western civilization}}: the {{Wiki|Greco-Roman}} and the {{Wiki|Judeo-Christian}} [[traditions]]. In general, a pivotal [[element]] in the [[emergence]] of a new [[science]] is the [[development]] and refinement of instruments to precisely observe and possibly experiment with the [[phenomena]] under [[investigation]]. Galileo’s use of the {{Wiki|telescope}} to examine the {{Wiki|sun}}, {{Wiki|moon}}, and {{Wiki|planets}} signaled the [[emergence]] of the [[science]] of {{Wiki|astronomy}}, much as Van Leeuwenhoek’s use of the microscope in observing minute [[life]] [[forms]] was instrumental to the [[emergence]] of {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|biology}}. It is therefore reasonable to assume that if there is to be, or ever has been, a [[science]] of [[Consciousness]], it will be heralded by the [[development]] and refinement of an instrument with which states of [[Consciousness]] can be observed with rigor and precision. The only instrument [[humanity]] has ever had for directly observing the [[mind]] is the [[mind]] itself, so that must be the instrument to be refined. The untrained [[attention]] is habitually prone to alternating bouts of [[agitation]] and [[dullness]], so if the [[mind]] is to be used as a reliable tool for exploring and experimenting with [[Consciousness]], these dysfunctional traits need to be replaced with attentional stability and vividness.
  
While the [[philosophers]] of {{Wiki|ancient Greece}} were certainly interested in the nature of the [[mind]], there is little evidence that they developed any sophisticated means for refining the [[attention]]. The Pythagorean brotherhood and the {{Wiki|mystery}} schools may have devised such methods, but if they did, such [[knowledge]] has not been preserved. Jewish mystics also wrote extensively on the nature of [[Consciousness]],1 but the development of techniques to cultivate attentional stability and vividness for the rigorous exploration of [[Consciousness]] was not a strong suit of this [[tradition]] either. The {{Wiki|Greeks}} did coin the term eudaimonia, commonly translated as genuine [[happiness]], or [[human]] flourishing, referring to “the perfect [[life]]” in so far as [[perfection]] is attainable by [[humanity]]. For {{Wiki|Plotinus}}, the source of genuine [[happiness]] lies within the [[human]] [[spirit]], but when the {{Wiki|concept}} of eudaimonia was absorbed into the {{Wiki|Christian}} [[tradition]], Augustine insisted that the [[soul]] must look outside itself—to God—for such [[perfection]].2
+
While the [[philosophers]] of {{Wiki|ancient Greece}} were certainly [[interested]] in the [[nature]] of the [[mind]], there is little {{Wiki|evidence}} that they developed any sophisticated means for refining the [[attention]]. The Pythagorean brotherhood and the {{Wiki|mystery}} schools may have devised such [[methods]], but if they did, such [[knowledge]] has not been preserved. [[Wikipedia:Judaism|Jewish]] [[mystics]] also wrote extensively on the [[nature]] of [[Consciousness]],1 but the [[development]] of [[techniques]] to cultivate attentional stability and vividness for the rigorous exploration of [[Consciousness]] was not a strong suit of this [[tradition]] either. The {{Wiki|Greeks}} did coin the term eudaimonia, commonly translated as genuine [[happiness]], or [[human]] flourishing, referring to “the {{Wiki|perfect}} [[life]]” in so far as [[perfection]] is attainable by [[humanity]]. For {{Wiki|Plotinus}}, the source of genuine [[happiness]] lies within the [[human]] [[spirit]], but when the {{Wiki|concept}} of eudaimonia was absorbed into the {{Wiki|Christian}} [[tradition]], Augustine insisted that the [[soul]] must look outside itself—to God—for such [[perfection]].2
  
However, it must be added that a principal way he taught to go about this endeavor was through a contemplative process that draws the [[attention]] inwards, going beyond the [[self]] to a direct encounter with [[God]], the very source of eudaimonia.3 In this regard, perhaps the fundamental [[difference]] between {{Wiki|Plotinus}} and Augustine has to do with their [[views]] on the parameters of [[human]] identity, the boundary between the [[human]] [[soul]] and the [[divine]].
+
However, it must be added that a [[principal]] way he [[taught]] to go about this endeavor was through a {{Wiki|contemplative}} process that draws the [[attention]] inwards, going beyond the [[self]] to a direct encounter with [[God]], the very source of eudaimonia.3 In this regard, perhaps the fundamental [[difference]] between {{Wiki|Plotinus}} and Augustine has to do with their [[views]] on the parameters of [[human]] [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]], the boundary between the [[human]] [[soul]] and the [[divine]].
  
Within the {{Wiki|Christian}} [[tradition]], the early desert fathers were certainly aware of the need to [[calm]] the [[mind]], as is evidenced in the seminal fifth-century volume on contemplative practice entitled The Conferences of Cassian.4 But it is not clear that {{Wiki|Christian}} contemplatives of that period or the later medieval {{Wiki|era}} devised effective means for training the [[attention]] as a means for observing [[mental]] events. This failure may be at least in part responsible for the widespread conclusion among {{Wiki|Christian}} mystics that the highest states of {{Wiki|contemplation}} are necessarily fleeting, commonly lasting no longer than about half an hour.5 This insistence on the fleeting nature of [[mystical]] union appears to originate with Augustine,6 and it is reflected almost a millennium later in the writings of Meister Eckhart, who emphasized that the state of contemplative [[rapture]] is invariably transient, with even its residual effects lasting no longer than three days.7
+
Within the {{Wiki|Christian}} [[tradition]], the early desert fathers were certainly {{Wiki|aware}} of the need to [[calm]] the [[mind]], as is evidenced in the seminal fifth-century volume on {{Wiki|contemplative}} practice entitled The Conferences of Cassian.4 But it is not clear that {{Wiki|Christian}} contemplatives of that period or the later {{Wiki|medieval}} {{Wiki|era}} devised effective means for {{Wiki|training}} the [[attention]] as a means for observing [[mental]] events. This failure may be at least in part responsible for the widespread conclusion among {{Wiki|Christian}} [[mystics]] that the [[highest]] states of {{Wiki|contemplation}} are necessarily fleeting, commonly lasting no longer than about half an hour.5 This insistence on the fleeting [[nature]] of [[mystical]] union appears to originate with Augustine,6 and it is reflected almost a millennium later in the writings of {{Wiki|Meister Eckhart}}, who emphasized that the [[state]] of {{Wiki|contemplative}} [[rapture]] is invariably transient, with even its residual effects lasting no longer than three days.7
 
[[File:Scmandala.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Scmandala.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
With the advent of the Protestant Reformation and the [[Scientific]] Revolution, the gradual decline of {{Wiki|Christian}} contemplative inquiry into the nature of [[Consciousness]] rapidly accelerated. Given the Protestant emphasis on the Augustinian theme of the [[essential]] iniquity of the [[human]] [[soul]], and man’s utter inability to achieve salvation or [[know]] [[God]] except by [[faith]], there was no longer any {{Wiki|theological}} incentive for such inquiry. Salvation was emphatically presented as an undeserved gift from the [[Creator]]. So genuine [[happiness]], which is to be truly [[experienced]] only in the hereafter, is in no way earned by understanding the [[mind]] or achieving [[exceptional]] states of [[mental]] health and [[balance]].
+
With the advent of the {{Wiki|Protestant Reformation}} and the [[Scientific]] {{Wiki|Revolution}}, the [[gradual]] {{Wiki|decline}} of {{Wiki|Christian}} {{Wiki|contemplative}} inquiry into the [[nature]] of [[Consciousness]] rapidly accelerated. Given the {{Wiki|Protestant}} {{Wiki|emphasis}} on the Augustinian theme of the [[essential]] iniquity of the [[human]] [[soul]], and man’s utter inability to achieve {{Wiki|salvation}} or [[know]] [[God]] except by [[faith]], there was no longer any {{Wiki|theological}} incentive for such inquiry. {{Wiki|Salvation}} was emphatically presented as an undeserved [[gift]] from the [[Creator]]. So genuine [[happiness]], which is to be truly [[experienced]] only in the hereafter, is in no way earned by [[understanding]] the [[mind]] or achieving [[exceptional]] states of [[mental]] [[health]] and [[balance]].
  
{{Wiki|Descartes}}, whose ideological [[influence]] on the [[Scientific]] Revolution is hard to overestimate, was deeply committed to the introspective examination of the [[mind]]. But like his {{Wiki|Greek}} and {{Wiki|Christian}} predecessors, he did not devise means to refine the [[attention]] so that the [[mind]] could reliably be used to observe [[mental]] events. On the contrary, he naively believed that anything that was clearly and distinctly [[perceived]] by means of introspection was invariably valid—an assumption that was effectively refuted by {{Wiki|William James}} at the end of the nineteenth century.8 Moreover, in a {{Wiki|theological}} move that effectively removed the [[human]] [[mind]] from the natural [[world]], {{Wiki|Descartes}} decreed that the [[soul]] is divinely infused into the [[body]], where it exerts its [[influence]] on the [[body]] by way of the pineal gland. It was this gland, he believed, that, on decision of the [[soul]], induces the voluntary [[actions]] of the [[body]], while all other [[actions]] are reflexive. This [[philosophical]] stance probably accounts in large part for the fact that the Western [[scientific]] study of the [[mind]] did not even begin for more than two centuries after {{Wiki|Descartes}}. And until the last three decades of the twentieth century, the pineal gland was uniquely neglected by {{Wiki|physiological}} and biochemical investigators. Although various factors may be responsible for the [[scientific]] avoidance of this region of the {{Wiki|brain}}, it seems plausible that one [[reason]] was that, given the special status attributed to it by {{Wiki|Descartes}}, it was still considered to be outside the proper domain of natural [[science]].
+
{{Wiki|Descartes}}, whose {{Wiki|ideological}} [[influence]] on the [[Scientific]] {{Wiki|Revolution}} is hard to overestimate, was deeply committed to the introspective {{Wiki|examination}} of the [[mind]]. But like his {{Wiki|Greek}} and {{Wiki|Christian}} predecessors, he did not devise means to refine the [[attention]] so that the [[mind]] could reliably be used to observe [[mental]] events. On the contrary, he naively believed that anything that was clearly and distinctly [[perceived]] by means of {{Wiki|introspection}} was invariably valid—an assumption that was effectively refuted by {{Wiki|William James}} at the end of the nineteenth century.8 Moreover, in a {{Wiki|theological}} move that effectively removed the [[human]] [[mind]] from the natural [[world]], {{Wiki|Descartes}} decreed that the [[soul]] is divinely [[infused]] into the [[body]], where it exerts its [[influence]] on the [[body]] by way of the [[pineal gland]]. It was this gland, he believed, that, on [[decision]] of the [[soul]], induces the voluntary [[actions]] of the [[body]], while all other [[actions]] are reflexive. This [[philosophical]] stance probably accounts in large part for the fact that the [[Western]] [[scientific]] study of the [[mind]] did not even begin for more than two centuries after {{Wiki|Descartes}}. And until the last three decades of the twentieth century, the [[pineal gland]] was uniquely neglected by {{Wiki|physiological}} and biochemical investigators. Although various factors may be responsible for the [[scientific]] avoidance of this region of the {{Wiki|brain}}, it seems plausible that one [[reason]] was that, given the special {{Wiki|status}} attributed to it by {{Wiki|Descartes}}, it was still considered to be outside the proper domain of natural [[science]].
  
Another trend in {{Wiki|Europe}} at the dawn of the modern {{Wiki|era}} provided yet a further incentive for not delving deeply into the [[human]] [[mind]], and that was the witch-[[hunting]] craze from the late fifteenth century through the mid-seventeenth century. During this period, anyone who exhibited [[exceptional]] [[mental]] [[powers]], including the [[Power]] of [[spiritual]] [[healing]], was immediately suspect of [[being]] a witch. While nearly all [[traditional]] {{Wiki|societies}} have believed in witchcraft, the {{Wiki|Christian}} [[tradition]] in particular attributed the [[powers]] of witches to the [[Devil]], which is the rationale for the biblical commandment that such [[people]] are to be put to [[death]].9 The common [[belief]] that [[demons]] and other [[spiritual]] entities roved about in the natural [[world]] (sometimes taking possession of [[human]] [[souls]]) was of course deeply incompatible with the [[emerging]] mechanical [[view]] of the [[universe]]. After all, [[scientists]] couldn’t very well establish orderly [[physical]] laws in the [[objective]] [[world]] as long as there were immaterial [[spirits]] roving about, intervening at will in the affairs of man and nature. So many natural [[philosophers]] of the late sixteenth century simply dismissed them as [[illusions]]. Newton, on the other hand, who devoted much of his [[time]] to developing his own {{Wiki|theology}}, withdrew [[evil]] [[spirits]] from the [[objective]] [[physical]] [[world]] and placed them inside the [[human]] [[mind]] in the [[form]] of [[mental]] disorders. God’s outer creation had now been cleansed of these contaminating influences, leaving only the inner [[being]] of man defiled. It would take another two hundred years before Western psychoanalysts would have the nerve to begin the [[scientific]] exploration of these dark inner [[realities]].
+
Another trend in {{Wiki|Europe}} at the dawn of the {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|era}} provided yet a further incentive for not delving deeply into the [[human]] [[mind]], and that was the witch-[[hunting]] craze from the late fifteenth century through the mid-seventeenth century. During this period, anyone who exhibited [[exceptional]] [[mental]] [[powers]], [[including]] the [[Power]] of [[spiritual]] [[healing]], was immediately suspect of [[being]] a witch. While nearly all [[traditional]] {{Wiki|societies}} have believed in {{Wiki|witchcraft}}, the {{Wiki|Christian}} [[tradition]] in particular attributed the [[powers]] of {{Wiki|witches}} to the [[Devil]], which is the rationale for the {{Wiki|biblical}} commandment that such [[people]] are to be put to [[death]].9 The common [[belief]] that [[demons]] and other [[spiritual]] entities roved about in the natural [[world]] (sometimes taking possession of [[human]] [[souls]]) was of course deeply incompatible with the [[emerging]] mechanical [[view]] of the [[universe]]. After all, [[scientists]] couldn’t very well establish orderly [[physical]] laws in the [[objective]] [[world]] as long as there were {{Wiki|immaterial}} [[spirits]] roving about, intervening at will in the affairs of man and [[nature]]. So many natural [[philosophers]] of the late sixteenth century simply dismissed them as [[illusions]]. [[Newton]], on the other hand, who devoted much of his [[time]] to developing his [[own]] {{Wiki|theology}}, withdrew [[evil]] [[spirits]] from the [[objective]] [[physical]] [[world]] and placed them inside the [[human]] [[mind]] in the [[form]] of [[mental]] disorders. [[God’s]] outer creation had now been cleansed of these contaminating [[influences]], leaving only the inner [[being]] of man [[defiled]]. It would take another two hundred years before [[Western]] {{Wiki|psychoanalysts}} would have the {{Wiki|nerve}} to begin the [[scientific]] exploration of these dark inner [[realities]].
  
In short, the trajectory of Western [[science]] from the [[time]] of {{Wiki|Copernicus}} to the modern day seems to have been influenced by medieval {{Wiki|Christian}} [[cosmology]]. Just as [[hell]] was [[symbolized]] as [[being]] in the center of the [[earth]], and [[heaven]] was in the outermost reaches of [[space]], the inner, subjective [[world]] of man was depicted as [[being]] the locus of [[evil]], while the [[objective]] [[world]] was free of such [[moral]] contamination. It hardly seems an accident that the [[science]] that initiated the [[Scientific]] Revolution was {{Wiki|astronomy}}, and it took a full three hundred years for the [[scientific]] [[discipline]] of [[psychology]] to begin. And it was only in the closing years of the twentieth century that the [[scientific]] community began to regard [[Consciousness]] as a legitimate [[subject]] of [[scientific]] inquiry.
+
In short, the trajectory of [[Western]] [[science]] from the [[time]] of {{Wiki|Copernicus}} to the {{Wiki|modern}} day seems to have been influenced by {{Wiki|medieval}} {{Wiki|Christian}} [[cosmology]]. Just as [[hell]] was [[symbolized]] as [[being]] in the center of the [[earth]], and [[heaven]] was in the outermost reaches of [[space]], the inner, [[subjective]] [[world]] of man was depicted as [[being]] the locus of [[evil]], while the [[objective]] [[world]] was free of such [[moral]] contamination. It hardly seems an accident that the [[science]] that [[initiated]] the [[Scientific]] {{Wiki|Revolution}} was {{Wiki|astronomy}}, and it took a full three hundred years for the [[scientific]] [[discipline]] of [[psychology]] to begin. And it was only in the closing years of the twentieth century that the [[scientific]] {{Wiki|community}} began to regard [[Consciousness]] as a legitimate [[subject]] of [[scientific]] inquiry.
 
[[File:Schubring 001.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Schubring 001.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
Why did it take psychology—which itself emerged only after many [[scientists]] felt that they had already discovered all the principal laws of the universe—a century before it began to address the nature of [[Consciousness]]? This was due in large part to the fifty-year domination of {{Wiki|academic}} [[psychology]] by behaviorism. In 1913, the American behaviorist John B. Watson declared that {{Wiki|psychologists}} must avoid the use of all subjective terms such as [[sensation]], [[perception]], image, [[desire]], purpose, and even [[thinking]] and [[emotion]] as they are subjectively defined. And he attributed [[belief]] in the very [[existence]] of [[Consciousness]] to ancient superstitions and magic.10 Forty years later, B. F. Skinner echoed this theme by asserting that [[mind]] as such does not [[exist]] at all, only dispositions for {{Wiki|behavior}}. It took another decade before the futility of equating subjective [[mental]] processes with “[[objective]]” {{Wiki|behavioral}} dispositions became increasingly apparent to the [[scientific]] community. The behaviorist approach did [[nothing]] to explain the nature of the [[mind]], let alone [[Consciousness]]; it just reduced these subjective [[phenomena]] to a class of [[objective]] processes they could study with the available tools of [[science]].
+
Why did it take psychology—which itself emerged only after many [[scientists]] felt that they had already discovered all the [[principal]] laws of the universe—a century before it began to address the [[nature]] of [[Consciousness]]? This was due in large part to the fifty-year {{Wiki|domination}} of {{Wiki|academic}} [[psychology]] by {{Wiki|behaviorism}}. In 1913, the [[American]] behaviorist John B. Watson declared that {{Wiki|psychologists}} must avoid the use of all [[subjective]] terms such as [[sensation]], [[perception]], image, [[desire]], {{Wiki|purpose}}, and even [[thinking]] and [[emotion]] as they are subjectively defined. And he attributed [[belief]] in the very [[existence]] of [[Consciousness]] to [[ancient]] {{Wiki|superstitions}} and magic.10 Forty years later, B. F. Skinner echoed this theme by asserting that [[mind]] as such does not [[exist]] at all, only dispositions for {{Wiki|behavior}}. It took another decade before the futility of equating [[subjective]] [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}} with “[[objective]]” {{Wiki|behavioral}} dispositions became increasingly apparent to the [[scientific]] {{Wiki|community}}. The behaviorist approach did [[nothing]] to explain the [[nature]] of the [[mind]], let alone [[Consciousness]]; it just reduced these [[subjective]] [[phenomena]] to a class of [[objective]] {{Wiki|processes}} they could study with the available tools of [[science]].
  
With the [[emergence]] of [[cognitive]] [[psychology]] during the 1960s, subjective [[experience]] was once again allowed back into the [[realm]] of [[scientific]] research, but the role of introspection in exploring the [[mind]] was still marginalized in this field, just as it is in the rapidly progressing [[discipline]] of {{Wiki|neuroscience}}. Rather than equating [[mental]] processes with {{Wiki|behavioral}} dispositions, [[cognitive]] {{Wiki|psychologists}} and neuroscientists now equate them with neural events. As neurologist Antonio R. Damasio recently commented, “the {{Wiki|biological}} processes now presumed to correspond to [[mind]] processes in fact are [[mind]] processes and will be seen to be so when understood in sufficient detail…the private personal mind…indeed is {{Wiki|biological}} and will one day be described in terms both {{Wiki|biological}} and [[mental]].”11 However, what neuroscientists actually [[know]] is that specific neural events (N) are correlated to specific [[mental]] events (M), such that if N occurs, M occurs; if M occurs, N occurs; if N doesn’t occur, M doesn’t occur; and if M doesn’t occur, N doesn’t occur. Such a correlation could imply that the occurrence of N has a [[causal]] role in the production of M, or vice versa; or it could imply that N and M are actually the same [[phenomenon]] viewed from different perspectives. There is not enough [[scientific]] [[knowledge]] at this point to determine which of these types of correlation is the correct one. But Damasio seems to overlook this {{Wiki|ambiguity}} and simply decrees the equivalence of [[mental]] and neural processes, without any [[logical]] or [[empirical]] justification. In other words, this equivalence is simply a [[metaphysical]] [[belief]].
+
With the [[emergence]] of [[cognitive]] [[psychology]] during the 1960s, [[subjective]] [[experience]] was once again allowed back into the [[realm]] of [[scientific]] research, but the role of {{Wiki|introspection}} in exploring the [[mind]] was still marginalized in this field, just as it is in the rapidly progressing [[discipline]] of {{Wiki|neuroscience}}. Rather than equating [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}} with {{Wiki|behavioral}} dispositions, [[cognitive]] {{Wiki|psychologists}} and [[neuroscientists]] now equate them with neural events. As neurologist Antonio R. Damasio recently commented, “the {{Wiki|biological}} {{Wiki|processes}} now presumed to correspond to [[mind]] {{Wiki|processes}} in fact are [[mind]] {{Wiki|processes}} and will be seen to be so when understood in sufficient detail…the private personal mind…indeed is {{Wiki|biological}} and will one day be described in terms both {{Wiki|biological}} and [[mental]].”11 However, what [[neuroscientists]] actually [[know]] is that specific neural events (N) are correlated to specific [[mental]] events (M), such that if N occurs, M occurs; if M occurs, N occurs; if N doesn’t occur, M doesn’t occur; and if M doesn’t occur, N doesn’t occur. Such a correlation could imply that the occurrence of N has a [[causal]] role in the production of M, or [[vice versa]]; or it could imply that N and M are actually the same [[phenomenon]] viewed from different perspectives. There is not enough [[scientific]] [[knowledge]] at this point to determine which of these types of correlation is the correct one. But Damasio seems to overlook this {{Wiki|ambiguity}} and simply decrees the equivalence of [[mental]] and neural {{Wiki|processes}}, without any [[logical]] or [[empirical]] {{Wiki|justification}}. In other words, this equivalence is simply a [[metaphysical]] [[belief]].
  
While [[writing]] this essay, I questioned Damasio on this point, and he responded that in his [[book]] The [[Feeling]] of What Happens12 he goes to great [[pains]] to explain that neural patterns are not equivalent to [[mental]] images. There is an explanatory gap, he points out, regarding the process by which a neural pattern is converted to a [[mental]] image; and {{Wiki|neuroscience}}, in particular, and [[science]], in general, may never be able to bridge that gap. He further acknowledges that the “physicality” of [[mental phenomena]] has not yet been identified {{Wiki|scientifically}}; it is simply a working {{Wiki|hypothesis}}. As hard as I try, I just can't see the [[logic]] in his position. To say that A is B, implies an identity, not a [[causal]] relation between two distinct entities A and B. He seems to be saying that [[mental phenomena]] are {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]] produced by prior {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]]. But that still implies that [[mental phenomena]] are equivalent to some kind of {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]]. So the distinction between [[mental]] and neural processes fades out immediately.
+
While [[writing]] this essay, I questioned Damasio on this point, and he responded that in his [[book]] The [[Feeling]] of What Happens12 he goes to great [[pains]] to explain that neural patterns are not {{Wiki|equivalent}} to [[mental]] images. There is an explanatory gap, he points out, regarding the process by which a neural pattern is converted to a [[mental]] image; and {{Wiki|neuroscience}}, in particular, and [[science]], in general, may never be able to bridge that gap. He further acknowledges that the “physicality” of [[mental phenomena]] has not yet been identified {{Wiki|scientifically}}; it is simply a working {{Wiki|hypothesis}}. As hard as I try, I just can't see the [[logic]] in his position. To say that A is B, implies an [[Wikipedia:Identity (social science)|identity]], not a [[causal]] [[relation]] between two {{Wiki|distinct}} entities A and B. He seems to be saying that [[mental phenomena]] are {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]] produced by prior {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]]. But that still implies that [[mental phenomena]] are {{Wiki|equivalent}} to some kind of {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]]. So the {{Wiki|distinction}} between [[mental]] and neural {{Wiki|processes}} fades out immediately.
  
In the [[book]] cited above, Damasio explains why {{Wiki|neuroscience}} has been wrong about not making clear the distinctions between first-[[person]] and third- [[person]] [[views]] regarding discussions on [[mind]] and [[Consciousness]]. This is an important and valid point. At the same [[time]], he seems to advocate that in the final analysis, [[mental]] processes are their {{Wiki|neural correlates}} viewed from a first- [[person]] perspective; and neural processes are their [[mental]] correlates viewed from a third-[[person]] perspective. But this widespread [[belief]] is just that—an speculative hypothesis—and not a {{Wiki|scientifically}} demonstrated conclusion, despite the fact that it is commonly taken for granted by researchers in this field.
+
In the [[book]] cited above, Damasio explains why {{Wiki|neuroscience}} has been wrong about not making clear the {{Wiki|distinctions}} between first-[[person]] and third- [[person]] [[views]] regarding discussions on [[mind]] and [[Consciousness]]. This is an important and valid point. At the same [[time]], he seems to advocate that in the final analysis, [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}} are their {{Wiki|neural correlates}} viewed from a first- [[person]] {{Wiki|perspective}}; and neural {{Wiki|processes}} are their [[mental]] correlates viewed from a third-[[person]] {{Wiki|perspective}}. But this widespread [[belief]] is just that—an speculative hypothesis—and not a {{Wiki|scientifically}} demonstrated conclusion, despite the fact that it is commonly taken for granted by researchers in this field.
  
 
[[File:Sailand.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Sailand.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
  
How does Damasio explain the fact that the neural processes that he equates with [[mental]] processes have the capacity to be about other things? This question, called the hard problem, is regarded by many [[philosophers]] as a formidable, unsolved {{Wiki|mystery}}. But Damasio assures his readers that this turns out to be no {{Wiki|mystery}} at all: “evolution has crafted a {{Wiki|brain}} that is in the business of directly representing the organism and indirectly representing whatever the organism interacts with.” {{Wiki|Brain}} cells, he declares, “designed to be about other things and other doings.”13 In short, his solution to this problem is that the {{Wiki|brain}} has the capacity to represent other things because it was designed that way “by evolution.” This “explanation” obviously illuminates [[nothing]] other than the fact that Damasio has great [[faith]] in the mysterious ways of evolution, which for the biologist here takes on the role {{Wiki|theologians}} have long ascribed to [[God]].
+
How does Damasio explain the fact that the neural {{Wiki|processes}} that he equates with [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}} have the capacity to be about other things? This question, called the hard problem, is regarded by many [[philosophers]] as a formidable, unsolved {{Wiki|mystery}}. But Damasio assures his readers that this turns out to be no {{Wiki|mystery}} at all: “[[evolution]] has crafted a {{Wiki|brain}} that is in the business of directly representing the {{Wiki|organism}} and indirectly representing whatever the {{Wiki|organism}} interacts with.” {{Wiki|Brain}} {{Wiki|cells}}, he declares, “designed to be about other things and other doings.”13 In short, his {{Wiki|solution}} to this problem is that the {{Wiki|brain}} has the capacity to represent other things because it was designed that way “by [[evolution]].” This “explanation” obviously illuminates [[nothing]] other than the fact that Damasio has great [[faith]] in the mysterious ways of [[evolution]], which for the [[biologist]] here takes on the role {{Wiki|theologians}} have long ascribed to [[God]].
  
[[Mental]] events viewed introspectively appear to be radically different types of processes than neural events viewed objectively. Moreover, if one confines oneself to the introspective examination of the [[mind]], one evidently learns little if anything about the {{Wiki|brain}}. And if {{Wiki|brain}} [[scientists]] were to confine their research to the {{Wiki|brain}} alone, without reference to any first-[[person]] reports of [[mental]] [[experience]], they would learn little if anything about the [[mind]]. Indeed, they would have no [[reason]], on the basis of neural events alone, to conclude that they are correlated to any [[mental]] events at all. Damasio accounts for this disparity as follows: “The appearance of a gulf between [[mental states]] and [[physical]]/{{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]] comes from the large disparity between two [[bodies]] of knowledge—the good understanding of [[mind]] we have achieved through centuries of introspection and the efforts of [[cognitive]] [[science]] versus the incomplete neural specification we have achieved through the efforts of {{Wiki|neuroscience}}.”14
+
[[Mental]] events viewed introspectively appear to be radically different types of {{Wiki|processes}} than neural events viewed objectively. Moreover, if one confines oneself to the introspective {{Wiki|examination}} of the [[mind]], one evidently learns little if anything about the {{Wiki|brain}}. And if {{Wiki|brain}} [[scientists]] were to confine their research to the {{Wiki|brain}} alone, without reference to any first-[[person]] reports of [[mental]] [[experience]], they would learn little if anything about the [[mind]]. Indeed, they would have no [[reason]], on the basis of neural events alone, to conclude that they are correlated to any [[mental]] events at all. Damasio accounts for this disparity as follows: “The [[appearance]] of a gulf between [[mental states]] and [[physical]]/{{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]] comes from the large disparity between two [[bodies]] of knowledge—the good [[understanding]] of [[mind]] we have achieved through centuries of {{Wiki|introspection}} and the efforts of [[cognitive]] [[science]] versus the incomplete neural specification we have achieved through the efforts of {{Wiki|neuroscience}}.”14
  
Many contemporary [[scientists]] and [[philosophers]] would challenge his assertion that we now have “a good understanding” of the [[mind]] as a result of centuries of introspection and discoveries in [[cognitive]] [[science]]. Biologist {{Wiki|Edward O. Wilson}} maintains that [[logic]] launched from introspection is limited and usually unreliable, which is why even today [[people]] [[know]] more about their automobiles than they do about their own [[minds]].15 The general consensus among {{Wiki|psychologists}} is that introspection is an unreliable means for investigating the [[mind]]. As for our current understanding of the [[mind]] and [[Consciousness]], two of America’s most prominent [[philosophers]] of [[mind]] comment, “[[Consciousness]] stands alone today as a topic that often leaves even the most sophisticated thinkers tongue-tied and confused,”16 and “where the [[mind]] is concerned we are characteristically confused and in disagreement.”17 The real gist of Damasio’s assertion seems to be that we already have enough understanding of [[mental]] processes themselves, so now the emphasis should be placed on {{Wiki|neuroscience}} to explore the {{Wiki|biological}} processes that are, after all, the same as [[mental]] processes, just viewed from an [[objective]] perspective.
+
Many contemporary [[scientists]] and [[philosophers]] would challenge his [[assertion]] that we now have “a good [[understanding]]” of the [[mind]] as a result of centuries of {{Wiki|introspection}} and discoveries in [[cognitive]] [[science]]. Biologist {{Wiki|Edward O. Wilson}} maintains that [[logic]] launched from {{Wiki|introspection}} is limited and usually unreliable, which is why even today [[people]] [[know]] more about their automobiles than they do about their [[own]] [[minds]].15 The general consensus among {{Wiki|psychologists}} is that {{Wiki|introspection}} is an unreliable means for investigating the [[mind]]. As for our current [[understanding]] of the [[mind]] and [[Consciousness]], two of America’s most prominent [[philosophers]] of [[mind]] comment, “[[Consciousness]] stands alone today as a topic that often leaves even the most sophisticated thinkers tongue-tied and confused,”16 and “where the [[mind]] is concerned we are characteristically confused and in disagreement.”17 The real gist of Damasio’s [[assertion]] seems to be that we already have enough [[understanding]] of [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}} themselves, so now the {{Wiki|emphasis}} should be placed on {{Wiki|neuroscience}} to explore the {{Wiki|biological}} {{Wiki|processes}} that are, after all, the same as [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}}, just viewed from an [[objective]] {{Wiki|perspective}}.
  
If [[scientists]] were presented with a new instrument for observing a specific type of natural [[phenomena]], the first [[logical]] step for them to take before using this instrument would be to examine its nature and capacities. Does this instrument present the [[scientists]] merely its own artifacts, like looking through a kaleidoscope, or does it provide them with {{Wiki|data}} that [[exist]] independently of it? If it does yield such [[information]], does it distort it in the process of bringing it to them, or does it provide them with truly [[objective]] {{Wiki|data}} from a source independent of the instrument? Only after they have understood the design, functioning, reliability, and capacities of the instrument could they confidently use it to collect {{Wiki|data}}.
+
If [[scientists]] were presented with a new instrument for observing a specific type of natural [[phenomena]], the first [[logical]] step for them to take before using this instrument would be to examine its [[nature]] and capacities. Does this instrument {{Wiki|present}} the [[scientists]] merely its [[own]] {{Wiki|artifacts}}, like looking through a kaleidoscope, or does it provide them with {{Wiki|data}} that [[exist]] {{Wiki|independently}} of it? If it does yield such [[information]], does it distort it in the process of bringing it to them, or does it provide them with truly [[objective]] {{Wiki|data}} from a source {{Wiki|independent}} of the instrument? Only after they have understood the design, functioning, reliability, and capacities of the instrument could they confidently use it to collect {{Wiki|data}}.
  
The [[primary]] instrument that all [[scientists]] have used to make any type of observation is the [[human]] [[mind]]. Does this instrument provide us only with its own artifacts, without any access to any [[objective]] [[reality]] [[existing]] independently of the [[mind]]? Or if the [[mind]] provides us with [[information]] about the [[objective]] [[world]], does it distort it in the process? For [[reasons]] outlined above, the [[scientific]] study of the [[mind]] in the West was delayed for three centuries after the inception of the [[Scientific]] Revolution, which is tantamount to using an instrument for three hundred years before subjecting it to [[scientific]] scrutiny.
+
The [[primary]] instrument that all [[scientists]] have used to make any type of observation is the [[human]] [[mind]]. Does this instrument provide us only with its [[own]] {{Wiki|artifacts}}, without any access to any [[objective]] [[reality]] [[existing]] {{Wiki|independently}} of the [[mind]]? Or if the [[mind]] provides us with [[information]] about the [[objective]] [[world]], does it distort it in the process? For [[reasons]] outlined above, the [[scientific]] study of the [[mind]] in the [[West]] was delayed for three centuries after the inception of the [[Scientific]] {{Wiki|Revolution}}, which is tantamount to using an instrument for three hundred years before subjecting it to [[scientific]] {{Wiki|scrutiny}}.
 
[[File:Riversflow.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Riversflow.JPG|thumb|250px|]]
What kind of [[scientific]] worldview has emerged as a result of this profound oversight and the enormous disparity of our understanding of the [[mind]] and the rest of the natural [[world]]? Wilson expresses the [[view]] of many [[scientists]] with his assertion that outside our heads there is an independent, [[objective]] [[world]], and inside our heads is a reconstitution of [[reality]] based on sensory input and the [[self]]-assembly of concepts. The proper task of [[scientists]], he claims is to correctly align our inner representations of [[reality]] with the [[world]] outside our heads.18 The problem here, which he openly acknowledges, is that [[scientists]] have no [[body]] of external [[objective]] [[truth]] by which the alignment of [[scientific]] theories and the [[world]] outside our heads can be calibrated. In other words, the [[empirical]] {{Wiki|data}} that we perceive, together with our [[scientific]] theories that account for them, all consists of [[mental]] representations “within our heads”; and we have no [[objective]] yardstick with which to compare those representations with what we assume to be the “real [[world]].”
+
What kind of [[scientific]] worldview has emerged as a result of this profound oversight and the enormous disparity of our [[understanding]] of the [[mind]] and the rest of the natural [[world]]? Wilson expresses the [[view]] of many [[scientists]] with his [[assertion]] that outside our heads there is an {{Wiki|independent}}, [[objective]] [[world]], and inside our heads is a reconstitution of [[reality]] based on sensory input and the [[self]]-assembly of [[Wikipedia:concept|concepts]]. The proper task of [[scientists]], he claims is to correctly align our inner {{Wiki|representations}} of [[reality]] with the [[world]] outside our heads.18 The problem here, which he openly acknowledges, is that [[scientists]] have no [[body]] of external [[objective]] [[truth]] by which the alignment of [[scientific]] theories and the [[world]] outside our heads can be calibrated. In other words, the [[empirical]] {{Wiki|data}} that we {{Wiki|perceive}}, together with our [[scientific]] theories that account for them, all consists of [[mental]] {{Wiki|representations}} “within our heads”; and we have no [[objective]] yardstick with which to compare those {{Wiki|representations}} with what we assume to be the “real [[world]].”
  
How are we to get out of this conundrum? Wilson suggests, “Criteria of [[objective]] [[truth]] might be attainable through [[empirical]] investigation. The key lies in clarifying the still poorly understood operations composing the [[mind]] and in improving the piecemeal approach [[science]] has taken to its material properties.”19 Like Damasio, Wilson assumes that the [[mind]] is actually composed of {{Wiki|brain}} processes, but as I have already pointed out, at this point such an assertion is simply a [[metaphysical]] [[belief]], not a {{Wiki|scientifically}} established fact. Given how little [[scientists]] presently understand about the relation between the [[mind]] and {{Wiki|brain}}, it would be far more [[objective]] to regard this as a topic to be researched with an open [[mind]], rather than assuming (or demanding) that [[science]] will one day confirm our current materialistic biases. In [[order]] to understand the relation between [[scientific]] theories and the [[objective]] [[phenomena]] they ostensibly represent, we clearly need to have a more thorough, [[scientific]] understanding of the [[mind]]. As I commented earlier, the first step in developing a [[science]] of any kind of [[phenomena]] is to develop and refine instruments that allow one to observe and possibly experiment with the [[phenomena]] under investigation. The only instrument we have that enables us to observe [[mental phenomena]] directly is the [[mind]] itself. But since the [[time]] of {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, the West has made little if any progress in developing means of refining the [[mind]] so that it can be used as a reliable instrument for observing [[mental]] events. And judging by the writings of many [[scientists]], such as E. O. Wilson, there continues to be considerable resistance against developing any such [[empirical]] [[science]] even today.
+
How are we to get out of this {{Wiki|conundrum}}? Wilson suggests, “Criteria of [[objective]] [[truth]] might be attainable through [[empirical]] [[investigation]]. The key lies in clarifying the still poorly understood operations composing the [[mind]] and in improving the piecemeal approach [[science]] has taken to its material properties.”19 Like Damasio, Wilson assumes that the [[mind]] is actually composed of {{Wiki|brain}} {{Wiki|processes}}, but as I have already pointed out, at this point such an [[assertion]] is simply a [[metaphysical]] [[belief]], not a {{Wiki|scientifically}} established fact. Given how little [[scientists]] presently understand about the [[relation]] between the [[mind]] and {{Wiki|brain}}, it would be far more [[objective]] to regard this as a topic to be researched with an open [[mind]], rather than assuming (or demanding) that [[science]] will one day confirm our current {{Wiki|materialistic}} biases. In [[order]] to understand the [[relation]] between [[scientific]] theories and the [[objective]] [[phenomena]] they ostensibly represent, we clearly need to have a more thorough, [[scientific]] [[understanding]] of the [[mind]]. As I commented earlier, the first step in developing a [[science]] of any kind of [[phenomena]] is to develop and refine instruments that allow one to observe and possibly experiment with the [[phenomena]] under [[investigation]]. The only instrument we have that enables us to observe [[mental phenomena]] directly is the [[mind]] itself. But since the [[time]] of {{Wiki|Aristotle}}, the [[West]] has made little if any progress in developing means of refining the [[mind]] so that it can be used as a reliable instrument for observing [[mental]] events. And judging by the writings of many [[scientists]], such as E. O. Wilson, there continues to be considerable resistance against developing any such [[empirical]] [[science]] even today.
  
[[Thus]], if we follow this present materialistic trend, no such [[empirical]] [[science]] of [[Consciousness]] is likely to emerge in the foreseeable future. Rather, if the [[cognitive]] sciences continue to be constrained by the [[metaphysical]] dictates of [[scientific]] materialism,20 all we will do is reduce [[Consciousness]] to something that can be explored and understood within the parameters of that {{Wiki|dogma}}, as various researchers, such as Crick and Koch,21 are already attempting to do. Just as kinematics (the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} study of matter in motion) must precede mechanics in the study of {{Wiki|physics}}, the rigorous, firsthand investigation of [[Consciousness]] must precede any formulation of the mechanisms that account the [[emergence]] of [[Consciousness]]. Modern [[science]] has never developed a rigorous introspective methodology for observing the [[phenomena]] of [[conscious]] [[mental]] processes and states. {{Wiki|William James}}, the foremost pioneer of American [[psychology]], [[acknowledged]] the importance of studying {{Wiki|behavioral}} and {{Wiki|neural correlates}} to [[mental]] processes, but he emphasized the [[primary]] role of introspection in this endeavor.22 However, the untrained [[mind]], which is prone to alternating [[agitation]] and dullness, is an unreliable and inadequate instrument for observing anything.
+
[[Thus]], if we follow this {{Wiki|present}} {{Wiki|materialistic}} trend, no such [[empirical]] [[science]] of [[Consciousness]] is likely to emerge in the foreseeable {{Wiki|future}}. Rather, if the [[cognitive]] [[sciences]] continue to be constrained by the [[metaphysical]] dictates of [[scientific]] materialism,20 all we will do is reduce [[Consciousness]] to something that can be explored and understood within the parameters of that {{Wiki|dogma}}, as various researchers, such as Crick and Koch,21 are already attempting to do. Just as kinematics (the {{Wiki|phenomenological}} study of {{Wiki|matter}} in {{Wiki|motion}}) must precede mechanics in the study of {{Wiki|physics}}, the rigorous, firsthand [[investigation]] of [[Consciousness]] must precede any formulation of the mechanisms that account the [[emergence]] of [[Consciousness]]. {{Wiki|Modern}} [[science]] has never developed a rigorous introspective [[Wikipedia:scientific method|methodology]] for observing the [[phenomena]] of [[conscious]] [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}} and states. {{Wiki|William James}}, the foremost pioneer of [[American]] [[psychology]], [[acknowledged]] the importance of studying {{Wiki|behavioral}} and {{Wiki|neural correlates}} to [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}}, but he emphasized the [[primary]] role of {{Wiki|introspection}} in this endeavor.22 However, the untrained [[mind]], which is prone to alternating [[agitation]] and [[dullness]], is an unreliable and inadequate instrument for observing anything.
 
[[File:Relig.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Relig.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
To [[transform]] it into a suitable instrument for [[scientific]] exploration, the stability and vividness of the [[attention]] must be developed to a high degree. James was well aware of the importance of developing such sustained, voluntary [[attention]],23 but he [[acknowledged]] that he did not [[know]] how to achieve this task.24 To sum up, the modern West has developed a sophisticated [[science]] of {{Wiki|behavioral}} and {{Wiki|neural correlates}} of [[Consciousness]], but no [[science]] of [[Consciousness]] itself, for it has failed to develop sophisticated, rigorous means of exploring the [[phenomena]] of [[Consciousness]] firsthand. And this is the first step towards an [[empirical]] [[science]] of any class of natural [[phenomena]]. [[Thus]] with regard to exploring the nature, origins, and potentials of [[Consciousness]], [[cognitive]] [[scientists]] and neuroscientists are more like [[astrologers]] (who carefully examine correlates between the [[celestial]] and terrestrial [[phenomena]]) than astronomers (who carefully examine [[celestial]] [[phenomena]] themselves). A second result of the historical development of [[science]] is that the modern West has an elaborate [[science]] of [[mental]] illness, but no [[science]] of [[mental]] health. Indeed there is hardly any [[scientific]] consensus on the criteria by which to identify [[mental]] health. Nor do we in the West have any [[science]] that shows how to cultivate [[extraordinary]] [[mental]] health or genuine [[happiness]]. In short, the theme of eudaimonia, a state [[human]] flourishing sometimes glossed as a “[[truth]]- given [[joy]],” has been forgotten in modern [[science]],25 and the very [[existence]] of a [[truth]] that yields such well-being has no place in the [[scientific]] [[view]] of [[human]] [[existence]] or the [[universe]] at large.
+
To [[transform]] it into a suitable instrument for [[scientific]] exploration, the stability and vividness of the [[attention]] must be developed to a high [[degree]]. James was well {{Wiki|aware}} of the importance of developing such sustained, voluntary [[attention]],23 but he [[acknowledged]] that he did not [[know]] how to achieve this task.24 To sum up, the {{Wiki|modern}} [[West]] has developed a sophisticated [[science]] of {{Wiki|behavioral}} and {{Wiki|neural correlates}} of [[Consciousness]], but no [[science]] of [[Consciousness]] itself, for it has failed to develop sophisticated, rigorous means of exploring the [[phenomena]] of [[Consciousness]] firsthand. And this is the first step towards an [[empirical]] [[science]] of any class of natural [[phenomena]]. [[Thus]] with regard to exploring the [[nature]], origins, and potentials of [[Consciousness]], [[cognitive]] [[scientists]] and [[neuroscientists]] are more like [[astrologers]] (who carefully examine correlates between the [[celestial]] and terrestrial [[phenomena]]) than [[astronomers]] (who carefully examine [[celestial]] [[phenomena]] themselves). A second result of the historical [[development]] of [[science]] is that the {{Wiki|modern}} [[West]] has an elaborate [[science]] of [[mental]] {{Wiki|illness}}, but no [[science]] of [[mental]] [[health]]. Indeed there is hardly any [[scientific]] consensus on the criteria by which to identify [[mental]] [[health]]. Nor do we in the [[West]] have any [[science]] that shows how to cultivate [[extraordinary]] [[mental]] [[health]] or genuine [[happiness]]. In short, the theme of eudaimonia, a [[state]] [[human]] flourishing sometimes glossed as a “[[truth]]- given [[joy]],” has been forgotten in {{Wiki|modern}} [[science]],25 and the very [[existence]] of a [[truth]] that yields such well-being has no place in the [[scientific]] [[view]] of [[human]] [[existence]] or the [[universe]] at large.
  
In short, the West presently has no [[pure]] [[science]] of [[Consciousness]] that reveals the nature, origins, and potentials of this natural [[phenomenon]], and it similarly lacks an applied [[science]] of [[Consciousness]] that reveals means for refining and enhancing [[Consciousness]] and thereby achieving eudaimonia. But the fact that the West has failed to develop such a [[science]] does not necessarily imply that all other [[human]] civilizations throughout {{Wiki|history}} have been equally deficient in this regard.
+
In short, the [[West]] presently has no [[pure]] [[science]] of [[Consciousness]] that reveals the [[nature]], origins, and potentials of this natural [[phenomenon]], and it similarly lacks an applied [[science]] of [[Consciousness]] that reveals means for refining and enhancing [[Consciousness]] and thereby achieving eudaimonia. But the fact that the [[West]] has failed to develop such a [[science]] does not necessarily imply that all other [[human]] {{Wiki|civilizations}} throughout {{Wiki|history}} have been equally deficient in this regard.
  
 
===The [[Buddhist]] [[Science]] of [[Consciousness]]===
 
===The [[Buddhist]] [[Science]] of [[Consciousness]]===
  
Over the course of its 2500-year {{Wiki|history}}, [[Buddhism]] has developed rigorous methods for refining the [[attention]], and then applying that [[attention]] to exploring the origins, nature, and role of [[Consciousness]] in the natural [[world]]. The [[empirical]] and [[rational]] investigations and discoveries by such great [[Indian]] contemplatives as [[Gautama]] the [[Buddha]] profoundly challenge many of the assumptions of the modern West, particularly those of [[scientific]] {{Wiki|materialism}}. This meeting of [[Buddhist]] and modern Western [[science]] also challenges our very notion of “[[metaphysics]].” In the nineteenth century, the origins of the [[physical]] [[universe]], the constitution of distant galaxies, and the internal structure of {{Wiki|molecules}} were all [[metaphysical]] issues. At that [[time]], there were no known ways of exploring these topics [[empirically]], but that is no longer the case. In the twenty-first century, the nature, origins, and [[destiny]] of [[human]] [[Consciousness]] are still [[metaphysical]] issues for the West, but are they similarly clouded in {{Wiki|mystery}} within the [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]]?
+
Over the course of its 2500-year {{Wiki|history}}, [[Buddhism]] has developed rigorous [[methods]] for refining the [[attention]], and then applying that [[attention]] to exploring the origins, [[nature]], and role of [[Consciousness]] in the natural [[world]]. The [[empirical]] and [[rational]] investigations and discoveries by such great [[Indian]] contemplatives as [[Gautama]] the [[Buddha]] profoundly challenge many of the {{Wiki|assumptions}} of the {{Wiki|modern}} [[West]], particularly those of [[scientific]] {{Wiki|materialism}}. This meeting of [[Buddhist]] and {{Wiki|modern}} [[Western]] [[science]] also challenges our very notion of “[[metaphysics]].” In the nineteenth century, the origins of the [[physical]] [[universe]], the constitution of distant {{Wiki|galaxies}}, and the internal {{Wiki|structure}} of {{Wiki|molecules}} were all [[metaphysical]] issues. At that [[time]], there were no known ways of exploring these topics [[empirically]], but that is no longer the case. In the twenty-first century, the [[nature]], origins, and [[destiny]] of [[human]] [[Consciousness]] are still [[metaphysical]] issues for the [[West]], but are they similarly clouded in {{Wiki|mystery}} within the [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]]?
 
[[File:Refin.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Refin.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
As new [[empirical]] strategies are devised for exploring [[phenomena]], [[metaphysics]] gives way to [[science]], mere [[belief]] is supplanted by [[knowledge]]. The approach that has repeatedly allowed for this gradual [[illumination]] of the natural [[world]] is called the [[scientific method]]. Webster’s Ninth New Collegiate Dictionary defines this as follows: “Principles and procedures for the systematic pursuit of [[knowledge]] involving the [[recognition]] and formulation of a problem, the collection of {{Wiki|data}} through observation and experiment, and the formulation and testing of hypotheses.” Does [[Buddhism]] include this procedure in its inquiry into the nature of the [[mind]] and [[Consciousness]]? In general, the framework of [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}} and practice consists of the [[Four Noble Truths]]: the [[truths]] of [[Suffering]], the source of [[Suffering]], the [[cessation]] of [[Suffering]] together with its source, and the [[path]] leading to that [[cessation]]. While [[Buddhist]] contemplatives have always placed a [[primary]] emphasis on fathoming the nature of the [[mind]], their orientation to this endeavor has been fundamentally pragmatic. Their first task is to [[recognize]] the nature and full range of [[Suffering]] to which [[humans]] are vulnerable. [[The first noble truth]] formulates that as the problem to be addressed. [[The second noble truth]] presents the {{Wiki|hypothesis}} that the [[essential]] [[causes]] of [[Suffering]] are to be found within the [[mind]], specifically in terms of [[cognitive]], [[emotional]], and attentional imbalances. [[The third noble truth]] hypothesizes that these afflictive tendencies can be irreversibly dispelled from the [[mind]]. And the [[fourth noble truth]] presents detailed procedures for collecting {{Wiki|data}} by observing [[mental]] processes and experimenting with techniques for [[transforming]] the [[mind]] and eliminating its afflictive elements.26
+
As new [[empirical]] strategies are devised for exploring [[phenomena]], [[metaphysics]] gives way to [[science]], mere [[belief]] is supplanted by [[knowledge]]. The approach that has repeatedly allowed for this [[gradual]] [[illumination]] of the natural [[world]] is called the [[scientific method]]. Webster’s Ninth New Collegiate {{Wiki|Dictionary}} defines this as follows: “{{Wiki|Principles}} and procedures for the systematic pursuit of [[knowledge]] involving the [[recognition]] and formulation of a problem, the collection of {{Wiki|data}} through observation and experiment, and the formulation and testing of {{Wiki|hypotheses}}.” Does [[Buddhism]] include this procedure in its inquiry into the [[nature]] of the [[mind]] and [[Consciousness]]? In general, the framework of [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|theory}} and practice consists of the [[Four Noble Truths]]: the [[truths]] of [[Suffering]], the source of [[Suffering]], the [[cessation]] of [[Suffering]] together with its source, and the [[path]] leading to that [[cessation]]. While [[Buddhist]] contemplatives have always placed a [[primary]] {{Wiki|emphasis}} on fathoming the [[nature]] of the [[mind]], their orientation to this endeavor has been fundamentally {{Wiki|pragmatic}}. Their first task is to [[recognize]] the [[nature]] and full range of [[Suffering]] to which [[humans]] are vulnerable. [[The first noble truth]] formulates that as the problem to be addressed. [[The second noble truth]] presents the {{Wiki|hypothesis}} that the [[essential]] [[causes]] of [[Suffering]] are to be found within the [[mind]], specifically in terms of [[cognitive]], [[emotional]], and attentional imbalances. [[The third noble truth]] hypothesizes that these {{Wiki|afflictive}} {{Wiki|tendencies}} can be irreversibly dispelled from the [[mind]]. And the [[fourth noble truth]] presents detailed procedures for collecting {{Wiki|data}} by observing [[mental]] {{Wiki|processes}} and experimenting with [[techniques]] for [[transforming]] the [[mind]] and eliminating its {{Wiki|afflictive}} elements.26
  
The very notion of observing the [[mind]] with the [[mind]] appears problematic to many thinkers, for it does not allow for the separation of [[subject]] and [[object]] that characterizes other kinds of [[scientific]] observations. This is a legitimate [[concern]]. Is it even possible to observe [[mental states]] and processes with the [[mind]]? Even with no [[mental]] training, we can detect our [[emotional]] states, we can observe [[thoughts]] and images arising in the [[mind]], and we can introspectively [[recognize]] from moment to moment whether our [[minds]] are [[calm]] or agitated. On a more basic level, we can perceive that we are conscious—we are aware not only of [[objects]] of [[Consciousness]] but of the presence of our own [[Consciousness]] of other things.27 And this faculty of [[mental]] [[perception]] is the only instrument we have for directly observing any [[mental phenomena]]. While it is true in this case that there is no [[absolute]] separation between the instrument of observation and the observed [[phenomena]], this fact does not necessarily ban the whole procedure from the [[realm]] of [[scientific]] exploration. After all, the inextricable relation between the system of measurement and the measured [[phenomena]] is a familiar theme in {{Wiki|quantum mechanics}}, but no one has suggested that such measurements be banned from {{Wiki|physics}}.
+
The very notion of observing the [[mind]] with the [[mind]] appears problematic to many thinkers, for it does not allow for the separation of [[subject]] and [[object]] that characterizes other kinds of [[scientific]] observations. This is a legitimate [[concern]]. Is it even possible to observe [[mental states]] and {{Wiki|processes}} with the [[mind]]? Even with no [[mental]] {{Wiki|training}}, we can detect our [[emotional]] states, we can observe [[thoughts]] and images [[arising]] in the [[mind]], and we can introspectively [[recognize]] from [[moment]] to [[moment]] whether our [[minds]] are [[calm]] or agitated. On a more basic level, we can {{Wiki|perceive}} that we are conscious—we are {{Wiki|aware}} not only of [[objects]] of [[Consciousness]] but of the presence of our [[own]] [[Consciousness]] of other things.27 And this {{Wiki|faculty}} of [[mental]] [[perception]] is the only instrument we have for directly observing any [[mental phenomena]]. While it is true in this case that there is no [[absolute]] separation between the instrument of observation and the observed [[phenomena]], this fact does not necessarily ban the whole procedure from the [[realm]] of [[scientific]] exploration. After all, the inextricable [[relation]] between the system of measurement and the measured [[phenomena]] is a familiar theme in {{Wiki|quantum mechanics}}, but no one has suggested that such measurements be banned from {{Wiki|physics}}.
  
In [[Buddhist]] contemplative practice, the experiential investigation of the [[mind]], including the nature, origins, and potentials of [[Consciousness]], is of paramount significance. But in [[order]] for such exploration be penetrating and reliable and for the insights gleaned from this process to be thoroughly assimilated, the attentional imbalances of laxity and [[excitation]] must first be dispelled. Only when the [[attention]] is lucid and [[calm]] can it be used effectively in this venture.28 The qualities of [[luminosity]] and stillness are actually innate to the [[relative]] ground state of {{Wiki|individual}} [[mind]], so the central challenge of this training is to settle the [[attention]] in that ground state. One of the remarkable discoveries of [[Buddhist]] contemplatives who have penetrated to this ground is that this stratum of [[Consciousness]] is imbued with an innate quality of [[bliss]]. In other words, when the [[attention]] is settled in a deep state of {{Wiki|equilibrium}}, temporarily free of laxity and [[excitation]], one spontaneously [[experiences]] a [[sense]] of inner [[peace]] and well- [[being]]. In [[order]] to penetrate to this substrate [[Consciousness]], a necessary prerequisite is the cultivation of a [[wholesome]] way of [[life]] that supports [[mental]] [[balance]] and harmonious relations with others. This is the [[essence]] of [[Buddhist]] [[ethics]], which is the foundation of all [[Buddhist]] practice.29
+
In [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|contemplative}} practice, the experiential [[investigation]] of the [[mind]], [[including]] the [[nature]], origins, and potentials of [[Consciousness]], is of paramount significance. But in [[order]] for such exploration be penetrating and reliable and for the [[insights]] gleaned from this process to be thoroughly assimilated, the attentional imbalances of {{Wiki|laxity}} and [[excitation]] must first be dispelled. Only when the [[attention]] is lucid and [[calm]] can it be used effectively in this venture.28 The qualities of [[luminosity]] and stillness are actually innate to the [[relative]] ground [[state]] of {{Wiki|individual}} [[mind]], so the central challenge of this {{Wiki|training}} is to settle the [[attention]] in that ground [[state]]. One of the remarkable discoveries of [[Buddhist]] contemplatives who have penetrated to this ground is that this stratum of [[Consciousness]] is imbued with an innate [[quality]] of [[bliss]]. In other words, when the [[attention]] is settled in a deep [[state]] of {{Wiki|equilibrium}}, temporarily free of {{Wiki|laxity}} and [[excitation]], one spontaneously [[experiences]] a [[sense]] of inner [[peace]] and well- [[being]]. In [[order]] to penetrate to this substrate [[Consciousness]], a necessary prerequisite is the [[cultivation]] of a [[wholesome]] way of [[life]] that supports [[mental]] [[balance]] and harmonious relations with others. This is the [[essence]] of [[Buddhist]] [[ethics]], which is the foundation of all [[Buddhist]] practice.29
 
[[File:Rcxu.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Rcxu.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
According to generations of [[Buddhist]] contemplatives, simply settling the [[attention]] in the substrate [[Consciousness]], with a high degree of attentional stability and clarity, is not enough to irreversibly free the [[mind]] of [[afflictions]] and [[obscurations]]. For this one must penetrate to the [[ultimate]] ground state of [[Consciousness]], prior to the {{Wiki|conceptual}} demarcations of [[subject]] and [[object]], [[mind]] and matter, and even [[existence]] and nonexistence. This [[primordial]] [[Consciousness]] is metaphorically described as [[being]] [[empty]] and luminous, and its has never been sullied by afflictive imbalances of any kind. The [[realization]] of this state of [[Consciousness]] is said to yield a state of well-being, or eudaimonia, that transcends the [[imagination]], and it is the unified culmination of the [[Buddhist]] pragmatic pursuit of freedom from [[Suffering]] and the epistemic pursuit of [[knowledge]]. With such [[insight]], one comes to understand not only the nature of [[Consciousness]] but the relation between [[mental]] representations and their referents in the [[objective]] [[world]].
+
According to generations of [[Buddhist]] contemplatives, simply settling the [[attention]] in the substrate [[Consciousness]], with a high [[degree]] of attentional stability and clarity, is not enough to irreversibly free the [[mind]] of [[afflictions]] and [[obscurations]]. For this one must penetrate to the [[ultimate]] ground [[state]] of [[Consciousness]], prior to the {{Wiki|conceptual}} demarcations of [[subject]] and [[object]], [[mind]] and {{Wiki|matter}}, and even [[existence]] and [[Wikipedia:Existence|nonexistence]]. This [[primordial]] [[Consciousness]] is {{Wiki|metaphorically}} described as [[being]] [[empty]] and {{Wiki|luminous}}, and its has never been sullied by {{Wiki|afflictive}} imbalances of any kind. The [[realization]] of this [[state]] of [[Consciousness]] is said to yield a [[state]] of well-being, or eudaimonia, that {{Wiki|transcends}} the [[imagination]], and it is the unified culmination of the [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|pragmatic}} pursuit of freedom from [[Suffering]] and the {{Wiki|epistemic}} pursuit of [[knowledge]]. With such [[insight]], one comes to understand not only the [[nature]] of [[Consciousness]] but the [[relation]] between [[mental]] {{Wiki|representations}} and their referents in the [[objective]] [[world]].
  
With this understanding of three dimensions of Consciousness—ranging from the [[Wikipedia:Psyche (psychology)|psyche]] that can immediately be viewed introspectively, to the substrate [[Consciousness]], to [[primordial]] Consciousness—the [[Buddhist]] [[view]] of the [[mind]] challenges many common assumptions in the modern West. According to many {{Wiki|psychologists}} today, the normal [[mind]] is deemed to be healthy, but it is nevertheless [[subject]] to a wide range of [[mental]] distress, including {{Wiki|depression}}, [[anxiety]], and frustration. But these can be managed with drug therapy and counseling when they become excessive. While [[unhappiness]] comes simply from [[being]] [[human]], [[happiness]] comes from outside: from the sensual and esthetic enjoyments, from possessions, from other [[people]], and, according to [[religious]] believers, from [[God]]. The modern Western [[view]] of the [[mind]] is still influenced by the Aristotelian assertion that all [[emotions]], in the appropriate circumstance and in moderation, are to be accepted.30 This believe has been incorporated into the {{Wiki|theory}} of evolution, which maintains that all our [[emotions]] and other [[mental]] traits must have served us well through [[human]] evolution, otherwise we wouldn’t have them.
+
With this [[understanding]] of three {{Wiki|dimensions}} of Consciousness—ranging from the [[Wikipedia:Psyche (psychology)|psyche]] that can immediately be viewed introspectively, to the substrate [[Consciousness]], to [[primordial]] Consciousness—the [[Buddhist]] [[view]] of the [[mind]] challenges many common {{Wiki|assumptions}} in the {{Wiki|modern}} [[West]]. According to many {{Wiki|psychologists}} today, the normal [[mind]] is deemed to be healthy, but it is nevertheless [[subject]] to a wide range of [[mental]] {{Wiki|distress}}, [[including]] {{Wiki|depression}}, [[anxiety]], and [[frustration]]. But these can be managed with {{Wiki|drug}} therapy and counseling when they become excessive. While [[unhappiness]] comes simply from [[being]] [[human]], [[happiness]] comes from outside: from the {{Wiki|sensual}} and esthetic enjoyments, from possessions, from other [[people]], and, according to [[religious]] believers, from [[God]]. The {{Wiki|modern}} [[Western]] [[view]] of the [[mind]] is still influenced by the {{Wiki|Aristotelian}} [[assertion]] that all [[emotions]], in the appropriate circumstance and in moderation, are to be accepted.30 This believe has been incorporated into the {{Wiki|theory}} of [[evolution]], which maintains that all our [[emotions]] and other [[mental]] traits must have served us well through [[human]] [[evolution]], otherwise we wouldn’t have them.
  
In start contrast to the above [[views]], [[Buddhist]] contemplatives state that the ordinary [[mind]] is dysfunctional, for it oscillates between states of (1) [[being]] obsessive/compulsive (succumbing to compulsive [[ideation]] and obsessively [[grasping]] onto [[thoughts]] and [[emotions]]) and (2) slipping into a stupor. We have grown habituated to experiencing such a dysfunctional [[mind]] and mistakenly take for granted the resultant [[mental]] discomfort, believing this to be normal and reasonably healthy. With this basic [[sense]] of inner [[dissatisfaction]], we then take solace in outer and inner [[pleasurable]] stimuli, which veil the symptoms of our dysfunctional [[minds]]. While the normal [[mind]] is habitually prone to states of attentional, [[emotional]], and [[cognitive]] imbalances, it is not intrinsically dysfunctional. By refining the [[attention]] we can make the [[mind]] serviceable and thereby rediscover the innate [[sense]] of well-being that emerges spontaneously from a balanced [[mind]]. And by fathoming the nature of [[Consciousness]] to its [[primordial]] ground, all the [[obscurations]] of the [[mind]] may be removed, resulting in irreversible freedom from [[Suffering]] and its source.
+
In start contrast to the above [[views]], [[Buddhist]] contemplatives [[state]] that the ordinary [[mind]] is dysfunctional, for it oscillates between states of (1) [[being]] obsessive/compulsive (succumbing to compulsive [[ideation]] and obsessively [[grasping]] onto [[thoughts]] and [[emotions]]) and (2) slipping into a {{Wiki|stupor}}. We have grown habituated to experiencing such a dysfunctional [[mind]] and mistakenly take for granted the resultant [[mental]] discomfort, believing this to be normal and reasonably healthy. With this basic [[sense]] of inner [[dissatisfaction]], we then take solace in outer and inner [[pleasurable]] {{Wiki|stimuli}}, which [[veil]] the symptoms of our dysfunctional [[minds]]. While the normal [[mind]] is habitually prone to states of attentional, [[emotional]], and [[cognitive]] imbalances, it is not intrinsically dysfunctional. By refining the [[attention]] we can make the [[mind]] serviceable and thereby rediscover the innate [[sense]] of well-being that emerges spontaneously from a balanced [[mind]]. And by fathoming the [[nature]] of [[Consciousness]] to its [[primordial]] ground, all the [[obscurations]] of the [[mind]] may be removed, resulting in irreversible freedom from [[Suffering]] and its source.
  
 
===Conclusion===
 
===Conclusion===
  
While the [[scientific]] study of [[Consciousness]] has come into vogue in recent years, it is overwhelmingly dominated by the [[metaphysical]] {{Wiki|dogma}} of [[scientific]] {{Wiki|materialism}}. The [[influence]] of [[belief]] system does little to impede progress in the [[physical]] sciences, but its stifling effect is evident in the {{Wiki|biological}} sciences (including medical [[science]]) and even more so in the [[cognitive]] sciences. One of the most limiting aspects of this {{Wiki|dogma}} is that it places a taboo on the [[empirical]] investigation of subjective events from a first-[[person]] perspective. And there is a widespread refusal among researchers in this field even to consider the possibility that [[mental]] events may be immaterial in nature, and not simply epiphenomena of the {{Wiki|brain}}. Given the [[scientific]] ideals of {{Wiki|empiricism}} and {{Wiki|skepticism}}, it is ironic that the [[scientific]] community shows such resistance to the first-[[person]], [[empirical]] investigation of subjective [[mental]] events (as opposed to their {{Wiki|neural correlates}}) and that they show so little {{Wiki|skepticism}} toward the [[metaphysical]] claims of [[scientific]] {{Wiki|materialism}}.
+
While the [[scientific]] study of [[Consciousness]] has come into vogue in recent years, it is overwhelmingly dominated by the [[metaphysical]] {{Wiki|dogma}} of [[scientific]] {{Wiki|materialism}}. The [[influence]] of [[belief]] system does little to impede progress in the [[physical]] [[sciences]], but its stifling effect is evident in the {{Wiki|biological}} [[sciences]] ([[including]] {{Wiki|medical}} [[science]]) and even more so in the [[cognitive]] [[sciences]]. One of the most limiting aspects of this {{Wiki|dogma}} is that it places a {{Wiki|taboo}} on the [[empirical]] [[investigation]] of [[subjective]] events from a first-[[person]] {{Wiki|perspective}}. And there is a widespread refusal among researchers in this field even to consider the possibility that [[mental]] events may be {{Wiki|immaterial}} in [[nature]], and not simply epiphenomena of the {{Wiki|brain}}. Given the [[scientific]] ideals of {{Wiki|empiricism}} and {{Wiki|skepticism}}, it is ironic that the [[scientific]] {{Wiki|community}} shows such resistance to the first-[[person]], [[empirical]] [[investigation]] of [[subjective]] [[mental]] events (as opposed to their {{Wiki|neural correlates}}) and that they show so little {{Wiki|skepticism}} toward the [[metaphysical]] claims of [[scientific]] {{Wiki|materialism}}.
 
[[File:Qbqmzio1.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
 
[[File:Qbqmzio1.jpg|thumb|250px|]]
If, as I have argued in this essay, the [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]] has developed a [[science]] of [[Consciousness]], why is this not commonly [[acknowledged]]? On the one hand, it emphasizes an introspective approach to the study of the [[mind]], the value of which is not commonly accepted among [[scientists]]. But there are other compelling [[reasons]] as well. Over the centuries [[Buddhism]] become decreasingly [[empirical]] in its orientation to understanding [[human]] [[existence]], and in the process [[elements]] of dogmatism and scholasticism have become increasingly prevalent.31 This degenerating trend has been exacerbated by much modern {{Wiki|academic}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} in the field of [[Buddhist]] studies, which tends to ignore the [[exceptional]] [[experiences]] and insights of [[Buddhist]] adepts, refusing even to consider the possibility that they may have made [[extraordinary]] discoveries that may be pertinent to our contemporary understanding of the [[mind]] and its role in nature. In the most extreme cases, Western Buddhologists even go so far as to make the absurd claim that [[experience]] has never played a prominent role in [[Buddhist]] practice.32 But the problem is not just in the [[representation]] of [[Buddhist]] practice in this West. Over the centuries the [[spirit]] of open-minded inquiry seems to have faded among both [[Buddhist]] [[scholars]] and contemplatives. This has gotten to such a point, according to one contemporary [[Tibetan Buddhist]] [[scholar]], that the [[primary]] [[concern]] of many [[Buddhist]] [[meditators]] is mainly to ensure that they are following the correct procedure of a [[meditation]] technique, rather than rigorously exploring the nature of the [[mind]] or anything else.33
+
If, as I have argued in this essay, the [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]] has developed a [[science]] of [[Consciousness]], why is this not commonly [[acknowledged]]? On the one hand, it emphasizes an introspective approach to the study of the [[mind]], the value of which is not commonly accepted among [[scientists]]. But there are other compelling [[reasons]] as well. Over the centuries [[Buddhism]] become decreasingly [[empirical]] in its orientation to [[understanding]] [[human]] [[existence]], and in the process [[elements]] of {{Wiki|dogmatism}} and [[scholasticism]] have become increasingly prevalent.31 This degenerating trend has been exacerbated by much {{Wiki|modern}} {{Wiki|academic}} {{Wiki|scholarship}} in the field of [[Buddhist]] studies, which tends to ignore the [[exceptional]] [[experiences]] and [[insights]] of [[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|adepts}}, refusing even to consider the possibility that they may have made [[extraordinary]] discoveries that may be pertinent to our contemporary [[understanding]] of the [[mind]] and its role in [[nature]]. In the most extreme cases, [[Western]] [[Buddhologists]] even go so far as to make the absurd claim that [[experience]] has never played a prominent role in [[Buddhist]] practice.32 But the problem is not just in the [[representation]] of [[Buddhist]] practice in this [[West]]. Over the centuries the [[spirit]] of open-minded inquiry seems to have faded among both [[Buddhist]] [[scholars]] and contemplatives. This has gotten to such a point, according to one contemporary [[Tibetan Buddhist]] [[scholar]], that the [[primary]] [[concern]] of many [[Buddhist]] [[meditators]] is mainly to ensure that they are following the correct procedure of a [[meditation]] technique, rather than rigorously exploring the [[nature]] of the [[mind]] or anything else.33
  
During the {{Wiki|Renaissance}}, {{Wiki|Europe}} emerged from the shackles of [[religious]] {{Wiki|dogma}} in part because of the [[influx]] of fresh and provocative ideas from classical Greece and the Arab [[world]]. Now the West (and all other countries dominated by the West) is in need of a {{Wiki|Renaissance}} to free it from the [[intellectual]] tyranny of [[scientific]] {{Wiki|materialism}}, which is often falsely conflated with [[science]] itself. The [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]], especially if it is re-instilled with the [[spirit]] of {{Wiki|empiricism}} and {{Wiki|skepticism}}, may play an important role in such a {{Wiki|Renaissance}}.
+
During the {{Wiki|Renaissance}}, {{Wiki|Europe}} emerged from the shackles of [[religious]] {{Wiki|dogma}} in part because of the [[influx]] of fresh and provocative [[ideas]] from classical {{Wiki|Greece}} and the Arab [[world]]. Now the [[West]] (and all other countries dominated by the [[West]]) is in need of a {{Wiki|Renaissance}} to free it from the [[intellectual]] tyranny of [[scientific]] {{Wiki|materialism}}, which is often falsely conflated with [[science]] itself. The [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]], especially if it is re-instilled with the [[spirit]] of {{Wiki|empiricism}} and {{Wiki|skepticism}}, may play an important role in such a {{Wiki|Renaissance}}.
  
Researchers in the [[mind]]/[[body]] problem commonly appeal to the authority of future [[scientists]] to confirm their present materialistic assumptions about the nature of [[Consciousness]]. Antonio R. Damasio, for example, claims “it is probably safe to say that by 2050 sufficient [[knowledge]] of {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]] will have wiped out the [[traditional]] [[dualistic]] separations of [[body]]/{{Wiki|brain}}, [[body]]/[[mind]] and {{Wiki|brain}}/[[mind]].”34 It took the [[scientific]] community fifty years to [[recognize]] that themind couldn’t meaningfully be reduced to a set of {{Wiki|behavioral}} dispositions. Hopefully it will not take that long before {{Wiki|neuroscientists}} open their [[minds]] to the possibility that the [[mind]] may not be meaningfully reduced to neural mechanisms either.
+
Researchers in the [[mind]]/[[body]] problem commonly appeal to the authority of {{Wiki|future}} [[scientists]] to confirm their {{Wiki|present}} {{Wiki|materialistic}} {{Wiki|assumptions}} about the [[nature]] of [[Consciousness]]. Antonio R. Damasio, for example, claims “it is probably safe to say that by 2050 sufficient [[knowledge]] of {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomena]] will have wiped out the [[traditional]] [[dualistic]] separations of [[body]]/{{Wiki|brain}}, [[body]]/[[mind]] and {{Wiki|brain}}/[[mind]].”34 It took the [[scientific]] {{Wiki|community}} fifty years to [[recognize]] that themind couldn’t meaningfully be reduced to a set of {{Wiki|behavioral}} dispositions. Hopefully it will not take that long before {{Wiki|neuroscientists}} open their [[minds]] to the possibility that the [[mind]] may not be meaningfully reduced to neural mechanisms either.
  
While [[science]] characteristically embraces the “disturbingly new,” it has a much harder [[time]] embracing the “disturbingly old,” namely, discoveries that were made long ago (let alone in an alien civilization), prior to the [[Scientific]] Revolution. Many [[Buddhists]], on the other hand, rely so heavily on the insights of the [[Buddha]] and later contemplatives of the past, that they have a hard [[time]] embracing disturbing new discoveries that challenge [[Buddhist]] [[beliefs]]. [[Scientific]] {{Wiki|materialists}} are so confident that the [[mind]] is [[nothing]] more than a {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomenon]] that they confuse this [[belief]] with [[scientific]] [[knowledge]]. Similarly, many [[traditional]] [[Buddhists]] are so confident of the validity of their [[doctrine]] that they confuse their [[belief]] with contemplative [[knowledge]]. In his [[book]] The Discoverers: A History of Man’s Search to [[Know]] His [[World]] and Himself, historian Daniel J. Boorstin refers to “the [[illusions]] of [[knowledge]]” as the principle obstacles to discovery. The great discoverers of the past, he declares, “had to battle against the current ‘facts’ and {{Wiki|dogmas}} of the learned.”35
+
While [[science]] characteristically embraces the “disturbingly new,” it has a much harder [[time]] embracing the “disturbingly old,” namely, discoveries that were made long ago (let alone in an alien {{Wiki|civilization}}), prior to the [[Scientific]] {{Wiki|Revolution}}. Many [[Buddhists]], on the other hand, rely so heavily on the [[insights]] of the [[Buddha]] and later contemplatives of the {{Wiki|past}}, that they have a hard [[time]] embracing {{Wiki|disturbing}} new discoveries that challenge [[Buddhist]] [[beliefs]]. [[Scientific]] {{Wiki|materialists}} are so confident that the [[mind]] is [[nothing]] more than a {{Wiki|biological}} [[phenomenon]] that they confuse this [[belief]] with [[scientific]] [[knowledge]]. Similarly, many [[traditional]] [[Buddhists]] are so confident of the validity of their [[doctrine]] that they confuse their [[belief]] with {{Wiki|contemplative}} [[knowledge]]. In his [[book]] The Discoverers: A History of Man’s Search to [[Know]] His [[World]] and Himself, historian Daniel J. Boorstin refers to “the [[illusions]] of [[knowledge]]” as the [[principle]] [[obstacles]] to discovery. The great discoverers of the {{Wiki|past}}, he declares, “had to {{Wiki|battle}} against the current ‘facts’ and {{Wiki|dogmas}} of the learned.”35
  
The [[scientific]] [[tradition]] has now joined the [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]] in its pursuit of understanding the nature, origins, and potentials of [[Consciousness]]. At this point in {{Wiki|history}}, it may be said that neither [[embodies]] a rigorous, unbiased, multifaceted [[science]] of [[Consciousness]]. But as [[scientists]] and [[Buddhists]] collaborate in the investigation of this [[phenomenon]] so central to [[human]] [[existence]], perhaps such a [[science]] may emerge to the benefit of both [[traditions]] and the [[world]] at large.
+
The [[scientific]] [[tradition]] has now joined the [[Buddhist]] [[tradition]] in its pursuit of [[understanding]] the [[nature]], origins, and potentials of [[Consciousness]]. At this point in {{Wiki|history}}, it may be said that neither [[embodies]] a rigorous, unbiased, multifaceted [[science]] of [[Consciousness]]. But as [[scientists]] and [[Buddhists]] collaborate in the [[investigation]] of this [[phenomenon]] so central to [[human]] [[existence]], perhaps such a [[science]] may emerge to the [[benefit]] of both [[traditions]] and the [[world]] at large.
  
  
==Bibliography==
+
==[[Bibliography]]==
  
{{Wiki|Aristotle}} (1985) Nicomachean [[Ethics]]. Terence Irwin (trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
+
{{Wiki|Aristotle}} (1985) Nicomachean [[Ethics]]. Terence Irwin (trans.). {{Wiki|Indianapolis}}: Hackett Publishing Company.
  
 
Boorstin, Daniel J. (1985) The Discoverers: A History of Man’s Search to [[Know]] His [[World]] and Himself. {{Wiki|New York}}: Vintage [[Books]].
 
Boorstin, Daniel J. (1985) The Discoverers: A History of Man’s Search to [[Know]] His [[World]] and Himself. {{Wiki|New York}}: Vintage [[Books]].
  
Burnaby, John. (1938/1991) Amor Dei: A Study of the [[Religion]] of St. Augustine. Norwich: The Canterbury Press.
+
Burnaby, John. (1938/1991) Amor Dei: A Study of the [[Religion]] of [[Wikipedia:Augustine of Hippo|St. Augustine]]. Norwich: The Canterbury Press.
  
Butler, Dom Cuthbert. (1967) Western [[Mysticism]]: The [[Teaching]] of Augustine, Gregory and Bernard on [[Contemplation]] and the Contemplative [[Life]]. 3rd ed., with “Afterthoughts” by Prof. David Knowles. {{Wiki|London}}: Constable & Co.
+
Butler, Dom Cuthbert. (1967) [[Western]] [[Mysticism]]: The [[Teaching]] of Augustine, Gregory and Bernard on [[Contemplation]] and the Contemplative [[Life]]. 3rd ed., with “Afterthoughts” by Prof. David Knowles. {{Wiki|London}}: Constable & Co.
  
Cabezón, José Ignacio. (1994) [[Buddhism]] and [[Language]]: A Study of Indo-Tibetan Scholasticism. Albany, NY: {{Wiki|State University of New York}} Press.
+
[[Cabezón]], José Ignacio. (1994) [[Buddhism]] and [[Language]]: A Study of [[Indo-Tibetan]] [[Scholasticism]]. [[Albany]], NY: {{Wiki|State University of New York}} Press.
  
Chadwick, Owen. (trans. & ed.) (1958) The Conferences of Cassian in Western Asceticism. Philadelphia: Westminster Press.
+
Chadwick, Owen. (trans. & ed.) (1958) The Conferences of Cassian in [[Western]] [[Asceticism]]. Philadelphia: Westminster Press.
  
Crick, F. and C. Koch. (1998) “Towards a Neurobiological {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Consciousness]]” in The Nature of [[Consciousness]]: [[Philosophical]] [[Debates]]. N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.) {{Wiki|Cambridge}}, MA: MIT Press, pp. 277-292.
+
Crick, F. and C. Koch. (1998) “Towards a Neurobiological {{Wiki|Theory}} of [[Consciousness]]” in The [[Nature]] of [[Consciousness]]: [[Philosophical]] [[Debates]]. N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.) {{Wiki|Cambridge}}, MA: MIT Press, pp. 277-292.
  
 
H. H. the [[Dalai Lama]]. (1999) [[Ethics]] for the New Millennium. {{Wiki|New York}}: Riverhead [[Books]].
 
H. H. the [[Dalai Lama]]. (1999) [[Ethics]] for the New Millennium. {{Wiki|New York}}: Riverhead [[Books]].
  
 
Damasio, Antonio R. (1998) The [[Feeling]] of What Happens: [[Body]] and [[Emotion]] in the Making of [[Consciousness]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Harcourt, Inc.
 
Damasio, Antonio R. (1998) The [[Feeling]] of What Happens: [[Body]] and [[Emotion]] in the Making of [[Consciousness]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Harcourt, Inc.
:———(2002) “How the {{Wiki|brain}} creates the [[mind]].” in [[Scientific]] American, Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 4-9.
+
:———(2002) “How the {{Wiki|brain}} creates the [[mind]].” in [[Scientific]] [[American]], Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 4-9.
  
Dennett, Daniel C. (1991) [[Consciousness]] Explained. Boston:  Little,  Brown  and Co.
+
Dennett, Daniel C. (1991) [[Consciousness]] Explained. [[Boston]]:  Little,  Brown  and Co.
  
James,  William.  (1890/1950)  The  Principles  of  [[Psychology]]. {{Wiki|New York}}:  Dover Publications.
+
James,  William.  (1890/1950)  The  {{Wiki|Principles}} of  [[Psychology]]. {{Wiki|New York}}:  Dover Publications.
 
:———(1892). “A plea for [[psychology]] as a [[science]].” [[Philosophical]] Review, 1,  pp. 146-153.
 
:———(1892). “A plea for [[psychology]] as a [[science]].” [[Philosophical]] Review, 1,  pp. 146-153.
:———(1890/1950) The Principles of [[Psychology]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Dover Publications. Matt, Daniel  C. (1990) Ayin: “The {{Wiki|Concept}} of [[Nothingness]] in Jewish [[Mysticism]].” in Robert K. C. Forman (ed.) The Problem of [[Pure Consciousness]]: [[Mysticism]] and [[Philosophy]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Oxford University Press.
+
:———(1890/1950) The {{Wiki|Principles}} of [[Psychology]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Dover Publications. Matt, Daniel  C. (1990) Ayin: “The {{Wiki|Concept}} of [[Nothingness]] in [[Wikipedia:Judaism|Jewish]] [[Mysticism]].” in Robert K. C. Forman (ed.) The Problem of [[Pure Consciousness]]: [[Mysticism]] and [[Philosophy]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: [[Oxford University Press]].
:———(1995) The [[Essential]] {{Wiki|Kabbalah}}:  The  [[Heart]]  of  Jewish  [[Mysticism]]. San Francisco: Harper San Francisco.
+
:———(1995) The [[Essential]] {{Wiki|Kabbalah}}:  The  [[Heart]]  of  [[Wikipedia:Judaism|Jewish]] [[Mysticism]]. [[San Francisco]]: {{Wiki|Harper San Francisco}}.
  
 
Searle, John. R. (1994) The Rediscovery of the [[Mind]]. {{Wiki|Cambridge}}, Mass.: MIT Press.
 
Searle, John. R. (1994) The Rediscovery of the [[Mind]]. {{Wiki|Cambridge}}, Mass.: MIT Press.
  
Sharf, Robert H. 1995. “[[Buddhist]] Modernism and the [[Rhetoric]] of [[Meditative]] [[Experiences]].” Numen (42) pp. 228-283.
+
Sharf, Robert H. 1995. “[[Buddhist]] {{Wiki|Modernism}} and the [[Rhetoric]] of [[Meditative]] [[Experiences]].” Numen (42) pp. 228-283.
:———1998.  “[[Experience]].”  In  Mark  C.  Taylor,  ed.  Critical  Terms  for  [[Religious]] Studies.  {{Wiki|Chicago}}: University of {{Wiki|Chicago}} Press, pp. 94-116.
+
:———1998.  “[[Experience]].”  In  Mark  C.  Taylor,  ed.  Critical  Terms  for  [[Religious]] Studies.  {{Wiki|Chicago}}: {{Wiki|University}} of {{Wiki|Chicago}} Press, pp. 94-116.
  
Snyder, C. R. & Shane J. Lopez (eds.) (2002) Handbook of Positive [[Psychology]]. {{Wiki|New York}}:  Oxford University Press.
+
[[Snyder]], C. R. & Shane J. [[Lopez]] (eds.) (2002) Handbook of Positive [[Psychology]]. {{Wiki|New York}}:  [[Oxford University Press]].
  
 
Wallace,  B.  Alan.  (1998)  The  Bridge  of  Quiescence:  Experiencing  [[Tibetan Buddhist]] [[Meditation]]. {{Wiki|Chicago}}: Open Court.
 
Wallace,  B.  Alan.  (1998)  The  Bridge  of  Quiescence:  Experiencing  [[Tibetan Buddhist]] [[Meditation]]. {{Wiki|Chicago}}: Open Court.
:———(1999) "The [[Buddhist Tradition]] of [[Samatha]]: Methods for Refining and Examining [[Consciousness]]." Journal of [[Consciousness]] Studies, 6, No. 2-3, 1999, pp. 175-187.
+
:———(1999) "The [[Buddhist Tradition]] of [[Samatha]]: [[Methods]] for Refining and Examining [[Consciousness]]." Journal of [[Consciousness]] Studies, 6, No. 2-3, 1999, pp. 175-187.
:———(2000)  The  Taboo  of  [[Subjectivity]]:  Toward  a  New  {{Wiki|Science}}  of  [[Consciousness]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Oxford University Press.
+
:———(2000)  The  {{Wiki|Taboo}}   of  [[Subjectivity]]:  Toward  a  New  {{Wiki|Science}}  of  [[Consciousness]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: [[Oxford University Press]].
  
Walshe, M. O. C. (trans.) (1979 & 1987) Meister Eckhart: Sermons & Treatises,Vols. I-III, Longmead: [[Element]] [[Books]] Ltd.
+
[[Walshe]], M. O. C. (trans.) (1979 & 1987) {{Wiki|Meister Eckhart}}: [[Sermons]] & Treatises,Vols. I-III, Longmead: [[Element]] [[Books]] Ltd.
  
 
Wilson, E. O. (1998) {{Wiki|Consilience}}: The Unity of [[Knowledge]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Alfred A. Knopf.]
 
Wilson, E. O. (1998) {{Wiki|Consilience}}: The Unity of [[Knowledge]]. {{Wiki|New York}}: Alfred A. Knopf.]
Line 148: Line 156:
 
{{Verse|verse|6.}} John Burnaby (1938: 52 & 67)
 
{{Verse|verse|6.}} John Burnaby (1938: 52 & 67)
  
{{Verse|verse|7.}} M. O’C Walshe (1979: 1: 7)
+
{{Verse|verse|7.}} M. O’C [[Walshe]] (1979: 1: 7)
  
 
{{Verse|verse|8.}} {{Wiki|William James}} (1890/1950) I:191-2 & 197-8. 9 Exodus 22:18. New International Version 10John B. Watson (1913).
 
{{Verse|verse|8.}} {{Wiki|William James}} (1890/1950) I:191-2 & 197-8. 9 Exodus 22:18. New International Version 10John B. Watson (1913).
Line 184: Line 192:
 
{{Verse|verse|24.}} Ibid. I: 424
 
{{Verse|verse|24.}} Ibid. I: 424
  
{{Verse|verse|25.}} One very promising development in modern [[psychology]] in this regard is the [[emergence]] of “positive [[psychology]].” See C. R. Snyder & Shane J. Lopez (eds.) (2002).
+
{{Verse|verse|25.}} One very [[promising]] [[development]] in {{Wiki|modern}} [[psychology]] in this regard is the [[emergence]] of “positive [[psychology]].” See C. R. [[Snyder]] & Shane J. [[Lopez]] (eds.) (2002).
  
 
{{Verse|verse|26.}} For a more detailed presentation of these [[Four Noble Truths]] within a contemporary context, see Wallace (1998: 29-101).
 
{{Verse|verse|26.}} For a more detailed presentation of these [[Four Noble Truths]] within a contemporary context, see Wallace (1998: 29-101).
Line 190: Line 198:
 
{{Verse|verse|27.}} The process by which the [[mind]] can attend to [[Consciousness]] itself is addressed in Wallace (1999).
 
{{Verse|verse|27.}} The process by which the [[mind]] can attend to [[Consciousness]] itself is addressed in Wallace (1999).
  
{{Verse|verse|28.}} For a detailed account of this type of attentional training, see Wallace (1998).
+
{{Verse|verse|28.}} For a detailed account of this type of attentional {{Wiki|training}}, see Wallace (1998).
  
{{Verse|verse|29.}} For a lucid presentation of [[Buddhist]] [[ethics]] presented within a modern, secular context see H.H. the [[Dalai Lama]] (1999).
+
{{Verse|verse|29.}} For a lucid presentation of [[Buddhist]] [[ethics]] presented within a {{Wiki|modern}}, {{Wiki|secular}} context see H.H. the [[Dalai Lama]] (1999).
  
 
{{Verse|verse|30.}} {{Wiki|Aristotle}} (1985)
 
{{Verse|verse|30.}} {{Wiki|Aristotle}} (1985)
  
{{Verse|verse|31.}} For a [[discussion]] of scholasticism within Indo-[[Tibetan Buddhism]] see José Ignacio Cabezón (1994).
+
{{Verse|verse|31.}} For a [[discussion]] of [[scholasticism]] within Indo-[[Tibetan Buddhism]] see [[José Ignacio Cabezón]] (1994).
  
{{Verse|verse|32.}} See Robert H. Sharf (1995) (1998).
+
{{Verse|verse|32.}} See [[Robert H. Sharf]] (1995) (1998).
  
 
{{Verse|verse|33.}} Personal {{Wiki|communication}} from [[Geshe Thupten Jinpa]], June 6, 2002.
 
{{Verse|verse|33.}} Personal {{Wiki|communication}} from [[Geshe Thupten Jinpa]], June 6, 2002.

Latest revision as of 15:07, 26 December 2023

Shell.JPG





“A Science of Consciousness: Buddhism (1), the Modern West (0)”

B. Alan Wallace Published in

The Pacific World: Journal of the Institute of Buddhist Studies

Third Series, No. 4, Fall 2002, pp. 15-32

Introduction

In his classic work Science and Civilization in China Joseph Needham explored the historical reasons why China, for all its long civilization, never developed science as we understand it in the modern West, namely a quantitative, technologically driven science of the outer, physical world. In this paper I shall first outline some of the reasons why Western civilization has never developed a science of Consciousness. I shall then argue that Buddhism has made major strides in developing such a science, and that the contemplative refinement of attention, and the subsequent utilization of such attention in exploring the mind firsthand plays a crucial role in such an endeavor. Such training of the mind is vital for investigating the nature of Consciousness, and it is also an important prerequisite to transforming Consciousness in the pursuit of mental health and genuine well-being. While Buddhism has a rich contemplative tradition for the first-person exploration of states of Consciousness, it never developed the sciences of the brain and behavior that we have in the modern West. So the integration of the first-person methodologies of Buddhism with the third-person methodologies of the cognitive sciences may lead to a richer understanding of Consciousness than either Buddhist or Western civilization has discovered on its own.

Historical Impediments to the Emergence of a Science of Consciousness in the West

SerindianGroup.jpg

When asking why the West has yet to develop a science of Consciousness, I turn first to the twin roots of Western civilization: the Greco-Roman and the Judeo-Christian traditions. In general, a pivotal element in the emergence of a new science is the development and refinement of instruments to precisely observe and possibly experiment with the phenomena under investigation. Galileo’s use of the telescope to examine the sun, moon, and planets signaled the emergence of the science of astronomy, much as Van Leeuwenhoek’s use of the microscope in observing minute life forms was instrumental to the emergence of modern biology. It is therefore reasonable to assume that if there is to be, or ever has been, a science of Consciousness, it will be heralded by the development and refinement of an instrument with which states of Consciousness can be observed with rigor and precision. The only instrument humanity has ever had for directly observing the mind is the mind itself, so that must be the instrument to be refined. The untrained attention is habitually prone to alternating bouts of agitation and dullness, so if the mind is to be used as a reliable tool for exploring and experimenting with Consciousness, these dysfunctional traits need to be replaced with attentional stability and vividness.

While the philosophers of ancient Greece were certainly interested in the nature of the mind, there is little evidence that they developed any sophisticated means for refining the attention. The Pythagorean brotherhood and the mystery schools may have devised such methods, but if they did, such knowledge has not been preserved. Jewish mystics also wrote extensively on the nature of Consciousness,1 but the development of techniques to cultivate attentional stability and vividness for the rigorous exploration of Consciousness was not a strong suit of this tradition either. The Greeks did coin the term eudaimonia, commonly translated as genuine happiness, or human flourishing, referring to “the perfect life” in so far as perfection is attainable by humanity. For Plotinus, the source of genuine happiness lies within the human spirit, but when the concept of eudaimonia was absorbed into the Christian tradition, Augustine insisted that the soul must look outside itself—to God—for such perfection.2

However, it must be added that a principal way he taught to go about this endeavor was through a contemplative process that draws the attention inwards, going beyond the self to a direct encounter with God, the very source of eudaimonia.3 In this regard, perhaps the fundamental difference between Plotinus and Augustine has to do with their views on the parameters of human identity, the boundary between the human soul and the divine.

Within the Christian tradition, the early desert fathers were certainly aware of the need to calm the mind, as is evidenced in the seminal fifth-century volume on contemplative practice entitled The Conferences of Cassian.4 But it is not clear that Christian contemplatives of that period or the later medieval era devised effective means for training the attention as a means for observing mental events. This failure may be at least in part responsible for the widespread conclusion among Christian mystics that the highest states of contemplation are necessarily fleeting, commonly lasting no longer than about half an hour.5 This insistence on the fleeting nature of mystical union appears to originate with Augustine,6 and it is reflected almost a millennium later in the writings of Meister Eckhart, who emphasized that the state of contemplative rapture is invariably transient, with even its residual effects lasting no longer than three days.7

Scmandala.jpg

With the advent of the Protestant Reformation and the Scientific Revolution, the gradual decline of Christian contemplative inquiry into the nature of Consciousness rapidly accelerated. Given the Protestant emphasis on the Augustinian theme of the essential iniquity of the human soul, and man’s utter inability to achieve salvation or know God except by faith, there was no longer any theological incentive for such inquiry. Salvation was emphatically presented as an undeserved gift from the Creator. So genuine happiness, which is to be truly experienced only in the hereafter, is in no way earned by understanding the mind or achieving exceptional states of mental health and balance.

Descartes, whose ideological influence on the Scientific Revolution is hard to overestimate, was deeply committed to the introspective examination of the mind. But like his Greek and Christian predecessors, he did not devise means to refine the attention so that the mind could reliably be used to observe mental events. On the contrary, he naively believed that anything that was clearly and distinctly perceived by means of introspection was invariably valid—an assumption that was effectively refuted by William James at the end of the nineteenth century.8 Moreover, in a theological move that effectively removed the human mind from the natural world, Descartes decreed that the soul is divinely infused into the body, where it exerts its influence on the body by way of the pineal gland. It was this gland, he believed, that, on decision of the soul, induces the voluntary actions of the body, while all other actions are reflexive. This philosophical stance probably accounts in large part for the fact that the Western scientific study of the mind did not even begin for more than two centuries after Descartes. And until the last three decades of the twentieth century, the pineal gland was uniquely neglected by physiological and biochemical investigators. Although various factors may be responsible for the scientific avoidance of this region of the brain, it seems plausible that one reason was that, given the special status attributed to it by Descartes, it was still considered to be outside the proper domain of natural science.

Another trend in Europe at the dawn of the modern era provided yet a further incentive for not delving deeply into the human mind, and that was the witch-hunting craze from the late fifteenth century through the mid-seventeenth century. During this period, anyone who exhibited exceptional mental powers, including the Power of spiritual healing, was immediately suspect of being a witch. While nearly all traditional societies have believed in witchcraft, the Christian tradition in particular attributed the powers of witches to the Devil, which is the rationale for the biblical commandment that such people are to be put to death.9 The common belief that demons and other spiritual entities roved about in the natural world (sometimes taking possession of human souls) was of course deeply incompatible with the emerging mechanical view of the universe. After all, scientists couldn’t very well establish orderly physical laws in the objective world as long as there were immaterial spirits roving about, intervening at will in the affairs of man and nature. So many natural philosophers of the late sixteenth century simply dismissed them as illusions. Newton, on the other hand, who devoted much of his time to developing his own theology, withdrew evil spirits from the objective physical world and placed them inside the human mind in the form of mental disorders. God’s outer creation had now been cleansed of these contaminating influences, leaving only the inner being of man defiled. It would take another two hundred years before Western psychoanalysts would have the nerve to begin the scientific exploration of these dark inner realities.

In short, the trajectory of Western science from the time of Copernicus to the modern day seems to have been influenced by medieval Christian cosmology. Just as hell was symbolized as being in the center of the earth, and heaven was in the outermost reaches of space, the inner, subjective world of man was depicted as being the locus of evil, while the objective world was free of such moral contamination. It hardly seems an accident that the science that initiated the Scientific Revolution was astronomy, and it took a full three hundred years for the scientific discipline of psychology to begin. And it was only in the closing years of the twentieth century that the scientific community began to regard Consciousness as a legitimate subject of scientific inquiry.

Schubring 001.jpg

Why did it take psychology—which itself emerged only after many scientists felt that they had already discovered all the principal laws of the universe—a century before it began to address the nature of Consciousness? This was due in large part to the fifty-year domination of academic psychology by behaviorism. In 1913, the American behaviorist John B. Watson declared that psychologists must avoid the use of all subjective terms such as sensation, perception, image, desire, purpose, and even thinking and emotion as they are subjectively defined. And he attributed belief in the very existence of Consciousness to ancient superstitions and magic.10 Forty years later, B. F. Skinner echoed this theme by asserting that mind as such does not exist at all, only dispositions for behavior. It took another decade before the futility of equating subjective mental processes with “objectivebehavioral dispositions became increasingly apparent to the scientific community. The behaviorist approach did nothing to explain the nature of the mind, let alone Consciousness; it just reduced these subjective phenomena to a class of objective processes they could study with the available tools of science.

With the emergence of cognitive psychology during the 1960s, subjective experience was once again allowed back into the realm of scientific research, but the role of introspection in exploring the mind was still marginalized in this field, just as it is in the rapidly progressing discipline of neuroscience. Rather than equating mental processes with behavioral dispositions, cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists now equate them with neural events. As neurologist Antonio R. Damasio recently commented, “the biological processes now presumed to correspond to mind processes in fact are mind processes and will be seen to be so when understood in sufficient detail…the private personal mind…indeed is biological and will one day be described in terms both biological and mental.”11 However, what neuroscientists actually know is that specific neural events (N) are correlated to specific mental events (M), such that if N occurs, M occurs; if M occurs, N occurs; if N doesn’t occur, M doesn’t occur; and if M doesn’t occur, N doesn’t occur. Such a correlation could imply that the occurrence of N has a causal role in the production of M, or vice versa; or it could imply that N and M are actually the same phenomenon viewed from different perspectives. There is not enough scientific knowledge at this point to determine which of these types of correlation is the correct one. But Damasio seems to overlook this ambiguity and simply decrees the equivalence of mental and neural processes, without any logical or empirical justification. In other words, this equivalence is simply a metaphysical belief.

While writing this essay, I questioned Damasio on this point, and he responded that in his book The Feeling of What Happens12 he goes to great pains to explain that neural patterns are not equivalent to mental images. There is an explanatory gap, he points out, regarding the process by which a neural pattern is converted to a mental image; and neuroscience, in particular, and science, in general, may never be able to bridge that gap. He further acknowledges that the “physicality” of mental phenomena has not yet been identified scientifically; it is simply a working hypothesis. As hard as I try, I just can't see the logic in his position. To say that A is B, implies an identity, not a causal relation between two distinct entities A and B. He seems to be saying that mental phenomena are biological phenomena produced by prior biological phenomena. But that still implies that mental phenomena are equivalent to some kind of biological phenomena. So the distinction between mental and neural processes fades out immediately.

In the book cited above, Damasio explains why neuroscience has been wrong about not making clear the distinctions between first-person and third- person views regarding discussions on mind and Consciousness. This is an important and valid point. At the same time, he seems to advocate that in the final analysis, mental processes are their neural correlates viewed from a first- person perspective; and neural processes are their mental correlates viewed from a third-person perspective. But this widespread belief is just that—an speculative hypothesis—and not a scientifically demonstrated conclusion, despite the fact that it is commonly taken for granted by researchers in this field.

Sailand.jpg

How does Damasio explain the fact that the neural processes that he equates with mental processes have the capacity to be about other things? This question, called the hard problem, is regarded by many philosophers as a formidable, unsolved mystery. But Damasio assures his readers that this turns out to be no mystery at all: “evolution has crafted a brain that is in the business of directly representing the organism and indirectly representing whatever the organism interacts with.” Brain cells, he declares, “designed to be about other things and other doings.”13 In short, his solution to this problem is that the brain has the capacity to represent other things because it was designed that way “by evolution.” This “explanation” obviously illuminates nothing other than the fact that Damasio has great faith in the mysterious ways of evolution, which for the biologist here takes on the role theologians have long ascribed to God.

Mental events viewed introspectively appear to be radically different types of processes than neural events viewed objectively. Moreover, if one confines oneself to the introspective examination of the mind, one evidently learns little if anything about the brain. And if brain scientists were to confine their research to the brain alone, without reference to any first-person reports of mental experience, they would learn little if anything about the mind. Indeed, they would have no reason, on the basis of neural events alone, to conclude that they are correlated to any mental events at all. Damasio accounts for this disparity as follows: “The appearance of a gulf between mental states and physical/biological phenomena comes from the large disparity between two bodies of knowledge—the good understanding of mind we have achieved through centuries of introspection and the efforts of cognitive science versus the incomplete neural specification we have achieved through the efforts of neuroscience.”14

Many contemporary scientists and philosophers would challenge his assertion that we now have “a good understanding” of the mind as a result of centuries of introspection and discoveries in cognitive science. Biologist Edward O. Wilson maintains that logic launched from introspection is limited and usually unreliable, which is why even today people know more about their automobiles than they do about their own minds.15 The general consensus among psychologists is that introspection is an unreliable means for investigating the mind. As for our current understanding of the mind and Consciousness, two of America’s most prominent philosophers of mind comment, “Consciousness stands alone today as a topic that often leaves even the most sophisticated thinkers tongue-tied and confused,”16 and “where the mind is concerned we are characteristically confused and in disagreement.”17 The real gist of Damasio’s assertion seems to be that we already have enough understanding of mental processes themselves, so now the emphasis should be placed on neuroscience to explore the biological processes that are, after all, the same as mental processes, just viewed from an objective perspective.

If scientists were presented with a new instrument for observing a specific type of natural phenomena, the first logical step for them to take before using this instrument would be to examine its nature and capacities. Does this instrument present the scientists merely its own artifacts, like looking through a kaleidoscope, or does it provide them with data that exist independently of it? If it does yield such information, does it distort it in the process of bringing it to them, or does it provide them with truly objective data from a source independent of the instrument? Only after they have understood the design, functioning, reliability, and capacities of the instrument could they confidently use it to collect data.

The primary instrument that all scientists have used to make any type of observation is the human mind. Does this instrument provide us only with its own artifacts, without any access to any objective reality existing independently of the mind? Or if the mind provides us with information about the objective world, does it distort it in the process? For reasons outlined above, the scientific study of the mind in the West was delayed for three centuries after the inception of the Scientific Revolution, which is tantamount to using an instrument for three hundred years before subjecting it to scientific scrutiny.

Riversflow.JPG

What kind of scientific worldview has emerged as a result of this profound oversight and the enormous disparity of our understanding of the mind and the rest of the natural world? Wilson expresses the view of many scientists with his assertion that outside our heads there is an independent, objective world, and inside our heads is a reconstitution of reality based on sensory input and the self-assembly of concepts. The proper task of scientists, he claims is to correctly align our inner representations of reality with the world outside our heads.18 The problem here, which he openly acknowledges, is that scientists have no body of external objective truth by which the alignment of scientific theories and the world outside our heads can be calibrated. In other words, the empirical data that we perceive, together with our scientific theories that account for them, all consists of mental representations “within our heads”; and we have no objective yardstick with which to compare those representations with what we assume to be the “real world.”

How are we to get out of this conundrum? Wilson suggests, “Criteria of objective truth might be attainable through empirical investigation. The key lies in clarifying the still poorly understood operations composing the mind and in improving the piecemeal approach science has taken to its material properties.”19 Like Damasio, Wilson assumes that the mind is actually composed of brain processes, but as I have already pointed out, at this point such an assertion is simply a metaphysical belief, not a scientifically established fact. Given how little scientists presently understand about the relation between the mind and brain, it would be far more objective to regard this as a topic to be researched with an open mind, rather than assuming (or demanding) that science will one day confirm our current materialistic biases. In order to understand the relation between scientific theories and the objective phenomena they ostensibly represent, we clearly need to have a more thorough, scientific understanding of the mind. As I commented earlier, the first step in developing a science of any kind of phenomena is to develop and refine instruments that allow one to observe and possibly experiment with the phenomena under investigation. The only instrument we have that enables us to observe mental phenomena directly is the mind itself. But since the time of Aristotle, the West has made little if any progress in developing means of refining the mind so that it can be used as a reliable instrument for observing mental events. And judging by the writings of many scientists, such as E. O. Wilson, there continues to be considerable resistance against developing any such empirical science even today.

Thus, if we follow this present materialistic trend, no such empirical science of Consciousness is likely to emerge in the foreseeable future. Rather, if the cognitive sciences continue to be constrained by the metaphysical dictates of scientific materialism,20 all we will do is reduce Consciousness to something that can be explored and understood within the parameters of that dogma, as various researchers, such as Crick and Koch,21 are already attempting to do. Just as kinematics (the phenomenological study of matter in motion) must precede mechanics in the study of physics, the rigorous, firsthand investigation of Consciousness must precede any formulation of the mechanisms that account the emergence of Consciousness. Modern science has never developed a rigorous introspective methodology for observing the phenomena of conscious mental processes and states. William James, the foremost pioneer of American psychology, acknowledged the importance of studying behavioral and neural correlates to mental processes, but he emphasized the primary role of introspection in this endeavor.22 However, the untrained mind, which is prone to alternating agitation and dullness, is an unreliable and inadequate instrument for observing anything.

Relig.jpg

To transform it into a suitable instrument for scientific exploration, the stability and vividness of the attention must be developed to a high degree. James was well aware of the importance of developing such sustained, voluntary attention,23 but he acknowledged that he did not know how to achieve this task.24 To sum up, the modern West has developed a sophisticated science of behavioral and neural correlates of Consciousness, but no science of Consciousness itself, for it has failed to develop sophisticated, rigorous means of exploring the phenomena of Consciousness firsthand. And this is the first step towards an empirical science of any class of natural phenomena. Thus with regard to exploring the nature, origins, and potentials of Consciousness, cognitive scientists and neuroscientists are more like astrologers (who carefully examine correlates between the celestial and terrestrial phenomena) than astronomers (who carefully examine celestial phenomena themselves). A second result of the historical development of science is that the modern West has an elaborate science of mental illness, but no science of mental health. Indeed there is hardly any scientific consensus on the criteria by which to identify mental health. Nor do we in the West have any science that shows how to cultivate extraordinary mental health or genuine happiness. In short, the theme of eudaimonia, a state human flourishing sometimes glossed as a “truth- given joy,” has been forgotten in modern science,25 and the very existence of a truth that yields such well-being has no place in the scientific view of human existence or the universe at large.

In short, the West presently has no pure science of Consciousness that reveals the nature, origins, and potentials of this natural phenomenon, and it similarly lacks an applied science of Consciousness that reveals means for refining and enhancing Consciousness and thereby achieving eudaimonia. But the fact that the West has failed to develop such a science does not necessarily imply that all other human civilizations throughout history have been equally deficient in this regard.

The Buddhist Science of Consciousness

Over the course of its 2500-year history, Buddhism has developed rigorous methods for refining the attention, and then applying that attention to exploring the origins, nature, and role of Consciousness in the natural world. The empirical and rational investigations and discoveries by such great Indian contemplatives as Gautama the Buddha profoundly challenge many of the assumptions of the modern West, particularly those of scientific materialism. This meeting of Buddhist and modern Western science also challenges our very notion of “metaphysics.” In the nineteenth century, the origins of the physical universe, the constitution of distant galaxies, and the internal structure of molecules were all metaphysical issues. At that time, there were no known ways of exploring these topics empirically, but that is no longer the case. In the twenty-first century, the nature, origins, and destiny of human Consciousness are still metaphysical issues for the West, but are they similarly clouded in mystery within the Buddhist tradition?

Refin.jpg

As new empirical strategies are devised for exploring phenomena, metaphysics gives way to science, mere belief is supplanted by knowledge. The approach that has repeatedly allowed for this gradual illumination of the natural world is called the scientific method. Webster’s Ninth New Collegiate Dictionary defines this as follows: “Principles and procedures for the systematic pursuit of knowledge involving the recognition and formulation of a problem, the collection of data through observation and experiment, and the formulation and testing of hypotheses.” Does Buddhism include this procedure in its inquiry into the nature of the mind and Consciousness? In general, the framework of Buddhist theory and practice consists of the Four Noble Truths: the truths of Suffering, the source of Suffering, the cessation of Suffering together with its source, and the path leading to that cessation. While Buddhist contemplatives have always placed a primary emphasis on fathoming the nature of the mind, their orientation to this endeavor has been fundamentally pragmatic. Their first task is to recognize the nature and full range of Suffering to which humans are vulnerable. The first noble truth formulates that as the problem to be addressed. The second noble truth presents the hypothesis that the essential causes of Suffering are to be found within the mind, specifically in terms of cognitive, emotional, and attentional imbalances. The third noble truth hypothesizes that these afflictive tendencies can be irreversibly dispelled from the mind. And the fourth noble truth presents detailed procedures for collecting data by observing mental processes and experimenting with techniques for transforming the mind and eliminating its afflictive elements.26

The very notion of observing the mind with the mind appears problematic to many thinkers, for it does not allow for the separation of subject and object that characterizes other kinds of scientific observations. This is a legitimate concern. Is it even possible to observe mental states and processes with the mind? Even with no mental training, we can detect our emotional states, we can observe thoughts and images arising in the mind, and we can introspectively recognize from moment to moment whether our minds are calm or agitated. On a more basic level, we can perceive that we are conscious—we are aware not only of objects of Consciousness but of the presence of our own Consciousness of other things.27 And this faculty of mental perception is the only instrument we have for directly observing any mental phenomena. While it is true in this case that there is no absolute separation between the instrument of observation and the observed phenomena, this fact does not necessarily ban the whole procedure from the realm of scientific exploration. After all, the inextricable relation between the system of measurement and the measured phenomena is a familiar theme in quantum mechanics, but no one has suggested that such measurements be banned from physics.

In Buddhist contemplative practice, the experiential investigation of the mind, including the nature, origins, and potentials of Consciousness, is of paramount significance. But in order for such exploration be penetrating and reliable and for the insights gleaned from this process to be thoroughly assimilated, the attentional imbalances of laxity and excitation must first be dispelled. Only when the attention is lucid and calm can it be used effectively in this venture.28 The qualities of luminosity and stillness are actually innate to the relative ground state of individual mind, so the central challenge of this training is to settle the attention in that ground state. One of the remarkable discoveries of Buddhist contemplatives who have penetrated to this ground is that this stratum of Consciousness is imbued with an innate quality of bliss. In other words, when the attention is settled in a deep state of equilibrium, temporarily free of laxity and excitation, one spontaneously experiences a sense of inner peace and well- being. In order to penetrate to this substrate Consciousness, a necessary prerequisite is the cultivation of a wholesome way of life that supports mental balance and harmonious relations with others. This is the essence of Buddhist ethics, which is the foundation of all Buddhist practice.29

Rcxu.jpg

According to generations of Buddhist contemplatives, simply settling the attention in the substrate Consciousness, with a high degree of attentional stability and clarity, is not enough to irreversibly free the mind of afflictions and obscurations. For this one must penetrate to the ultimate ground state of Consciousness, prior to the conceptual demarcations of subject and object, mind and matter, and even existence and nonexistence. This primordial Consciousness is metaphorically described as being empty and luminous, and its has never been sullied by afflictive imbalances of any kind. The realization of this state of Consciousness is said to yield a state of well-being, or eudaimonia, that transcends the imagination, and it is the unified culmination of the Buddhist pragmatic pursuit of freedom from Suffering and the epistemic pursuit of knowledge. With such insight, one comes to understand not only the nature of Consciousness but the relation between mental representations and their referents in the objective world.

With this understanding of three dimensions of Consciousness—ranging from the psyche that can immediately be viewed introspectively, to the substrate Consciousness, to primordial Consciousness—the Buddhist view of the mind challenges many common assumptions in the modern West. According to many psychologists today, the normal mind is deemed to be healthy, but it is nevertheless subject to a wide range of mental distress, including depression, anxiety, and frustration. But these can be managed with drug therapy and counseling when they become excessive. While unhappiness comes simply from being human, happiness comes from outside: from the sensual and esthetic enjoyments, from possessions, from other people, and, according to religious believers, from God. The modern Western view of the mind is still influenced by the Aristotelian assertion that all emotions, in the appropriate circumstance and in moderation, are to be accepted.30 This believe has been incorporated into the theory of evolution, which maintains that all our emotions and other mental traits must have served us well through human evolution, otherwise we wouldn’t have them.

In start contrast to the above views, Buddhist contemplatives state that the ordinary mind is dysfunctional, for it oscillates between states of (1) being obsessive/compulsive (succumbing to compulsive ideation and obsessively grasping onto thoughts and emotions) and (2) slipping into a stupor. We have grown habituated to experiencing such a dysfunctional mind and mistakenly take for granted the resultant mental discomfort, believing this to be normal and reasonably healthy. With this basic sense of inner dissatisfaction, we then take solace in outer and inner pleasurable stimuli, which veil the symptoms of our dysfunctional minds. While the normal mind is habitually prone to states of attentional, emotional, and cognitive imbalances, it is not intrinsically dysfunctional. By refining the attention we can make the mind serviceable and thereby rediscover the innate sense of well-being that emerges spontaneously from a balanced mind. And by fathoming the nature of Consciousness to its primordial ground, all the obscurations of the mind may be removed, resulting in irreversible freedom from Suffering and its source.

Conclusion

While the scientific study of Consciousness has come into vogue in recent years, it is overwhelmingly dominated by the metaphysical dogma of scientific materialism. The influence of belief system does little to impede progress in the physical sciences, but its stifling effect is evident in the biological sciences (including medical science) and even more so in the cognitive sciences. One of the most limiting aspects of this dogma is that it places a taboo on the empirical investigation of subjective events from a first-person perspective. And there is a widespread refusal among researchers in this field even to consider the possibility that mental events may be immaterial in nature, and not simply epiphenomena of the brain. Given the scientific ideals of empiricism and skepticism, it is ironic that the scientific community shows such resistance to the first-person, empirical investigation of subjective mental events (as opposed to their neural correlates) and that they show so little skepticism toward the metaphysical claims of scientific materialism.

Qbqmzio1.jpg

If, as I have argued in this essay, the Buddhist tradition has developed a science of Consciousness, why is this not commonly acknowledged? On the one hand, it emphasizes an introspective approach to the study of the mind, the value of which is not commonly accepted among scientists. But there are other compelling reasons as well. Over the centuries Buddhism become decreasingly empirical in its orientation to understanding human existence, and in the process elements of dogmatism and scholasticism have become increasingly prevalent.31 This degenerating trend has been exacerbated by much modern academic scholarship in the field of Buddhist studies, which tends to ignore the exceptional experiences and insights of Buddhist adepts, refusing even to consider the possibility that they may have made extraordinary discoveries that may be pertinent to our contemporary understanding of the mind and its role in nature. In the most extreme cases, Western Buddhologists even go so far as to make the absurd claim that experience has never played a prominent role in Buddhist practice.32 But the problem is not just in the representation of Buddhist practice in this West. Over the centuries the spirit of open-minded inquiry seems to have faded among both Buddhist scholars and contemplatives. This has gotten to such a point, according to one contemporary Tibetan Buddhist scholar, that the primary concern of many Buddhist meditators is mainly to ensure that they are following the correct procedure of a meditation technique, rather than rigorously exploring the nature of the mind or anything else.33

During the Renaissance, Europe emerged from the shackles of religious dogma in part because of the influx of fresh and provocative ideas from classical Greece and the Arab world. Now the West (and all other countries dominated by the West) is in need of a Renaissance to free it from the intellectual tyranny of scientific materialism, which is often falsely conflated with science itself. The Buddhist tradition, especially if it is re-instilled with the spirit of empiricism and skepticism, may play an important role in such a Renaissance.

Researchers in the mind/body problem commonly appeal to the authority of future scientists to confirm their present materialistic assumptions about the nature of Consciousness. Antonio R. Damasio, for example, claims “it is probably safe to say that by 2050 sufficient knowledge of biological phenomena will have wiped out the traditional dualistic separations of body/brain, body/mind and brain/mind.”34 It took the scientific community fifty years to recognize that themind couldn’t meaningfully be reduced to a set of behavioral dispositions. Hopefully it will not take that long before neuroscientists open their minds to the possibility that the mind may not be meaningfully reduced to neural mechanisms either.

While science characteristically embraces the “disturbingly new,” it has a much harder time embracing the “disturbingly old,” namely, discoveries that were made long ago (let alone in an alien civilization), prior to the Scientific Revolution. Many Buddhists, on the other hand, rely so heavily on the insights of the Buddha and later contemplatives of the past, that they have a hard time embracing disturbing new discoveries that challenge Buddhist beliefs. Scientific materialists are so confident that the mind is nothing more than a biological phenomenon that they confuse this belief with scientific knowledge. Similarly, many traditional Buddhists are so confident of the validity of their doctrine that they confuse their belief with contemplative knowledge. In his book The Discoverers: A History of Man’s Search to Know His World and Himself, historian Daniel J. Boorstin refers to “the illusions of knowledge” as the principle obstacles to discovery. The great discoverers of the past, he declares, “had to battle against the current ‘facts’ and dogmas of the learned.”35

The scientific tradition has now joined the Buddhist tradition in its pursuit of understanding the nature, origins, and potentials of Consciousness. At this point in history, it may be said that neither embodies a rigorous, unbiased, multifaceted science of Consciousness. But as scientists and Buddhists collaborate in the investigation of this phenomenon so central to human existence, perhaps such a science may emerge to the benefit of both traditions and the world at large.


Bibliography

Aristotle (1985) Nicomachean Ethics. Terence Irwin (trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

Boorstin, Daniel J. (1985) The Discoverers: A History of Man’s Search to Know His World and Himself. New York: Vintage Books.

Burnaby, John. (1938/1991) Amor Dei: A Study of the Religion of St. Augustine. Norwich: The Canterbury Press.

Butler, Dom Cuthbert. (1967) Western Mysticism: The Teaching of Augustine, Gregory and Bernard on Contemplation and the Contemplative Life. 3rd ed., with “Afterthoughts” by Prof. David Knowles. London: Constable & Co.

Cabezón, José Ignacio. (1994) Buddhism and Language: A Study of Indo-Tibetan Scholasticism. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

Chadwick, Owen. (trans. & ed.) (1958) The Conferences of Cassian in Western Asceticism. Philadelphia: Westminster Press.

Crick, F. and C. Koch. (1998) “Towards a Neurobiological Theory of Consciousness” in The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. N. Block, O. Flanagan, and G. Güzeldere (eds.) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 277-292.

H. H. the Dalai Lama. (1999) Ethics for the New Millennium. New York: Riverhead Books.

Damasio, Antonio R. (1998) The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt, Inc.

———(2002) “How the brain creates the mind.” in Scientific American, Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 4-9.

Dennett, Daniel C. (1991) Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co.

James, William. (1890/1950) The Principles of Psychology. New York: Dover Publications.

———(1892). “A plea for psychology as a science.” Philosophical Review, 1, pp. 146-153.
———(1890/1950) The Principles of Psychology. New York: Dover Publications. Matt, Daniel C. (1990) Ayin: “The Concept of Nothingness in Jewish Mysticism.” in Robert K. C. Forman (ed.) The Problem of Pure Consciousness: Mysticism and Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
———(1995) The Essential Kabbalah: The Heart of Jewish Mysticism. San Francisco: Harper San Francisco.

Searle, John. R. (1994) The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Sharf, Robert H. 1995. “Buddhist Modernism and the Rhetoric of Meditative Experiences.” Numen (42) pp. 228-283.

———1998. “Experience.” In Mark C. Taylor, ed. Critical Terms for Religious Studies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 94-116.

Snyder, C. R. & Shane J. Lopez (eds.) (2002) Handbook of Positive Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.

Wallace, B. Alan. (1998) The Bridge of Quiescence: Experiencing Tibetan Buddhist Meditation. Chicago: Open Court.

———(1999) "The Buddhist Tradition of Samatha: Methods for Refining and Examining Consciousness." Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, No. 2-3, 1999, pp. 175-187.
———(2000) The Taboo of Subjectivity: Toward a New Science of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

Walshe, M. O. C. (trans.) (1979 & 1987) Meister Eckhart: Sermons & Treatises,Vols. I-III, Longmead: Element Books Ltd.

Wilson, E. O. (1998) Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.]

Footnotes

1.See, for example, Daniel C. Matt (1990) (1995).

2. John Burnaby (1938: 47-49)

3. Dom Cuthbert Butler (1967: 28-29)

4. Owen Chadwick (1958)

5. Dom Cuthbert Butler (1967:26)

6. John Burnaby (1938: 52 & 67)

7. M. O’C Walshe (1979: 1: 7)

8. William James (1890/1950) I:191-2 & 197-8. 9 Exodus 22:18. New International Version 10John B. Watson (1913).

9. Exodus 22:18. New International Version

10. John B. Watson (1913).

11. Antonio R. Damasio (2002:7)

12. Anonio R. Damasio (1998)

13. Ibid. p. 9

14. Ibid. p. 6

15. E. O. Wilson (1998: 96-97)

16. Daniel Dennett (1991:21-22)

17. John R. Searle (1994: 247)

18. E. O. Wilson (1998: 60-61)

19. Ibid. p. 60

20. Cf. B. Alan Wallace (2000)

21. F. Crick, and C. Koch (1998)

22. W. James 1890/1950: I: 185

23. W. James (1890/1950) I: 416-424

24. Ibid. I: 424

25. One very promising development in modern psychology in this regard is the emergence of “positive psychology.” See C. R. Snyder & Shane J. Lopez (eds.) (2002).

26. For a more detailed presentation of these Four Noble Truths within a contemporary context, see Wallace (1998: 29-101).

27. The process by which the mind can attend to Consciousness itself is addressed in Wallace (1999).

28. For a detailed account of this type of attentional training, see Wallace (1998).

29. For a lucid presentation of Buddhist ethics presented within a modern, secular context see H.H. the Dalai Lama (1999).

30. Aristotle (1985)

31. For a discussion of scholasticism within Indo-Tibetan Buddhism see José Ignacio Cabezón (1994).

32. See Robert H. Sharf (1995) (1998).

33. Personal communication from Geshe Thupten Jinpa, June 6, 2002.

34. Antonio R. Damasio (2002:9). See also John R. Searle (1994:100).

35. Daniel J. Boorstin (1985: xv)

Source

alanwallace.org